Skip to main content

Full text of "A treatise on the Augustinian doctrine of predestination"

See other formats


FRQM  THE  LIBT^R^  OF 

TRINITY  COLLEGE 

TORgT^TO 


A  TREATISE  ON  THE 


AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTEINE 


OF 


PREDESTINATION 


By  J.  B.  MOZLEY,  D.D. 

I.ATR  CANON  OF  CHRIST  CHURCH  AND  REGIUS  PROFESSOR  OF  DIVINITY  AT  OXFOKD 


THIRD    EDITION 

WITH   ANALYSIS    OF   CONTENTS  AND   INDEX 


LONDON 

JOHN    MURRAY,    ALBEMARLE    STREET 
1883 


II 


&T 

£/  c 

ML 


LON'DOX  :     PRINTED     BY 

AXU   co.,   NKW-STREET 

PARLIAMENT     STREET 


1 1  7 1 0  0 

OCT  1  91984 


CONTENTS. 


PAGK 

SUMMARY   OF   CONTENTS [7] 

CHAPTER 

/      I.  STATEMENT  OF  THE  ARGUMENT  FOR  PREDESTINATION   .  I 

II.  EXAMINATION  OF  THE  ARGUMENT  FOR  PREDESTINATION  15 

III.  THE  PELAGIAN  CONTROVERSY        ......  40 

IV.  DIFFERENT  INTERPRETATIONS  OF  ORIGINAL  SIN      .        .  100 
AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  OF  PREDESTINATION      .        .     .  12(» 

UGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  OF  GRACE   .       .        .        .        .148 

B?  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  OF  FINAL  PERSEVERANCE     .    .  1 7l> 

AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  OF  FREEWILL     .        .        .        .  10« 

IX.  SCHOLASTIC  THEORY  OF  NECESSITY                      . .        .    .  238 

X.  SCHOLASTIC  DOCTRINE  OF  PREDESTINATION     .        .        .  259 

XI.  CONCLUSION 29H 

NOTES    .  321 


SUMMAEY   OF   CONTENTS. 

CHAPTER   I. 

STATEMENT   OF   THE   ARGUMENT   FOR    PREDESTINATION. 

PAGE 

Distinction  between  the  predestinarian  and  necessitarian  view  1 
Ground  of  the  Supralapsarian,  of  S.  Augustine,  of  the 

Jansenists  ..........  4 

Mode  in  which  the  doctrine  of  Predestination  is  extracted  from 

that  of  original  sin 5 

Distinction  drawn  in  Scripture  between  two  covenants  .  .  9 
The  predestinarian's  defence  of  his  doctrine  on  the  score  of 

justice 12 

Nakedly  stated  the  doctrine  paradoxical 14 

CHAPTER   II. 

EXAMINATION   OF   THE   ARGUMENT   FOR   PREDESTINATION. 

Two  different  kinds  of  truths  on  which  philosophy  proceeds  ;  one 

of  which,  the  conception,  is  absolute,  the  other  indistinct   .     16 
Ideas  of  substance,  cause,  infinity     ......     16 

On  the  mysteriousness  of  infinite  numbers        .         .          .         .20 

The  human  mind  can  have  relation  to  truths  without  the 

medium  of  distinct  ideas 21 

On  the  maxim  that  every  event  must  have  a  cause  .  .  .22 
Real  question  at  issue,  have  we,  or  have  we  not,  a  sense  of 

originality  in  our  actions  ? 23 

The  ideas  of  Divine  power  and  freewill  are  truths  on  which  we 

cannot  raise  definite  absolute  systems  .  .  .  .27 
All  imperfect  truths  run  into  contradictions  when  pursued  .  29 
The  counter  principles  of  humility  and  self-respect  in  human 

nature        ..........     30 

We  are  not  to  measure  the  mysterious  consequences  of  the  sin 

of  Adam  by  human  analogies       ......     33 

Language  of  Scripture  two-sided  on  this  question  .  .  .35 
Predestination  comes  before  us  in  Scripture  as  an  impression 

upon  the  mind  of  the  individual.         .         .         .         .         .37 

In  the  New  Testament  the  Christian  is  addressed  as  the  heir  to 

eternal  glory       .........     40 

a 


[8]  Summary  of  Contents. 

I'AOE 

The  doctrine  of  Predestination  profitable  or  mischievous  accord 
ing  to  the  moral  principle  of  those  who  receive  it  .  .42 

The  feeling  of  being  predestinate  not  a  literal  certainty  in 
those  who  hold  it,  only  a  strong  impression  .  .  .45 


CHAPTER  III. 

THE    PELAGIAN     CONTROVERSY. 

History  favours  the  assertion  that  Pelagianism  was  a  reaction 

from  Augustinianism  ........ 

Formula  nihil  botiimi  sine  gratia  satisfied  the  Primitive  Church  . 
When  minds  began  to  reason  the  combination  of  grace  and  free 
will  issued  in  two  opposing  assertions         .... 

The  Pelagian  position       ........ 

S.  Augustine's  objection  to  the  Pelagian  doctrine  of  grace 

In  what  sense  the  Pelagian  argument  lay  at  the  root  of  the 

errors  of  Pelagianism  .          .          .          .          .         .          .         . 

Doctrine  of  perfectibility  as  held  by  Pelagius  and  his  opponents 
Heads  of  the  great  controversy — the  power  of  the  will,   the 

nature  of  virtue  and  vice,  and  the  Divine  justice 
Pelagius'  appeal  to  instinctive  sense  of  freedom  of  the  will ; 

S.  Augustine's  counter-appeal  to  the  sense  of  sin 
The  power  of  custom  over  the  will  .          .          .          . 
Pelagius  relied  on  sense  of  bare  ability  in  spite  of  habit  . 
And  disputed  the  fact  of  hereditary  sin    ..... 
On  trial  of  the  will  as  condition  of  highest  human  virtue  . 

Trial  not  necessary  to  all  goodness 

Power  of  choosing  good  or  evil  not  perfection  of  man's  nature  . 
Christian  doctrine  of   grace   in   accordance  with  our  nature  ; 

Pelagian  reduction  of  all  virtue  to  effort  an  artificial  limit   . 
The  question  of  the  Divine  justice   ...... 

S.  Augustine's  argument  stated         ...... 

The  general  fact  of  human  sinfulness  requires  some  law  of  sin 

in  our  nature  to  explain  it  . 

Remarks  on  the  argument  which  infers  sin  from  pain 
The  Manichean  and  Pelagian  theories  on  the  existence  of  evil . 
Between  these  the  Church  has  taken  a  middle  course 
Bearing  of  the  Pelagian  arguments  on  the  Catholic  doctrines  of 

the  original  state  of  man,  the  Incarnation,  and  the  Atonement 
S.  Augustine  on  the  first  sin  of  man  ..... 

The  Pelagian  doctrine  in  denying  the  Fall  rejected  Paradise     . 
Its  bearing  on  the  Incarnation ....... 

S.  Augustine's  answer      ........ 

The  Pelagian  fundamentally  opposed  to  the  doctrine  of  the 

Atonement.         ......... 

The  philosophical  fault  in  Pelagianism 

Its  low  moral  tendency    ........ 


Summary  of  Contents.  [9] 


CHAPTER  IV. 

DIFFERENT   INTERPRETATIONS    OF    ORIGINAL    SIN. 

PAGTC 

The  language  of  the  Primitive  Church  on  this  doctrine  .  .  101 
Its  principal  writers,  Justin  Martyr,  Clement  of  Alexandria, 

and  others,  came  from  the  ranks  of  Gentile  philosophy  .  106 
Prominence  given  by  the  early  Church  to  doctrine  of  the  Logos  106 
S.  Clement  of  Alexandria  011  the  effects  of  the  Fall .  .  .  108 
Statements  of  three  first  centuries  bearing  on  this  question  .  112 
The  view  of  the  early  Church  before  S.  Augustine's  time  with 

respect  to  virtuous  heathen  and  unbaptized  infants  .  .115 
The  Western  Church  has  entered  more  deeply  than  the  Eastern 

into  the  mysteries  of  the  inner  man  .....  116 
S.  Augustine  explained  the  corruption  of  human  nature  as  the 

loss  of  freewill    .........  118 

Difference  between  Augustine  and  Clement  in  the  estimation 

of  heathen  morals        ........   110 

S.  Augustine's  modification  of  view  in  such  cases  as  Socrates 

and  Fabricius      .         .         .         .         .         .         .         .         .   121 

Pelagians  adopted  a  future  state  between  heaven  and  hell  .  122 
Remarks  of  the  author  on  the  extreme  results  of  S.  Augustine's 

doctrine  of  original  sin        .         .         .         .         .         .         .124 


CHAPTER  V. 

AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE     OF    PREDESTINATION. 

-*•"•   Statement  of  S.  Augustine's  doctrine        .....  126 

Qualified  doctrine  held  by  other  schools  .....  131 

(— r-  S.  Augustine  regarded  Predestination  as  a  perplexing  mystery, 

a  hidden  justice  .........  134 

<— -=•  His  argument  drawn  from  the  Incarnation       ....  143 

r  Difference  between  S.  Augustine's  doctrine  and  the  Scriptural 

one  ;  Scripture  asserts  contrary  truths         ....  146 
If  Revelation  as  a  whole  does  not  state  a  truth  of  Predestination 

that  stopping  short  is  a  designed  stopping  short  .         .         .  147 

CHAPTER  VI. 

AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  OF  GRACE. 

Language  of  the  Church  always  been  that  grace  assists  the  will  148 
S.  Augustine's  treatise  De  Gratia  Ckristi  ....  149 
His  answer  to  Pelagius'  book  on  freewill .....  150 
The  gift  of  perseverance  .  .  ......  .  155 


[TO]  Summary  of  Contents. 


S.  Augustine's  argument  that  sin  is  a  negation  .  .  .  161 
The  attribute  of  God  as  Creator  a  truth  almost  peculiar  to  the 

Bible.  . 161 

Difference  between  the  Bible  and  ancient  philosophy  on  the 

world  invisible    .........   162 

S.  Augustine's  argument  from  the  fact  of  prayer  .  .  .  166 
Summary  of  his  doctrine  of  Grace  ......  169 

His  definition  of  Christian  love 172 

Observations  on  S.  Augustine's  doctrine  of  Irresistible  Grace  .  176 


CHAPTER   VII. 

AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE    OF    FINAL     PERSEVERANCE. 

Doctrine  of  Final  Perseverance  not  a  predestinarian  one  but  one 
of  morals  and  religion         .......   180 

On  Solon's  rule  of  happiness  in  life 181 

On  change  of  character    ........  183 

The  doctrine  of  trial  and  probation 184 

A  case  for  charitable  supposition      .         .         ...         .         .   186 

Rule  of  final  perseverance  as  a  test  depends  on  our  discrimina 
tion  in  applying  it       ........   187 

S.  Augustine  on  this  doctrine  .......  188 

His  book  De  Dono  Perseverantise      ......  193 

Summary  of  S.  Augustine's  doctrine         .....   194 


CHAPTER  VIII. 

AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE  OF  FREEWILL. 

On  the  existence  of  the  will 195 

Locke's  position  stated     ........  197 

Locke's  conclusion  against  a  self -determining  power  in  the  will 

inconsistent  with  his  admission  of  a  class  of  indistinct  ideas  201 
Important  results  in  theology  follow  the  decision  of  this 

question /.  201 

Archbishop  Whately  quoted /.  .  202 

His  argument  adopts  necessitarianism  .  .  ./  .  .  20$ 

The  question  pursued  in  a  note  .  .  .  ,  ' .  .  .  204 

The  language  of  S.  Augustine  in  his  book  De  Liber o  Arbitrio  .  20t 

It  coincides  with  Locke's .  .  .  ./-'  ....  20£ 
On  the  determination  of  the  will  ;  S.  Augustine's  language  is 

against  the  common  doctrine  of  Freewill  .  .  .  .21] 

Statement  wherein  lies  the  peculiarity  of  S.  Augustine's  view  .  22C 


Summary  of  Contents.  [  1 1  ] 

CHAPTER  IX. 

SCHOLASTIC    THEORY   OF   NECESSITY. 

PAGE 

Remarks  on  S.  Augustine  as  a  teacher  ;  one  such  writer  is  in 

himself  a  whole  age    . 233 

The  doctrine  of  S.  Augustine  reigned  in  the  mediaeval  Church 
till  the  Reformation,  when  the  Roman  Church  fell  back 
upon  a  strong  doctrine  of  freewill        .....  234 

S.    Thomas   Aquinas,   the   great  representative  of    mediaeval 
Augustinianism  ;  the  character  of  his  intellect.     Reserved 
for  a  modern  age  to  call  forth  the  analytical  power      .         .  235 
Aquinas'  mind  shows  enormous  grasp  and  capacity  .         .         .  230 
One  great  vice  of  the  scholastic  intellect  .....  230 

The  doctrine  of  Predestination  in  his  system  rests  in  philosophy  230 
Idea  of  the  Divine  power ;  argument  of  the  schoolmen  stated  .  230 
The  existence  of  evil  explained  by  them  under  two  heads          .  245 
The  first  head  an  extreme  instance  of  verbal  explanation .         .  245 
The  argument  of  variety  ........  250 

The  obvious  answer  to  it  as  unjust  ......  252 

The  word  Form  in  scholastic  language      .....  253 

Negative    position   of   evil  as  mere  privation  no  real   expla 
nation        ..........   255 

Real  source  of  the  schoolmen's  vain  solutions  ....  256 

Divine  power  incomprehensible  to  us  .         .         .         .  257 

Fact  of  human  ignorance  recognised  by  the  schoolmen  but  not 

acted  on 257 

The  mind  of  the  schoolmen  too  busy  for  the  stationary  attitude 
of  reflection  and  self -analysis       ......  259 

CHAPTER  X. 

SCHOLASTIC    DOCTRINE    OF    PREDESTINATION. 

Archbishop  Lawrence  on  the  doctrine  of  the  schoolmen    .         .  202 
He  confuses  different  schools.    The  doctrine  of  Aquinas  .         .  202 
Doctrine  of  grace  as  more  generally  understood  at  present  day    207 
The  Augustinian  and  Thomist  doctrine     .         .         .         .         .  209 

Verbal  subtleties  of  language  incorporating  Aristotle's  doctrine 
of  habits  with  the  doctrine  of  grace     .....  271 

The  three  theological  virtues  ;  the  seven  gifts  ....  273 

Remarks  of  the  author  on  the  doctrine  of  habits       .         .         .  273 
Cause  of  confusion  in  the  technical,  quaint  division  of  habits  .  275 
Aquinas  in  fheSumma  Theologica  lays  down  the  doctrine  of  Abso 
lute  Predestination      ........  278 

Author's  remarks  on  difference  of  tone  in  applying  this  doctrine 
— in  S.  Augustine  positive  good  and  positive  evil         .         .  279 


[i  2]  Summary  of  Contents. 


Tendency  in  Aquinas  to  reduce  the  distinction  to  a  higher  and 
lower  good .....  .  .  281 

The  Clementine  view  struggles  in  his  mind  with  the  Augustinian  285 
Case  of  infants  dying  in  original  sin  ;  Augustine's  doctrine  .  287 
What  the  schoolman  could  not  contradict  he  could  explain  .  288 

Aquinas'  mild  solution  of  the  difficulty 289 

The  position  laid  down  in  the  case  of  infants  cannot  stop  short 
of  a  wider  application.          .......  290 

The  author's  remarks  on  this  question 291 


CHAPTER  XI. 

CONCLUSION. 

Need  of  a  philosophical  perception  of  human  ignorance     .         .  293 
This  only  to  be  attained  by  close  introspection         .         .         .  294 
Activity  of  human  mind  opposed  to  passive  attitude  of  thought  295 
The  human  mind  has  a  luminous  and  dark  side         .         .         .   29fi 
The  deeper  sense  of  ignorance  not  unattended  by  danger.         .  298 
To  Hume  and  Hobbes  we  may  oppose  Butler  and  Pascal .         .  30C 
Tendency   of   controversial   minds   to  force  incomprehensible 
truths  to  their  logical  results       ......  301 

With  respect  to  the  Divine  power  S.  Augustine  took  up  an  ill- 
considered  position      ........  30$ 

The  mixture  of  weakness  and  power  in  some  leading  minds 

makes  the  task  of  estimating  authorities  difficult          .          .  30£ 
S.  Augustine  and  his  school  commenced  with  an  assumption 
which  no  modern  philosopher  would  allow ....  304 

The   common   sense  of  mankind  acknowledges  contradictory 

truths 30( 

The  Pelagian  and  Augustinian  systems  both  arise  upon  partial 
and  exclusive  bases     ........  30*3 

Wherein  the  predestinarian  is  at  fault 30*3 

The  Pelagian,   on  the  other  hand,   offends  against   the   first 
principles  of  piety        ........  30£ 

The  seventeenth  article  of  our  Church  has  allowed  a  place  for 
a  predestinarian  school        .......  31] 

Proposal  in  the  last  century  for  a  change  in  its  wording  .         .  31$ 
The  object  for  which  this  present  life  is  given  us  is  not  philo 
sophy  and  reasoning  ........  31^ 

The  propensity  to  over-estimate  particular  or  supposed  truths 

shown  alike  by  the  Roman  Catholic  and  Protestant     .         .  31 1 
In  the  limited  state  of  our  capacities  those  who  differ  from  one 
another  should  remember  that  they  may  differ  not  in  hold 
ing  truth  and  error  but  different  sides  of  the  same  truth     .  311 


INDEX   OF   PEOPEE   NAMES. 


ALVAREZ 

ALVAREZ,  406 

Ambrose  (St.),  338 

Auselm  (St.),  208,  234,  338 

Aquinas  (St.  Thomas),  4,  JO, 
234,  236,  239,  244,  249,  250, 
253,  257,  260,  263,  264,  266, 
270,  272,  275,  279,  281,  282, 

285,  289,  290,  323,  339,  396, 
400 

Aristotle,  271,  336 

Athanasius  (St.),  101,  111,  377 

Athenagoras,  107 

Augustine  (St.),  1,  3,  4,  10,13, 
44,  46,  49,  52,  54,  56,  71,  73, 
74,  76,  82,  84,  86,  90,  92,  95, 
100,  105,  112,  114,  117,  118, 
120,  122,  124,  126,  131,  132, 
134,  136,  140,  143,  145,  146, 
148,  150,  153,  158,  160,  163, 
167,  170,  172,  176,  179,  187, 
188,  191,  192,  195,  206,  209, 
210,  212,  215,  219,  221,  223, 
226,  232,  234,  253,  265,  285, 

286,  288,  302,  304,  343,  360, 
364,  366,  373,  374,  376,  379, 
381,  383,  386,  388,  390,  393, 
394,  399,  406,  409 

BASIL  (St.),  101,  377 
Bellarmine,  226 
Bernard  (St.),  234,  397,  399 
Bradwardine,  10,  52,  210,  234, 

237,  268,  279,  362 
Bull,  10,  76,  105,  107,  111,  377 
Butler,  300 


IREX^EUS 
CALVIN,  3,  393,  394,  396,  399, 

401,  402,  405,  407,  408 
Catarinus,  340 
Cclestius,  56 

Chrysostom  (St.),  289,  379 
Clement    of   Alexandria,    106, 

108,  112,  119,  120,  377,  379, 

380 

Coleridge,  79,  367,  368,  371 
Cornwallis,  312 
Cyprian    (St.),   32,    116,    163, 

377 
Cyril  (St.),  107,  377,  378 

EDWARDS,   3,   23,   25,  28,  44, 
143,  213 

FABRICIUS,  121 

GOODE,  178 
Gotteschalcus,  3,  389 
Gregory  Nazianzen,  114,  380 
Gregory  Nyssa,  114,  378,  380 

HAGENBACH,  107,  378 

Hinckmar,  389,  391,  392 

Hippocrates,  336 

Hilary,  53,  136 

Hobbes,  300 

Hooker,    131,   358,    386,     388, 

389 
Hume,  18,  21,  300,  325,  335 

IREN^EUS,  101,  106,377 


t'4] 


Index  of  Proper  Names. 


JACKSON 

JACKSON,  7,  10,  322,  356,  358 
Jansen,  4,  48,  52, 160,  226,  277, 

362,  383,  409 
Julian,  51,  53,  60,  62,  70,  72, 

77,  92,  94,  98,  120,  171,  375, 

376 
Justin  Martyr,  101,   106,  109, 

113,346,377,378 


YORKE 
Paulinas,  360 
Percy,  312 
Pinelar,  83 
Polybius,  336 
Porteous,  312 
Prosper,  136,  407 

EEMIGIUS,  389,  390,  392 


KING,  202 


LAURENCE,  262,  264,  266 
Lessius,  226 

Locke,  21,  197,  198,  208,  324 
Lombard   (Peter),   3,   10,  234, 
237,  239,  246,  248,  265,  400 


MILL,  25,  326, 328,  330,  332,335 
Molina,  226 


NEANDER,  361 
Newton,  John,  31 7 


ORIGEN,  101,  109,  113,  357 
Overall,  178 


PASCAL,  20,  21,  33,  282,   300, 

401,  402,  404,  408 
Paul,  290,  340 
Pelag-ius,  49,  51,  52,  54,  55,  56, 

60,  150,  278,  360,  367 


SENECA,  290 
Simeon  Barsema,  348 
Socrates,  121 
Solon,  180 
Stilling-fleet,  324 
Suarez,  226 

TACITUS,  336 

Tatian,  101,  107,  111,  377,  378 

Taylor,   Jeremy,    33,   34,    340 

342,  344,  346,  348,  350,  380 
Toplady,  2,  5,  7,  28,  321 
Tertullian,  101,  107,  116,  117 

377,  378 

USHER,  3 

VINCENTIUS  VICTOR,  114 

WALL,  114 

Wbately,  77,  202,  204,  353 
Wollaston,  312 

YORKE,  312 


THE 

AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE 


OF 


PREDESTINATION. 


CHAPTER  I. 

STATEMENT  OF  THE    ARGUMENT  FOR  PREDESTINATION. 

THE  design  of  this  treatise  is  to  give  an  account  of  S. 
Augustine's  doctrine  of  Predestination,  together  with  such 
comments  as  may  be  necessary  for  a  due  examination  of,  and 
judgment  upon,  it.  Before  entering,  however,  on  S.  Augus 
tine's  statements,  some  general  description  of  the  doctrine 
itself,  its  grounds,  and  its  defences,  will  be  necessary :  and 
these  will  require  special  consideration,  with  a  view  to 
ascertaining  their  soundness  and  validity.  This  introduc 
tory  matter  will  occupy  the  following  chapter,  in  addition  to 
the  present  one,  in  which  I  shall  endeavour  to  give  a  general 
description  of  the  doctrine. 

A  distinction  must,  in  the  first  instance,  be  drawn  be 
tween  the  predestinarian  and  the  necessitarian  or  fatalist. 
The  predestinarian  and  the  fatalist  agree,  indeed,  in  the 
facts  of  the  case,  and  equally  represent  mankind  as  acting 
necessarily,  whether  for  good  or  evil,  in  distinction  to  act 
ing  by  an  original  motion  of  the  will.  But  the  fatalist 
goes  to  philosophy  for  the  reason  of  this  state  of  things,  the 
predestinarian  to  a  truth  of  revelation  ;  the  former  argues 
from  the  nature  of  things,  the  latter  from  a  particular  fact 
of  which  he  has  been  informed  by  competent  authority. 

B 


The  Argument 


CHAP.   T. 


The  fatalist  takes  the  general  ground  that  every  event  must 
have  a  cause  ;  and  applying  it  to  the  case  of  human  actions, 
argues  that  just  as  the  action  must  have  a  cause,  so  that 
cause,  even  if  we  say  it  is  the  will's  own  choice,  must  have 
itself  a  cause;  this  further  cause  another  cause.  Being 
thus  provided  with  an  unlimited  series  of  causes  in  the  case 
of  every  human  action,  while  the  past  existence  of  the  agent 
is  limited,  he  extends  this  series  backwards  till  it  reaches 
a  point  at  which  it  goes  outside  of  the  agent ;  who  is  con 
sequently  proved  to  have  acted  ultimately  from  causes  over 
which  he  had  no  control. 

There  is  another  kind  of  necessitarianism,  again,  which 
takes  for  its  basis,  instead  of  a  physical  assumption,  like 
the  one  just  mentioned,  a  religious  one — the  attribute  of 
the  Divine  power ;  and  argues  downwards  from  the  First 
Cause,  instead  of  backwards  from  human  action.  To  the 
metaphysician  who  believes  in  a  Creator  or  First  Cause, 
and  who  contemplates  man  in  relation  to  that  Being,  one 
great  and  primary  difficulty  presents  itself  in  the  question 
how  a  being  can  be  a  creature,  and  yet  have  freewill,  and 
be  a  spring  of  action  to  himself,  a  self-moving  being.  Our 
very  notion  of  cause  and  effect  is  of  the  cause  as  active,  the 
effect  as  passive  ;  and,  therefore,  if  man  is  an  effect,  how 
is  he  an  active  being  ?  A  tool  or  instrument  that  we  make, 
issues  inert  out  of  our  hands,  and  only  capable  of  that 
motion  which  the  maker  of  it  gives  it.  To  make  a  machine 
is  to  cause  the  whole  series  of  motions  which  it  performs. 
Our  idea  of  creation  is  thus  at  variance  with  the  idea  of 
free  agency  in  the  thing  made.  Man  as  a  self-moving 
being  and  the  originator  of  his  own  acts,  is  a  first  cause  in 
nature  ;  but  how  can  we  acknowledge  a  second  first  cause 
— a  first  cause  which  is  an  effect,  a  created  originality?1 

Of  course  the  fact  of  moral  evil  is  at  once  an  answer 
to  this  line  of  argument ;  so  far,  at  any  rate,  as  to  disprove 
the  cogency  and  decisiveness  of  it.  For  unless  we  make 

1  If  man  be  a  self-determining  as  there  are  men  in  the  world? — 

agent,  will  it  not  necessarily  follow,  Toplady,  vol.  vi.  p.  31.     If  I  am  an 

that  there  are  as  many  First  Causes  independent  animal,  I  am  also  neces* 

(i.e   in  other  words,  as  many  Gods)  sarily  self-existent. — p.  4o. 


CFAP.  i. 


For  Predestination. 


God  the  author  of  evil,  moral  evil  must  be  referred  to  some 
original  source  other  than  God  ;  in  which  case  the  attribute 
of  the  Divine  omnipotence  is  seen  to  meet  in  the  first  in 
stance  with  something  counter  to  it  ;  and  so  cannot  be 
argued  upon  as  if  it  were  the  whole  of  the  truth  in  the 
question  under  consideration.  But  so  far  as  we  attend  to 
this  attribute  exclusively,  as  is  the  fault  with  some  schools, 
this  is  the  natural  argument  from  it. 

The  necessitarian  thus  believes  freewill  not  only  to  be 
false,  but  to  be  impossible.  On  the  other  hand,  the  pre- 
destinarian  cannot  believe  it  to  be  impossible,  because  he 
admits,  on  the  authority  of  Scripture,  that  the  first  man 
Adam,  in  the  state  in  which  he  was  created,  had  it.1  He 
only  believes  that  man  has  since  the  fall  been  deprived  of 
it,  and  regards  it  as  an  historical  fact,  not  an  existing  one. 
He  is  thus  excluded,  on  this  question,  from  the  ground  of 
philosophy,  from  the  perfect  and  consistent  theory  of  the 
fatalist,  and  draws  his  conclusion  from  the  revealed  doctrine 
of  the  fall. 

But  though  predestinarians,  as  such,  draw  their  con 
clusion  from  the  particular  sin  of  Adam,  such  a  ground  is 
so  unsatisfactory  to  a  philosophical  mind,  that  few  have,  in 
fact,  confined  themselves  to  it.  Some  have  dispensed  with 
it  altogether,  and  adopted  the  philosophy  either  of  causes,2 
or  of  the  Divine  power  :  the  latter  being  the  ground  of  the 
supralapsarian,  who  asks  how  such  a  universal  effect  could 
follow  from  a  particular  sin,  except  by  the  will  of  (iod 

1  Augustine  endows  Adam  with  15.     Though  the  latter  afterwards 

freewill:  '  Potuit  non  peccare  primus  calls  the  notion  of  Adam's  fivcwill 

homo,  potuitnon  mori.potuit  bonum  'frigidum    commentum,'    and    ;isks 

nondeserere.  Nunquiddicturi  sumus  why  he  should  not  have  been  the 

non  potuit  peccare  qui  tale  habebat  subject  of  a  decree,  as  his  posterity 

liberum    arbitrium.'  —  De   Corr.    et  were:  'Atqui   predestinatio   vdint, 

Grat.   c.    12.     'Homo   male   utens  nolint,  in  posteris  se  profert.  Nequo 

libero   arbitrio    et    se    perdidit   et  enim   factum   est   naturaliter   Mt  a 

ipsum.'    Ench.  c.  30.    Lombard  (L.  salute  exciderent  omnes  uniu.s  '^ar- 

2.   Distinct    24.    1.),    Gotteschalus  entis  culpa.  Quid  eos  prohibet  fateri 

(Usher,  p.  29.),  and  Calvin,  follow  de  uno  homine  quod  inviti  dr  toto 

Augustine:  'In  hisprseclarisdotibus  humano  genere  concedunt.'  —  Jnstit. 

excelluit  prima    hominis    conditio.  1.  3.  c.  23. 

...  In  hac  integritate  libero  arbi-  2  Edwards,  On  the  Freedom  of 

trio  pollebat  homo.'—  Instit.  1.  1.  c.  the  Will. 

B  2 


The  Argument  CHAP.  i. 


ordaining  it  so,  and  so  pushes  back  the  ground  of  fact 
immediately  to  one  of  philosophical  principle.1 
have  not  without  detriment  to  their  consistency  as  reasoners, 
mixed  the  two  grounds.  The  ground  which  S.  Augustine 
adopted  and  which  the  Jansenists  revived,  was  in  the  mam 
that  of  Scripture,  though  the  former  joined  to  it  occa 
sionally  that  of  philosophy1 :  the  medieval  predestinanans 
took  in  the  main  the  ground  of  philosophy,  mixing  with  it 
occasionally  that  of  Scripture.  The  theory  of  necessity 
last  described,  was  adopted  under  the  name  of  'the  physical 
predetermination  of  the  will '  by  this  medieval  school,2 
who  maintained  that  there  could  be  but  one  true  cause  of 
every  event,  all  other  causes  being  secondary  and  inter 
mediate  ;  and  applying  it  to  the  case  of  human  actions, 
explained  that  though  they  had  a  4  voluntary  cause,'  or  a 
cause  in  the  human  will,  this  was  only  secondary  and  inter 
mediate  between  the  agent  and  the  first  cause  ;  protecting 
this  position  from  the  consequence  which  it  apparently  in 
volved  in  the  case  of  evil  actions,  that  God  was  the  author 
of  evil,  by  distinctions  which  it  is  not  necessary  here  to 
state ;  yet  the  same  writers  referred  to  the  fact  of  the  fall 
as  the  ground  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination.3  Pre- 
destinarian  preachers,  again,  guided  half  by  sentiment  and 
half  by  theory,  are  accustomed,  though  using  the  scriptural 
ground  as  their  basis  on  this  question,  to  speak  of  the 
doctrine  of  freewill  as  an  insult  to  the  Divine  Power,  which 

1  NOTE  I.  doctrine  of  efficacious  grace,  which 
At  qui  omnium  connexionem  re-       rests  upon  original  sin.     'Predeter- 

rumquo  causarum  qua  fit  omne  quod  minatio  physica  necessaria  statuitur 
fit,  fati  nomine  appellant ;  non  mul-  omnibus  agentibus  ex  vi  causse 
turn  cum  iis  de  verbi  controversia  secundse  quse  essentialiter  tarn  in 
certandum  atque  laborandum  est,  operari  quam  in  esse  suo  subordina- 
quandoquidem  ipsam  causarum  ordi-  tur  primse,  a  qua  ad  agendum  prse- 
nem  et  quandam  connexionem,  summi  moveri  debet ;  Christi  adjutorium 
Dei  tribuunt  voluntati. — De  Civit.  nequaquam  sed  Isesse  voluntati  prop- 
Dei,  1.  5.  c.  8.  ter  sohim  vulnus  necessarium  est.' — 

2  Jansen  draws  the  distinction  De  Grat.  Christi  Salvatoris,  1.  8.  c. 
between  the  theory  of  the  'predeter-  1,  2. 

minatio  physica '   of  the    will    '  ex  s  Ratio  reprobationis    est  origi- 

philosophia    profecta,'    and    which  nale  peccatum.     Aquinas,  vol.  viii. 

'  defenditur    a    sectatoribus    sancti  p.  330. 
Thomse,'     and    the    predestinarian 


CHAP.  i.  For  Predestination.  5 

is  to  mix  the  two  grounds  ;  for  while  the  scriptural  ground 
is  one  of  fact,  the  argument  of  the  Divine  power  is  an  ab 
stract  argument. 

Assuming,  however,  the  doctrine  of  the  fall  or  original 
sin  as  the  proper  ground  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination, 
how,  it  will  be  asked,  is  the  one  doctrine  the  reason  and 
basis  of  the  other  ?  In  the  following  way. 

The  doctrine  of  original  sin  represents  the  whole  human 
race  as  in  a  state  of  moral  ruin  in  consequence  of  the  trans 
gression  of  the  first  man,  incapable  of  doing  anything 
pleasing  and  acceptable  to  Grod,  or  performing  any  really 
good  act1 ;  that  is  to  say,  it  represents  the  human  race  as 
without  freewill.  And  such  being  the  condition  of  man, 
the  Divine  mercy  determines  on  his  rescue  out  of  it,  on 
raising  him  from  a  state  of  ruin  to  a  state  of  salvation. 
But  how  can  the  rescue  of  a  ruined  and  powerless  being 
be  effected  except  by  an  absolute  ace  of  power  on  the  part 
of  the  Deliverer  ?  The  subject  of  this  rescue  is  supposed 
to  be  unable  to  do  anything  for  himself ;  and  therefore,  if 
he  is  saved  at  all,  he  must  be  saved  without  any  waiting  for 
or  depending  upon  his  own  individual  agency.2  It  may 
perhaps  be  replied  that,  as  God  endowed  man  with  freewill, 
or  the  power  to  act  aright,  as  distinguished  from  a  necessary 
virtue,  at  the  creation ;  so  when  he  raises  him  out  of  this 
state  of  ruin  and  slavery  of  the  will,  he  may  endow  him 
again  with  freewill  only,  leaving  the  use  which  he  may 
make  of  it  to  himself,  as  before.  It  may  be  said  that  this 
would  be  a  true  act  of  grace  or  favour  on  the  part  of  Grod, 
and  therefore  that  we  need  not  suppose  that  in  the  act  of 
delivering  man  out  of  the  wretched  and  impotent  state  in 
which  he  is  by  nature,  (rod  does  anything  more  than  this. 

1  We  have  no  power  to  do  good  anything  towards  our  own  recovery 
works   pleasant   and  acceptable   to  Hence  it  was  God's  own  arm  which 

God,  without  the  grace  of  God  by  brought  salvation Conver- 

Christ    preventing     us.  —  Art.     x.  sion  is  a  new  birth,  and  resurrection 
Works   done   before   the    grace    of  a  new  creation.     What  infant  ever 
Christ  are  not  pleasant  to  God,  .  .  .  begat  itself  ?    What  inanimate  ear- 
rather  we  doubt  not  but  they  have  case  ever  qu'ckened  and  raised  itself  ? 
the  nature  of  sin. — Art.  xiii.  What  creature  ever  created  itself? 

2  So  totally    are   we   fallen  by  — Toplady,  vol.  iii.  p.  363. 
nature,  that  we  cannot  contribute 


The  Argument 


CHAP.   I. 


But  though  such  a  mode  of  acting  on  (rod's  part  does  not 
involve  any  positive  contradiction,  it  must  be  allowed  to  be 
at  variance  with  our  reasonable  notions  of  the  Divine  deal- 
ino-s;  for  what  is  this  but  to  institute  the  first  dispensation 
over 'again,  and  repeat  a  trial  which  has  been  undergone 
once,  and  had  its  issue  ?  Suppose  a  man  carried  away  by 
a  torrent,  to  master  which  he  had  proved  himself  unequal, 
would  it  be  a  reasonable  or  consistent  act  to  take  him  out 
only  to  recruit  his  strength  for  a  second  resistance  to  it  ? 
So,  after  man  in  the  exercise  of  freewill  has  fallen  and  lost 
freewill,  is  it  not  a  mockery  to  save  him  by  giving  him  free 
will  again?  What  will  he  do  with  the  gift,  but  tall  again  ? 
On  such  a  mode  of  Divine  dealing,  the  fall  may  be  re 
peated  indefinitely,  and  the  Divine  purposes  for  the  salvation 
of  man  may  remain  in  perpetual  suspense,  and  never  attain 
completion. 

The  principle,  then,  being  acknowledged  that  God  does 
not  repeat  His  dispensations,  it  follows  that  a  second  dis 
pensation  cannot  be  the  first  one  a  second  time  instituted, 
but  must  be  a  different  one  in  itself;  divided  substantially 
from  the  old  one  in  the  nature,  character,  and  effect  of  the 
aid  which  it  supplies  to  man  for  attaining  salvation.  A 
dispensation  which  left  the  salvation  of  man  dependent  on 
his  will,  was  highly  suitable  as  a  first  one  ;  suitable  alike 
to  the  justice  of  the  Creator  and  the  powers  of  the  untried 
creature,  and  such  as  we  should  naturally  expect  at  the 
beginning  of  things :  but  such  having  been  the  nature  of 
the  first,  the  second  must,  for  that  very  reason,  be  a  dis 
pensation  of  a  different  kind,  effecting  its  design  not  by  a 
conditional,  but  by  an  absolute  saving  act. 

And  independently  of  all  reasoning,  the  fact  is  plain 
from  Scripture  that  the  new  dispensation  differs  substan 
tially  from  the  old  in  the  nature  of  the  aid  which  it 
supplies  to  man  for  attaining  salvation.  God  is  not  repre 
sented  in  Scripture  as  repeating  his  dispensations,  but  as 
altering  them  according  to  the  wants  of  man.  The  Gospel 
aid  to  salvation,  then,  is,  in  accordance  with  the  fundamen 
tal  difference  in  man's  own  state,  fundamentally  different 
from  that  which  man  had  before  the  fall ;  and  if  funda- 


CHAP.  T.  For  Predestination.  7 

mentally  different,  different  in  the  way  which  has  been  just 
mentioned.  For  whatever  peculiarities  of  the  second  dis 
pensation  may  be  appealed  to,  if  the  grace  of  it  depends 
on  the  human  will  for  its  use  and  improvement,  it  is  funda 
mentally  a  dispensation  of  freewill  like  the  first  one. 

The  Divine  act,  then,  in  the  salvation  of  man  being,  as 
the  result  of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  an  absolute  one, 
effecting  its  purpose  with  infallible  certainty,  the  rest  of 
the  doctrine  of  predestination  follows  upon  ordinary  Chris 
tian  grounds.  It  is  confessed  by  all  that,  whatever  God 
does,  He  determines  or  decrees  to  do  from  all  eternity ;  for 
no  one  who  believes  properly  in  a  Grod  at  all,  can  suppose 
that  He  does  anything  on  a  sudden,  and  which  He  has  npt 
thought  of  before.  There  is,  therefore,  a  Divine  decree 
from  all  eternity  to  confer  this  certain  salvation  upon  those 
on  whom  it  is  conferred.  And,  again,  it  is  universally  ad 
mitted  that  only  a  portion  of  mankind  are  saved.  But  these 
two  admissions  complete  the  doctrine  of  predestination 
which  is,  that  Grod  has  decreed  from  all  eternity  to  save  by 
His  absolute  and  sovereign  power  a  select  portion  of  man 
kind,  leaving  the  rest  in  their  previous  state  of  ruin. 

The  doctrine  of  predestination  being  thus  reduced,  as 
its  essence  or  distinctive  part,  to  an  absolute  saving  act  on 
the  part  of  Grod  of  which  man  is  the  subject,  we  have  next 
to  consider  the  particular  nature  and  character  of  this  act. 
The  doctrine  of  predestination,  then,  while  it  represents 
Grod  as  deciding  arbitrarily  whom  He  saves,  and  whom  He 
leaves  for  punishment,  does  not  by  any  means  alter  the  con 
ditions  on  which  these  respective  ends  are  awarded.  His 
government  still  continues  moral — pledged  to  the  reward 
of  virtue  and  punishment  of  vice.  It  follows  that  in  ordain 
ing  those  whom  He  does  ordain  to  eternal  life,  Grod  decrees 
also  that  they  should  possess  the  qualifications  necessary  for 
that  state — those  of  virtue  and  piety.1  And  if  Grod  decrees 
that  particular  persons  shall  be  virtuous  and  pious  men, 

1  They  who  are  predestinated  to  that  life,  such  as  repentance,  faith, 

life  are  likewise  predestinated  to  all  sanctification.and  perseverance  unto 

those  means  which  are  indispensably  the  end. — Toplady,  vol.  v.  p.  251. 

necessary  in  order  to  their  meetness,  Jackson  mistakes  the  predestinarian 

entrance  upon,   and   enjoyment  of  position  on  this  head. — NOTE  II. 


The  Argument  CHAP.  i. 


He  necessarily  resolves  to  bestow  some  grace  upon  them 
which  will  control  their  wills  and  insure  this  result.  There 
are  two  main  kinds  of  grace  laid  down  in  the  schemes  of 
divines,  one,  assisting  grace,  which  depends  on  an  original 
act  of  the  human  will  for  its  use  and  cultivation,  and  which 
was  therefore  conferred  on  man  at  his  creation  when  the 
power  of  his  will  had  not  been  as  yet  tried  ;  the  other,  effec 
tive  or  irresistible  grace,  given  when  that  will  has  been  tried 
and  failed,  and  must  have  its  want  of  internal  strength 
supplied  by  control  from  without.  The  Divine  saving  act 
is  the  bestowal  of  this  irresistible  grace.  The  subject  of 
the  Divine  predestination  is  rescued  by  an  act  of  absolute 
power  from  the  dominion  of  sin,  dragged  from  it,  as  it 
were,  by  force,  converted,  filled  with  the  love  of  God  and 
his  neighbour,  and  qualified  infallibly  for  a  state  of  ulti 
mate  reward. 

Here,  then,  it  must  be  observed,  is  the  real  essence  and 
substance  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination.  Predestinarians  • 
do  not  differ  from  their  opponents  in  the  idea  of  eternal 
Divine  decrees,  which,  though  popularly  connected  with  this 
system  more  than  with  others,  belongs  in  truth  to  all  theo 
logical  systems  alike.  For  the  believer  in  freewill,  who 
only  admits  an  assisting  grace  of  God,  and  not  a  controlling 
one,  must  still  believe  that  God  determined  to  give  that 
assisting  grace,  in  whatsoever  instances  He  does  give  it, 
from  all  eternity.  Nor  do  they  differ  from  their  opponents 
in  the  ground  or  reason  of  God's  final  judgment  and  dis 
pensing  of  reward  and  punishment1 ;  for  this  takes  place  in 
both  schemes  wholly  upon  the  moral  ground  of  the  indi 
vidual's  good  or  bad  character.  But  the  difference  between 
the  predestinarians  and  their  opponents  is  as  to  that  act 
which  is  the  subject  matter  of  the  Divine  decree,  and  as  to 
the  mode  in  which  this  difference  of  moral  character  is  pro 
duced  ;  that  is  to  say,  the  two  schools  differ  as  to  the  nature, 
quality,  and  power  of  Divine  grace  under  the  Gospel ;  one 

1  Vita  geterna  .  .  .  gratia  mincu-  dirnn  est,    sed  tibi  gratia   est,    cui 

patur  non  ob  aliud  nisi  quod  gratis  gratia  est  et  ipsa  justitia. — Aug.  Ep. 

datur,   nee  ideo   quia   non   meritis  194.  n.  19.  21. 
tlatur  .  .  .  Justitise  quidem  stipen- 


CHAP.  i.  For  Predestination.  9 

school  maintaining  that  that  grace  is  only  assisting  grace, 
depending  on  the  human  will  for  its  use  and  improvement ; 
the  other,  that  it  is  irresistible  grace.  To  the  former  school 
belong  those  who  hold  one  interpretation  of  the  doctrine 
of  baptismal  regeneration  ;  who  maintain  the  sacrament  of 
baptism  to  be  the  medium  by  which  the  power  of  living  a 
holy  life  is  imparted  to  the  previously  corrupt  and  impo 
tent  soul ;  which  power,  however,  may  be  used  or  neglected 
according  to  the  individual's  own  choice. 

The  mode  in  which  the  doctrine  of  predestination  is 
extracted  from  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  being  thus 
shown,  it  may  be  added  that,  by  thus  reducing  as  we  have 
done  the  former  doctrine  to  its  pith  and  substance,  we  evi 
dently  much  widen  the  Scripture  argument  for  it,  extending 
it  at  once  from  those  few  and  scattered  passages  where  the 
word  itself  occurs,  to  a  whole  field  of  language.  The  whole 
Scripture  doctrine  of  grace  is  now  appealed  to  as  being  in 
substance  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  because  there  is 
only  the  Divine  foreknowledge  to  be  added  to  it,  in  order 
to  make  it  such.  Scripture  distinguishes  in  the  most  marked 
way  between  two  covenants.  The  first  was  that  under  which 
mankind  was  created,  and  which  ended  at  the  fall.  Its  lan 
guage  was — This  do,  and  thou  shalt  live.  It  endowed  man 
with  freewill,  or  the  power  to  obey  the  Divine  law,  and  in 
return  claimed  the  due  use  of  this  power  from  him,  the 
proper  exertion  of  that  freewill.  The  burden  of  obedience, 
the  attainment  of  salvation,  was  thrown  upon  the  man  him 
self.  And  of  this  covenant  the  Mosaic  law  was  a  kind  of 
re-enactment ;  not  that  the  law  was  really  a  continuation  of 
it,  but  it  was  so  by  a  supposition,  or  as  it  may  be  called  an 
instructive  fiction,  maintained  for  the  purpose  of  exhibit 
ing  and  proving  the  consequences  of  the  fall.  Man  was 
addressed  under  the  Mosaic  law,  as  if  he  had  the  full  power 
to  love  and  obey  Grod,  and  the  issue  of  the  attempt  showed 
his  inability ;  he  was  addressed  as  if  he  was  strong,  and  the 
event  proved  his  weakness.  This  was  the  covenant  of  works. 
The  covenant  of  grace  was  opposed  to  it.  But  how  could 
it  be  opposed  to  it,  if  under  that  covenant  the  salvation  of 
man  still  continued,  as  before,  dependent  on  his  freewill  ? 


' 


\ 

\ 

IO  The  Argument  CHAP.  i. 

If  it  be  said  that  there  was  the  addition  of  grace  under  the 
second  covenant,  given  besides  and  for  the  support  of  free 
will,  and  that  this  addition  makes  the  distinction  between 
the  two  covenants,  the  reply  is  obvious,  that  whatever  addi 
tion  of  grace  there  may  be  under  the  second,  no  substantial 
difference  is  made  out  so  long  as  the  use  of  this  grace  re 
mains  dependent  on  the  will.  The  burden  of  obedience  is 
still  thrown  on  the  man  himself  in  the  first  instance,  and 
his  salvation  depends  on  an  original  act  of  choice,  as  it  did 
under  the  first.  Moreover,  it  has  been  always  held  that  man 
had  grace  in  addition  to  freewill,  even  under  the  first 
covenant.1  Then,  in  what  are  the  two  opposed,  except  in 
the  nature,  quality,  and  power  of  that  grace  which  they 
respectively  confer,  that  in  the  one  grace  was,  and  in  the 
other  is  not,  dependent  on  any  original  motion  of  the  will 
for  its  effect  ?  The  grace  of  the  gospel  issues  in  being  an 
effective  and  irresistible  grace,  converting  the  will  itself, 
and  forming  the  holy  character  in  the  man  by  a  process  of 
absolute  creation  ;  according  to  such  texts  as  the  following  : 
'We  are  His  workmanship,  created  in  Jesus  Christ  unto 
good  works,  which  God  hath  before  ordained  that  we  should 
walk  in  them2 ; '  '  It  is  God  that  worketh  in  us  both  to  will 
and  to  do  of  His  good  pleasure3 ; '  '  According  as  God  hath 

1  Bull   '  On  the   State   of  Man  Homini  in    creatione,    sicut   de 

before  the  Fall,'  gives  this  as  the  angelis  diximus,  datum  est  per  gra 

doctrine  of  all  the  early  Fathers.  tiam   auxilium     ....     Non    talis 

Nam  et  tune  (cum  natura  erat  natura    facta    est  ut   sine    Divino 

Integra   et   sana)   esset  adjutorium  auxiiio  posset  manere  si  vellet.' — 

Dei  et  tanquam  lumen  sanis  oculis  Lombard,  L.  2.  Dis.  24. 
quo  adjuti  videant,  se  prseberet  vol-  Jackson    objects    to    a    super- 

entibus. — Aug.  De  Natura  et  Gratia,  natural    original   righteousness,    on 

c-  48.  the  ground  that  nature  would  not  be 

Quod  fuerit  conditus  in  gratia  corrupt  by  the  loss  of  it.     '  If  the 

videturrequirereipsarectitudoprimi  righteousness  of  the  firat  man  did 

status  in  qua  Deus  homines  fecit. —  consist  in   a  grace  supernatural,  or 

Aquinas  Summ.  Theol.  Prima  Q.  95.  in    any   quality   additional    to   his 

Art.  1.     See  NOTE  III.  constitution,  as  he  was  the  work  of 

Hoc  autem  (the  need  of  grace),  God,    this   grace   or  quality  might 

nedum  est  yerum   propter  depres-  have  been,  or  rather  was,  lost,  with- 

sionem  liberi  arbitrii  per  peccatum,  out  any  real  wound  unto  our  nature.' 

A-erum   etiam   propter   gravedinem  — Works,  vol.  ix.  p.  6. 
liberi    arbitrii    naturalem   qua   ad  2  Eph.  ii.  10. 

principaliterdiligendumsealligatur.  3  Phil.  ii.  13. 

— Bradwardiue,  p.  371. 


CHAP.  T.  For  Predestination.  1 1 

dealt  to  every  man  the  measure  of  faith1 ; '  '  Who  maketh 
thee  to  differ  from  another  ?  and  what  hast  thou  which  thou 
hast  not  received2? '  '  No  man  can  come  to  Me,  except  the 
Father  which  hath  sent  me,  draw  him3 ; '  4  Who  hath  saved 
us,  and  called  us  with  an  holy  calling,  not  according  to  our 
works  but  according  to  His  own  purpose  and  grace,  which 
was  given  to  us  in  Jesus  Christ  before  the  world  began4 ;' 
'  By  grace,  ye  are  saved  through  faith ;  and  that  not  of 
yourselves,  it  is  the  gift  of  God5 ; '  '  By  the  grace  of  God  I 
am  what  I  am6 ; '  *  Of  Him  are  ye  in  Jesus  Christ,  who  of 
God  is  made  unto  us  wisdom,  and  righteousness,  and  sanc- 
tification,  and  redemption  7 ;'  'If  any  man  be  in  Christ,  he 
is  a  new  creature8 ; '  '  And  I  will  give  them  one  heart,  and 
I  will  put  a  new  spirit  within  you ;  and  I  will  take  away 
the  stony  heart  out  of  their  flesh,  and  will  give  them  a  heart 
of  flesh.' 9  The  ground  of  Scripture  for  the  doctrine  of 
predestination  thus  becomes  a  large  and  general  one,  con 
sisting  of  a  certain  pervading  language,  instead  of  being 
confined  to  a  few  texts  in  which  the  word  itself  is  men 
tioned,  and  which  are  popularly  regarded  as  its  ground;  and 
the  doctrine  appears  to  be  no  more  than  the  gospel  doctrine 
of  grace,  with  the  addition  of  the  Divine  foreknowledge. 

From  the  basis  and  structure  of  the  doctrine  of  predes 
tination,  I  now  come  to  its  defences.  An  arbitrary  decree 
ordaining  from  all  eternity,  and  antecedently  to  any  diffe 
rence  of  desert,  some  of  the  human  race  to  eternal  life,  and 
others  to  eternal  punishment,  is  in  direct  opposition  to  our 
natural  idea  of  justice,  and  plainly  requires  a  defence.  And 
the  defence  given  for  it  rests  on  the  same  article  of  belief 
out  of  which  the  structure  of  the  doctrine  arose — the  article, 
viz.,  of  original  sin. 

It  is  true,  then,  predestinarians  say,  that  we  do  maintain 
an  arbitrary  decree,  ordaining,  antecedently  to  any  difference 
of  desert,  the  eternal  salvation  of  some  and  punishment  of 
others  of  the  human  race  :  but  remember  in  what  state  this 
decree  finds  the  human  race.  It  finds  the  whole  of  the 

1  Rom.  xii.  3.  «  2  Tim.  i.  9.  7  1  Cor.  i.  30. 

2  1  Cor.  iv.  7.  s  Eph.  ii.  8,  9.  8  2  Cor.  v.  17. 
8  John  vi.  44.                     6  1  Cor.  xv.  10.  9  Ezek.  xi.  19. 


12  The  Argument  CHAP.  *• 

human  race  deserving  of  eternal  punishment.  This  decree, 
then,  does  indeed  confer  gratuitous  and  undeserved  happi 
ness  upon  one  portion  of  mankind  ;  and  to  that  nobody  will 
have  any  objection  ;  for  it  would  indeed  be  a  rigorous  justice 
which  objected  to  an  excess  of  Divine  love  and  bounty:  but 
it  does  not  do  that  which  alone  could  be  made  matter  of 
accusation  against  it,  inflict  gratuitous  and  undeserved 
misery  upon  the  other.  It  simply  allows  the  evil  which  it 
already  finds  in  them  to  go  on  and  produce  its  natural  fruits. 
Had  this  decree,  indeed,  to  do  with  mankind  simply  as 
mankind,  it  could  not  without  injustice  devote  any  portion 
of  them  arbitrarily  to  eternal  punishment :  for  man  has  not, 
as  man,  any  guilt  at  all,  and  some  guilt  is  required  to  make 
his  punishment  just.  But  this  decree  has  not  to  do  with 
human  nature  simply,  but  with  human  nature  under  certain 
circumstances.  Mankind  are  brought  into  a  particular 
position  before  it  deals  with  them.  That  position  is  the 
position  of  guilt  in  which  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  places 
them.  Viewed  through  the  medium  of  that  doctrine,  the 
whole  human  race  lies  before  us,  prior  to  the  action  of  this 
decree  upon  them,  one  mass  of  perdition.  This  decree  only 
allows  a  portion  to  remain  such.  Viewed  through  that 
medium,  all  are  under  one  sentence  of  condemnation :  this 
decree  only  executes  this  sentence  upon  some.  But  if  it 
would  be  just  to  punish  the  whole,  it  cannot  be  unjust  to 
punish  a  part.  If  two  men  owe  us  debts,  we  may  certainly 
sue  one.  If  all  antecedently  deserve  eternal  punishment,  it 
cannot  be  unjust  that  some  should  be  antecedently  con 
signed  to  it.  Or  would  we  fall  into  the  singular  contradic 
tion  of  saying  that  a  sentence  is  just,  and  yet  all  execution 
of  it  whatever  unjust  ? 

The  question  of  justice,  then,  is  already  settled,  when 
man  first  comes  under  this  decree  ;  and  the  question  which 
is  settled  by  it  is  not  one  of  justice  at  all,  but  one  of  Divine 
arrangement  simply.  The  same  human  mass  which,  if 
innocent,  would  have  been  the  subject  of  God's  justice, 
becomes,  when  guilty,  the  subject  of  his  will  solely.  His 
absolute  sovereignty  now  comes  in,  and  He  hath  mercy  upon 
whom  He  will  have  mercy,  and  whom  He  will  He  hardeneth. 


CHAP.  i.  For  Predestination.  1 3 

'  Hath  not  the  potter  power  over  the  same  lump  to  make 
one  vessel  to  honour,  and  another  to  dishonour  ? '  Are  we 
to  complain  of  God's  justice  in  some  cases,  because  He  shows 
mercy  in  others  ?  To  do  so  would  be  for  the  creature  to 
dictate  to  the  Creator.  Man,  guilty,  has  lost  his  rights,  and 
falls  under  the  jurisdiction  of  (rod's  absolute  and  sovereign 
will,  with  which  remonstrance  is  ridiculous.1 

Such  is  the  defence  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination  on 
the  score  of  justice.  Absolutely,  or  apart  from  any  previous 
supposition,  it  is  admitted  to  be  unjust ;  but  the  defence  is 
that  it  must  not  be  considered  absolutely,  but  in  its  real 
and  intrinsic  relation  to  another  doctrine,  which  in  theo 
logical  order  precedes  it.  If  you  think  the  doctrine  unjust, 
it  is  said,  it  is  only  because  you  do  not  realise  what  the 
doctrine  of  original  sin  is,  and  what  it  commits  you  to. 
You  go  on  really,  and  in  your  heart  thinking  the  human 
mass  innocent  before  actual  sin,  and  therefore  you  are 
scandalised  at  the  antecedent  consignment  of  any  part  of 
it  to  punishment.  But  suppose  it  really  guilty,  as  your 
creed  represents  it,  and  you  will  not  be  scandalised  at  it. 
Fix  upon  your  mind  the  existence  of  real  ill-desert  ante 
cedent  to  actual  sin,  and  condemnation  will  appear  just 
and  natural.  The  first  step  mastered,  the  second  has  no 
difficulty  in  it. 

The  doctrine  of  predestination  itself,  and  its  defence  on 
the  score  of  justice,  thus  rest  upon  the  one  doctrine  of 
original  sin.  There  is  another  objection,  however,  made 
to  it,  which  is  met  in  another  way ;  for  this  doctrine,  it  is 
objected,  contradicts  our  experience  and  consciousness, 

1  Hie  si  dixerimus  quanto  melius  possumus  dicere,  quoniam  bona  sunt 

ambo  liberarentur ;  nihil  nobis  con-  cuncta  ista  quse  fee-it,  quanto  melius 

venientius  dicetur  quam,  0  homo,  tu  ilia  duplicasset,  et  multiplicasset,  ut 

quis  es  qui  respondeas  Deo?     Novit  multo   essent  plura  quam  sunt;  si 

quippe  ille  quid  agat,  et  quantus  enim  ea  non  cap^ret  mundus  nun- 

numerus  esse  debeat  primitus  om-  quid  non  posset  etiam  ipsum  facere 

nium  hominum,  deinde  sanctorum,  quantum    vellet    ampliorem  ?      Et 

sicut    siderum,    sicut     angelorum,  tamen  quantumcunque   faceret   rel 

atque,  ut  de  terrenis  loquamur,  sicut  ilia  plura,  vel  istum  capaciorem  et 

pecorum,  piscinm,  volatilium,  sicut  majorem,    nihilominus    eadem    de 

arborum  et  herbarum,  sicut  denique  multiplicandis  illis  dici  possent,  et 

foliorum  et  capillorum  nostrorum.  nullus  esset  immoderatus  modus. — 

Nam  DOS  humana  cogitatione  adhuc  Aug.  Ep.  186.  n.  22. 


The  Argument 


CHAP.   I. 


describing  us  as  acting  from  an  irresistible  influence  either 
for  ffood  or  evil ;  whereas  we  are  conscious  of  will  and 
choice  and  feel  that  we  are  not  forced  to  act  in  one  way 
or  another.  But  it  is  replied  that  this  objection  proceeds 
from  a  misapprehension  as  to  the  nature  of  this  irresistible 
influence.  The  terms  irresistible,  necessary,  and  other  like 
terms,  imply,  indeed,  in  their  common  use  an  inclination 
of  the  will  which  is  opposed,  and  express  a  certain  over 
whelming"  power  exerted  upon  the  man,  in  consequence  of 
which  he  is  obliged  to  act  against  this  inclination.  But 
in  the  present  instance  these  terms  are,  in  defect  of  proper 
language  for  the  purpose,  used  incorrectly,  and  express  a 
power  which  inclines  the  will  itself,  in  the  first  place,  and 
does  not  suppose  an  inclination  already  formed  which  it 
contradicts.  Between  our  experience  and  consciousness, 
then,  and  the  exertion  of  such  a  power  as  this  upon  our 
wills,  there  is  no  opposition.  Our  consciousness  is  only 
concerned  with  the  inclination  of  the  will  itself,  beyond 
which  we  cannot  by  any  stretch  of  thought  or  internal 
scrutiny  advance,  being  obliged  to  stay  at  the  simple  point 
of  our  will,  purpose,  inclinations  as  existing  in  us.  But  the 
inclination  itself  of  the  will  is  the  same,  however  it  may 
have  been  originated  ;  no  difference  therefore  respecting 
its  origin  touches  the  subject  matter  of  our  consciousness. 
This  question  affects  the  cause,  our  consciousness  is  con 
cerned  only  with  the  fact ;  these  two,  therefore,  can  never 
come  into  collision.  And  though  in  popular  language 
such  a  grace  would  be  spoken  of  as  obliging  a  man  to  act 
in  a  particular  way,  as  if  it  obliged  hirn  so  to  act  whether 
he  willed  or  not,  operating  as  physical  force  does,  indepen 
dent  of  the  will  of  the  agent  altogether ;  such  a  description 
of  it  is  incorrect,  and  misses  the  fundamental  distinction 
in  the  case.  The  agent  is  not  caused  by  it  to  act  in  spite 
of  his  will,  but  caused  to  will. 

This  general  description  of  the  structure  and  defence  of 
the  doctrine  of  predestination  will  perhaps  be  sufficient  as 
an  introduction  to  the  present  treatise.  Nakedly  stated, 
the  doctrine  is  simply  paradoxical,  and  those  who  are  ac 
quainted  with  no  more  than  the  mere  statement  of  it,  are 


CHAP.  i.  For  Predestination.  15 

apt  to  feel  surprise  and  perplexity  how  it  could  have  been 
maintained  by  the  pious  and  thoughtful  minds  that  have 
maintained  it.  But  it  must  be  admitted  that  its  para 
doxical  character  is  diminished,  when  we  come  to  examine 
its  grounds  and  construction.  It  happens  in  this  case,  as 
it  does  in  many  others,  that  the  surprise  which  the  con 
clusion  produced  is  lessened  by  an  acquaintance  with  the 
premisses,  the  steps  by  which  it  was  arrived  at. 

Simplicity  of  system  is  a  great  object  with  one  class  of 
minds.  The  attribute  of  Divine  power  has  also  in  many 
religious  minds  the  position  not  only  of  important,  but 
favourite  truth.  It  is  evident  how  acceptable  on  both  these 
grounds  must  be  a  system  which  contrives  in  harmony  with 
the  facts  of  experience  and  the  rule  of  justice,  to  secure 
the  one  great  idea  of  the  whole  spiritual  action  of  the 
human  race  being  the  pure  creation  of  Almighty  will. 
They  are  attracted  by  a  conclusion  which  gives  so  signal 
a  rebuke -to  human  pride,  and  witness  to  Divine  mercy,  and 
embrace  a  doctrine  which  alone  appears  fully  to  set  forth 
that  man  is  nothing  and  (rod  all  in  all. 


CHAPTER   II. 

EXAMINATION    OF    THE    ARGUMENT   FOR   PREDESTINATION. 

WHEN  particular  truths  of  philosophy  or  religion  are  used 
as  grounds  to  support  conclusions  which  are  repugnant  to 
natural  reason,  there  are  two  things  for  us  to  do.  First, 
we  have  to  examine  if  the  reasoning  upon  these  truths  is 
correct,  and  if  they  really  contain  the  conclusions  which 
have  been  drawn  from  them ;  and,  secondly,  if  this  should 
be  the  case,  we  have  to  examine  the  nature  of  these  truths, 
and  the  sense  or  manner  in  which  we  hold  them  ;  for  if  the 
truths  themselves  cannot  be  questioned,  and  yet  the  logical 
conclusions  from  them  are  untenable,  there  only  remains 
for  extricating  ourselves  from  the  difficulty,  the  considera- 


Examination  of  the  CHAP.  n. 


tion  that  these  truths  must  have  been  held  in  some  sense 
or  manner  which  was  improper  ;  which  impropriety  in  the 
manner  of  holding  them  has  heen  the  reason  why,  however 
certain  themselves,  they  have  led  to  such  untenable  results. 

Let  us  take  the  case  of  philosophical  predestination  in 
the  first  place,  or  of  predestination  as  resting  on  philoso 
phical  grounds,  or  what  is  ordinarily  called  necessitarianism 
or  fatalism  ;  and  let  us  examine  the  nature  of  these  grounds. 
It  will  be  evident  to  any  one  at  all  conversant  with  philo 
sophy,  and  who  will  summon  to  his  mind  a  few  instances  of 
the  different  kinds  of  truth,  to  which  it  calls  our  attention, 
and  which  it  assumes  and  uses  in  its  arguments  and  specu 
lations,  that  there  are  two  very  different  kinds  of  truths 
upon  which  philosophy  proceeds  —  one,  of  which  the  con 
ception  is  distinct  and  absolute  ;  the  other,  of  which  the 
conception  is  indistinct,  and  only  incipient  or  in  tendency. 
Of  ordinary  facts,  such  as  meet  the  senses  —  of  the  facts  of 
our  internal  consciousness,  our  own  feelings  and  sensations, 
bodily  and  mental,  we  have  distinct  conceptions,  so  far  at 
least,  that  these  are  complete  and  absolute  truths  embraced 
by  our  minds.  On  the  other  hand,  there  are  various  truths 
which  we  partly  conceive  and  partly  fail  in  conceiving  ;  the 
conception,  when  it  has  begun,  does  riot  advance  or  come 
to  a  natural  termination,  but  remains  a  certain  tendency 
of  thought  only.  Such  are  the  ideas  of  substance,  of 
cause,  of  infinity,  and  others  which  we  cannot  grasp  or 
subject  to  our  minds,  and  which,  when  we  follow  them  up, 
involve  us  in  the  utmost  perplexity,  and  carry  us  into 
great  apparent  contradictions.  These,  as  entertained  by 
our  minds,  are  incipient  truths,  not  final  or  absolute  ones. 
In  following  or  trying  to  follow  them,  we  feel  that  we  are 
in  a  certain  right  way,  that  we  are  going  in  a  certain  true 
direction  of  thought  ;  but  we  attain  no  goal,  and  arrive 
at  no  positive  apprehension. 

In  contemplating  material  objects,  I  encounter  a  num 
ber  of  impressions,  such  as  hardness,  softness,  smoothness, 
roughness,  colour,  which  are  only  qualities  ;  but  I  cannot 
rest  in  them,  but  push  on  to  some  substance  to  which  they 
belong,  and  from  which  it  is  absurd  to  imagine  them  apart. 


CHAP.  ii.       Argument  for  Predestination.  17 

But  I  cannot  form  the  least  idea  of  what  substance  is.  I 
find  myself  only  going  in  the  direction  of  something  which 
I  cannot  reach,  which  mocks  all  pursuit,  and  eludes  all 
grasp ;  I  have  only  a  sort  of  idea  of  a  confused  something 
lying  underneath  all  the  sensible  qualities  of  matter — that 
is  to  say,  beyond  and  outside  of  all  my  real  perceptions. 
And  I  am  just  as  incapable  of  forming  any  idea  of  a  spirit 
ual  substance  or  myself,  though  I  am  said  to  be  conscious 
of  it ;  for  this  plain  reason,  that  it  is  in  its  very  nature 
anterior  to  all  my  ideas. 

Again,  I  have  the  idea  of  force  or  power,  or,  what  is 
the  same  thing,  of  cause.  After  contemplating  any  event 
in  life  or  nature  I  find  myself  going  in  thought  beyond  it, 
to  consider  how  it  came  to  pass ;  and  this  thought  in  me, 
once  set  going,  tends,  by  some  instinctive  law,  some  con 
stitutional  motion  inherent  in  it,  in  the  direction  of  a  cause 
of  that  event ;  something  not  merely  antecedent  to  it,  but 
which  stands  in  such  a  relation  to  it,  as  that,  in  consequence 
of  it,  that  event  or  thing  exists.  The  intellect  pushes  on 
to  this  ultimate  resting  place,  and  satisfaction  of  its  own 
indigenous  want  and  desire.  But  while  the  movement 
towards  a  cause,  or  some  kind  of  idea  of  one,  is  part  of  our 
rational  nature,  I  find,  on  reflection,  that  I  can  form  no 
distinct  conception  whatever  of  what  a  cause  is.  What  is 
that  of  which  existence  is  the  necessary  fruit  and  result  ? 
We  can  form  no  idea  of  what  goes  on  previous  to,  and  with 
infallible  cogency  and  force  for,  producing  existence.  All 
this  preliminary  agency  is  so  entirely  hid  from  us,  and  our 
faculties  so  completely  stop  short  of  it,  that  it  seems 
almost  like  an  absurdity  to  us,  that  there  should  be  any 
thing  of  the  kind.  The  order  of  nature  puts  before  us  an 
endless  succession  of  antecedents  and  consequents,  but  in 
no  one  instance  can  we  see  any  necessary  connection 
between  the  antecedent  and  its  consequent.  The  relation 
between  the  so-called  cause  and  effect — the  circumstance 
in  a  cause  which  makes  it  a  cause,  is  wholly  removed  from 
my  view.  I  see  that  fire  melts  metals  and  hardens  clay, 
but  I  do  not  see  why  it  does  either ;  and  prior  to  experience, 
I  should  have  thought  it  as  likely  that  these  effects  would 

c 


j  g  Examination  q/  the  CHAP.  "• 

have  been  reversed.  The  motion  which  one  ball  set  in 
motion  communicates  to  another,  might  or  might  not  have 
taken  place  prior  to  experience.  I  see  nothing  in  the  first 
motion  to  produce  the  second,  and  can  conceive  no  motion 
upon  impact  with  as  little  contradiction  as  motion.  Again, 
I  look  into  myself,  and  observe  my  own  motions,  actions, 
thoughts.  I  find  that  by  a  certain  exertion  of  the  will,  I 
can  move  my  limbs,  raise  ideas,  excite  or  suppress  affec 
tions  and  emotions  ;  but  the  nature  of  that  power  by  which 
the  will  does  this,  is  absolutely  hidden  from  me.  When  I 
exert  all  my  force  to  lift  some  weight  or  remove  some  bar 
rier,  I  may  seem  at  first  to  myself  to  have  an  inward 
perception  of  that  force,  and  the  manner  in  which  it 
operates  ;  but  on  examination,  I  find  that  I  have  only  the 
idea  of  a  motion  of  the  will,  and  of  a  strain  of  the  muscles 
which  succeeds,  not  of  any  connection  between  the  two.1 
I  have  looked  around  and  within  me  then,  and  I  do  not  see 
a  cause  anywhere.  My  reason,  as  surely  as  it  leads  me  up 
to  the  truth,  that  there  is  a  cause  of  things,  stops  at  that 
point,  and  leaves  me  in  utter  perplexity  and  amazement  as 
to  what  a  cause  is.  It  is  a  wonder,  a  mystery,  an  incom 
prehensible  truth.  My  reason  forces  me  towards  the  idea 
of  something,  of  which  I  can  give  no  more  account  to 
myself  than  I  can  of  the  most  inexplicable  article  in  a 
creed.  What  can  be  more  astonishing  than  a  power  by 
which  anything  in  nature  is.  Do  all  the  mysteries  of 
revelation — do  even  the  wildest  dreams  of  superstition  ex- 

1  It  may  be  pretended  that  the  its  command  over  ideas  and  limbs, 
resistance  which  we  meet  with  in  ...  Secondly,  this  sentiment  of  an 
bodies,  obliging  us  frequently  to  endeavour  to  overcome  resistance 
exert  all  our  force,  and  call  up  all  has  no  known  connection  with  any 
our  power,  thus  gives  us  the  idea  of  event ;  what  follows  it,  we  know  by 
force  and  power.  It  is  this  nisus  or  experience,  but  would  not  know  it  a 
strong  endeavour  of  which  we  are  priori.  It  must,  however,  be  con- 
conscious,  that  is  the  original  irn-  fessed  that  the  animal  nisus  which 
pression  from  which  this  idea  is  we  experience,  though  it  can  afford 
copied.  But,  first,  we  attribute  no  accurate  or  precise  idea  of  power, 
power  to  a  vast  number  of  objects  enters  very  much  into  that  vulgar 
where  we  can  never  suppose  this  inaccurate  idea  which  is  formed  of 
resistance  or  force  to  take  place  ;  to  it.— Hume,  '  Enquiry  concerning  the 
the  bupreme  Being,  who  never  meets  Human  Understanding,'  sect.  7. 
with  any  resistance ;  to  the  mind  in 


CHAP.  n.       Argument  for  Predestination.  19 

ceed  it  ?  What  is  it  that  prevents  my  reason  from  reject 
ing  such  an  idea  ?  Simply,  that  my  reason  gives  it  me — • 
gives  it  me,  though  in  that  incipient  and  incomplete  state 
from  which  this  perplexity  ensues. 

Again,  the  idea  of  infinity  is  part  of  our  rational 
nature.  Particular  times,  spaces,  and  numbers,  end  ;  but 
we  cannot  possibly  think  of  time,  space,  and  number  in 
general  as  ending.  Any  particular  number  is  suggestive 
of  further  number.  In  two  or  three  straight  strokes  I  see 
a  necessary  capacity  of  multiplication,  two,  three,  or  any 
number  of  times  ad  infinitum.  I  imagine  myself  at  the 
top  of  a  high  mountain,  with  the  largest  conceivable  view 
all  around  me.  I  might  know  by  geography  that  there 
are  countries  which  lie  beyond  it  on  all  sides,  but  I  do  not 
wait  for  that  information.  There  is  something  in  me  by 
which  1 9 know  antecedently,  that  the  space  is  going  on  all 
the  same  as  space,  however  differently  it  may  be  occupied, 
beyond  my  sight  as  within  it.  Having  raised  in  my  mind 
the  largest  picture  of  space  I  can,  so  that  if  I  try  to  in 
crease,  I  simply  repeat  it,  I  have  still  a  sense  of  limitation. 
There  is  at  the  furthest  line  of  the  horizon  an  excess 
which  baffles  me,  which  is  not  included  in  the  imagined 
space,  or  it  would  not  be  an  excess,  and  which  yet  belongs 
and  is  attached  to  it  and  cannot  be  removed ;  an  incipient 
beyond  which  must  be  endless,  for  the  very  reason  that  it 
begins  ;  because  this  indefinable  excess,  for  the  very  reason 
that  it  exists  itself,  must  be  succeeded  by  the  like.  It  is 
the  same  with  respect  to  time.  Time,  space,  and  number, 
then,  do  not  end,  but  go  on  at  the  very  last ;  that  is  the 
very  latest  perception  we  have  of  them,  the  last  intelli 
gence  as  it  were  ;  they  are  ultimately  going  further.  They 
go  onward,  not  only  to  the  end  (which  particular  portions 
of  them  do),  but  at  the  end — i.e.  their  utmost  defined 
extent  in  our  imagination  ;  for  their  very  nature  is  pro 
gressive  ;  they  are  essentially  irrepressible,  uncontrollable, 
ever-growing,  without  capacity  for  standing  still  and  sub 
ject  to  the  absolute  necessity  of  being  continually  greater 
and  greater. 

But  while  we  find  in  our  minds  the  idea  of  infinity,  we 
c  2 


20  Examination  of  the  CHAP.  IT- 

have  no  idea  of  what  infinity  is.  I  mean  that  we  have  no 
idea  of  an  actual  infinite  quantity  of  anything.  We  ap 
prehend  so  much  of  extent  or  number  as  we  can  measure 
or  count,  and  can  go  on  adding ;  but  wherever  we  stop,  we 
are  on  the  margin  of  an  infinite  remainder,  which  is  not 
apprehended  by  us.  Imagine  a  large  crowd  increasing  in 
all  directions  without  end ;  it  is  obvious  that  such  number 
is  unintelligible  to  us ;  as  much  so  as  any  mysterious  article 
in  a  creed.  °  Some  idea  of  infinity  we  have  no  doubt,  other 
wise  we  should  not  be  able  to  think  or  speak  of  it  at  all ; 
and  that  seems  to  be  more  than  a  negative  idea,  as  it  has 
been  asserted  to  be  ;  for  it  is  the  idea  of  a  progress,  or  going 
further,  which  is  not  negative,  but  positive ;  but  it  is  no 
mental  image  or  reflection  of  actual  infinity.1 

We  find  then  a  certain  class  of  truths  in  philosophy  of 
which  we  have  only  a  half  conception ;  truths  which,  as 
entertained  by  us,  are  only  truths  in  tendency,  not  absolute, 
not  complete.  We  are  conscious  of  the  germs  of  various 
ideas  which  we  cannot  open  out,  or  realise  as  whole  or  con 
sistent  ones.  We  feel  ourselves  reaching  after  what  we  cannot 
grasp,  and  moving  onward  in  thought  towards  something 
we  cannot  overtake.  I  move  in  the  direction  of  a  substance 
and  a  cause  in  nature  which  I  cannot  find  :  my  thought 
reaches  after  infinity,  but  the  effort  is  abortive,  and  the  idea 
remains  for  ever  only  beginning.  I  encounter  mysterious 
truths  in  philosophy  before  I  come  to  them  in  religion, 
natural  or  revealed.  My  reason  itself  introduces  me  to 
them.  Were  I  without  the  faculty  of  reason,  I  should  not 
have  these  ideas  at  all,  or  derive  therefore  any  perplexity 
from  them.  I  should  want  no  substance  underneath  my 
impressions  ;  I  should  have  no  sense  of  an  excess  beyond 
the  range  of  my  eye  :  but  reason  creates  thesa  movements 

1  It  is  an  oblique  proof  of  the  ce  qu'il  est.  II  est  faux  qu'il  soit  pair, 

mysteriousness  of  infinite  number,  il  est  faux  qu'il  soit  impair;  car  en 

tli at  it  can  be  neither  odd  nor  even.  ajoutant  1'unite,  il  ne  change  point 

' Nous  connaissons  qu'il  y auninfini,  de  nature:  cependant  c'est  un  nom- 

et  ignorons  sa  nature,  comme  nous  bre,  et  tout  nombre  est  pair  ou  im- 

s-iyons  qu'il  est  faux  qua  les  nombres  pair ;  il  est  vrai  que  cela  s'entend 

soient  finis;  doncilestvraiqu'ilyaun  de  tous  nombres  finis.— Pascal  (ed. 

infini  en  nombre,  mais  nous  ne  savons  Faugere),  vol.  ii.  p.  164. 


CHAP.  it.        Argument  for  Predestination.  2  r 

in  my  mind,  and  so  introduces  me  to  indistinct  and  myste 
rious  truths  within  her  own  sphere. 

And  this,  it  may  be  remarked,  is  an  answer  to  those 
who  object  to  such  truths  in  religion,  and  reject  or  put 
aside  certain  doctrines  on  the  ground  that  they  relate  to 
subject-matter  of  which  we  can  form  no  conception,  and 
which,  therefore,  it  is  argued,  we  cannot  entertain  in  our 
minds  at  all ;  cannot  make  the  subject  of  thought,  or  there 
fore  of  belief.  It  is  wrong  to  say  that  we  are  wholly  unable 
to  entertain  truths  of  which  we  have  no  distinct  idea  ;  and 
those  who  suppose  so  have  an  incorrect  and  defective  notion 
of  the  constitution  of  the  human  mind.  The  human  mind 
is  so  constituted  as  to  have  relations  to  truth  without  the 
medium  of  distinct  ideas  and  conceptions.  The  constitu 
tion  of  our  minds  makes  this  mixed  state  of  ignorance  and 
knowledge  possible  to  us.  Were  the  alternative  of  pure 
ignorance  or  pure  knowledge  necessary,  it  is  evident  that, 
as  soon  as  we  turn  from  sensible  objects  and  mathematics, 
we  should  be  in  a  state  of  absolute  ignorance  and  unmixed 
darkness ;  we  should  not  only  be  ignorant  of  the  nature  of 
many  other  truths,  but  should  have  no  sort  of  idea  what 
those  truths  were  of  which  we  were  ignorant ;  we  should 
be  unable  to  think  of  or  discuss  them  on  that  account,  or 
even  to  name  them.  We  should  be  cut  off  wholly  from 
metaphysics,  and  all  that  higher  thought  and  philosophy 
which  have  occupied  the  human  mind  in  all  ages.  But  this 
alternative  is  not  necessary.1 

With  the  general  admission,  then,  of  this  class  of  truths 
in  philosophy,  we  come  to  the  grounds  upon  which  philo 
sophical  predestination  or  fatalism  is  raised.  We  find  these 
to  be  mainly  two — first,  the  maxim  that  every  event  must 
have  a  cause,  and,  secondly,  the  idea  of  the  Divine  Power  ; 
the  first  being  a  physical,  the  second  a  religious  assumption, 
but  both  alike  forming  premisses  from  which  a  scheme  of 
absolute  necessity  in  human  actions  is  logically  inferred. 

1  'Nous  sommes  sur  un  milieu  prises;  il  se  derobe,  et  fuit  d'une 

vaste,  toujoursincertains,  etflotlants  fuite  eternelle:  rien  ne   pent   1'ar- 

entre  1'ignorance  et  la  connaissance ;  reter.' — Pascal.     Locke  and  Hume 

et,  si  nous  pensons  aller  plus  avant,  both  substantially  admit  the  class  of 

noire  objet  branle,  et  echappe  a  nos  indistinct  ideas. — NOTE  IV. 


22 


Examination  of  the  CHAP.  n. 


To  take  first,  then,  the  maxim  that  every  event  must 
have  a  cause.  This  is  a  maxim  undoubtedly  that  approves 
itself  to  our  understanding.  If  we  see  a  body  which  has 
hitherto  been  at  rest,  start  out  of  this  state  of  rest  and 
begin  to  move,  we  naturally  and  necessarily  suppose  that 
there  must  be  some  cause  or  reason  of  this  new  mode  of  ex 
istence.  And  this  applies  to  moral  events  or  actions  as  well 
as  to  events  physical.  Every  action  which  is  performed  is 
undoubtedly  a  new  event  in  nature,  and  as  such  there  must 
have  been  some  cause  to  produce  it.  Moreover,  on  the  same 
principle  that  the  action  itself  must  have  a  cause,  that  cause 
must  have  another  cause,  and  so  on,  till  we  come  to  some 
cause  outside  of  and  beyond  the  agent  himself.  The 
maxim,  then,  that  there  must  be  a  cause  of  every  event  once 
granted,  the  conclusion  of  a  necessity  in  human  actions 
inevitably  follows. 

But  though  the  maxim  that  every  event  must  have  a 
cause  is  undoubtedly  true,  what  kind  of  a  truth  is  it  ?  Is 
it  a  truth  absolute  and  complete,  like  a  fact  of  sensation  or 
reflection  ;  or  is  it  a  truth  indistinct,  incipient,  and  in  ten 
dency  only,  like  one  of  those  ideas  which  have  just  been 
discussed  ?  It  is  a  truth  of  the  latter  kind,  for  this  simple 
reason,  that  there  is  a  contrary  truth  to  it.  When  we  look 
into  our  minds,  and  examine  the  nature  and  characteristics 
of  action,  we  find  that  we  have  a  certain  natural  and  irre 
sistible  impression  or  sense  of  our  originality  as  agents. 
We  feel  beforehand  that  we  can  do  a  thing  or  not  as  we 
please,  and  when  we  have  taken  either  course,  we  feel  after 
wards  that  we  could  have  taken  the  other,  and  experience 
satisfaction  or  regret,  as  may  be,  on  that  particular  account. 
That  our  actions  are  original  in  us,  is  the  ground  upon 
which  arise  peculiar  pleasures  and  pains  of  conscience, 
which  are  known  and  familiar  to  us.  Could  we  really  think 
that  they  were  not,  we  should  be  without  these  particular 
feelings ;  we  should  not  have  a  certain  class  of  sensations 
which  we  know  we  have.  We  have,  then,  a  certain  sense 
or  perception  of  our  originality  as  agents,  that  an  action 
is  original  in  us,  or  has  no  cause. 

This  originality  in  human  actions  is,  for  want  of  better 


CHAP.  ir.        Argument  for  Predestination.  23 

language,  sometimes  expressed  by  what  is  called  the  self- 
determination  of  the  will ;  and  from  this  mode  of  express 
ing  it  persons  have  endeavoured  to  extract  a  reductio  ad 
absurdum  of  the  truth  itself.  For  it  has  been  said,  '  If 
will  determines  will,  then  choice  orders  and  determines 
choice,  and  acts  of  choice  are  subject  to  the  decision  and 
follow  the  conduct  of  other  acts  of  choice  ; '  in  which  case 
every  act  whatever  of  the  will  must  be  preceded  by  a  for 
mer  act,  and  there  must  therefore  be  an  act  of  the  will 
before  the  first  act  of  the  will.1  But  in  the  first  place  it  is 
evident  this  is  at  the  best  an  argument  drawn  from  a  par 
ticular  mode  of  expressing  a  truth,  and  taking  advantage 
of  the  inherent  detects  of  language  ;  and  in  the  next  place 
that  it  does  not  do  justice  even  to  the  language;  for  however 
inconceivable  self-motion  strictly  speaking  may  be,  what  we 
mean  and,  so  far  as  we  can,  express  by  it,  is  one  indivisible 
motion,  not  a  relation  of  one  motion  to  another,  of  some 
thing  moving  to  something  being  moved,  as  is  supposed  in 
this  argument,  and  is  necessary  to  the  force  of  it.  The  real 
question,  however,  at  issue  is,  in  whatever  way  we  may 
express  it,  have  we  or  have  we  not  a  certain  sense  of  origi 
nality  in  our  acts ;  that  we  are  springs  of  motion  to  our 
selves  ;  that  however  particular  motives  and  impulses  from 
without  may  operate  on  us,  there  is  a  certain  ultimate 
decision,  which  we  can  make  either  way,  and  which  there 
fore  when  made,  in  one  way  or  the  other,  is  original.  If 
we  have,  we  have  a  certain  sense  or  perception  of  action  as 
being  something  uncaused,  i.e.  having  nothing  anterior  to 
it,  which  necessarily  produces  it — a  sense  or  perception 
which  goes  counter  to  the  other,  which  was  also  admitted 
to  exist  in  us,  of  the  necessity  of  a  cause  for  all  events, 

1  Edwards   '  On  the  Freedom  of  Et  si  quidam  ipsa  moverat  seipsam 

the  Will,' part  2.  sect.  1.     Aquinas  ad  volendum  oportuisset,  quod  medi- 

in  arguing  for  the  necessity  of  an  ante  consilio  hoc  ageret  ex  aliqu4 

extern  il  source  of  motion   to   the  voluntate  prsesupposita     Hocautem 

will   (moveri    ab    aliquo    exterior!  est  procedere  in  infinitum.     Unde 

principio)  reasons  in  the  same  way.  necesse  est  ponere  quod  in  primum 

4  Manifestum  est  quod  voluntas  in-  motum  voluntatis  voluntas  prodeat 

cipit  velle  aliquid  cum  hocprius  non  ex  instinctu  alicujus  exterioris  mo- 

vellet.     Necesse  est  ergo  quod   ab  ventis.' — Sum.  Theol.  p.  2.  q.  9.  art. 

aliquo  moveatur  ad  volendum.  ...  4. 


Examination  of  the 


CHAP.  ir. 


actions  included.  Kegarding  actions  in  their  general  cha 
racter  as  events,  we  say  they  must  have  a  cause  ;  but  in  their 
special  character  as  actions,  we  refuse  them  one  :  our  whole 
internal  feeling  and  consciousness  being  opposed  to  it. 
Here  then  are  two  contradictory  instincts  or  perceptions 
of  our  reason,  which  we  must  make  the  best  of,  and  arrive 
at  what  measure  of  truth  a  mixed  conclusion  gives.  We 
certainly  have  both  these  perceptions,  and  one  must  not  be 
made  to  give  way  to  the  other.  However  reason  may  de 
clare  for  the  originality  of  our  acts,  it  says  also  that  every 
event  must  have  a  cause  ;  again,  however  it  may  declare 
for  a  cause  of  every  event,  it  says  that  our  acts  are  original. 
Metaphysicians  on  both  sides  appear  to  have  under 
valued  the  one  or  the  other  of  these  rational  instincts  or 
perceptions,  according  to  their  bias  ;  the  advocates  of  free 
will  thinking  slightly  of  the  general  instinct  for  a  cause,  the 
advocates  of  necessity  thinking  slightly  of  our  perception,  as 
agents,  of  originality.  The  former  have  simply  dwelt  on 
our  inward  consciousness  of  power  of  choice,  dismissing  the 
principle  of  causes,  as  if,  however,  it  applied  to  other  events, 
it  did  not  apply  to  actions,  being  excluded  from  this  ground 
ipso  facto  by  this  sense  of  the  originality  of  our  actions. 
But  if  the  necessity  of  a  cause  of  events  is  true  at  all,  it 
must  apply  to  actions  as  well  as  to  other  events  ;  and  to 
suppose  that  it  is  ipso  facto  deprived  of  this  application 
by  this  special  sense  of  originality  in  the  case  of  actions,  is 
to  assume  that  we  cannot  have  two  contradictory  ideas  ; 
which,  according  to  what  I  endeavoured  to  show  in  this 
chapter,  is  a  false  assumption,  and  not  true  of  us  in  the  pre 
sent  imperfect  state  of  our  capacities,  in  which  we  may  have, 
and  have,  imperfect  opposing  perceptions  ;  though  it  is  of 
course  absurd  to  suppose  that  this  can  be  the  case  except 
in  a  very  imperfect  state  of  being,  or  that  there  can  be 
absolute  and  perfect  perceptions  in  opposition  to  each  other. 
The  latter,  on  the  other  hand,  have  regarded  the  principle 
of  causation  as  the  only  premiss  worth  taking  into  account 
on  this  question,  and  have  dismissed  the  sense  of  originality, 
as  if  it  were  a  mere  confused  and  blind  sentiment,  which, 
when  examined,  really  spoke  to  nothing,  and  was  found  to 


CHAP.  IT.       Argument  for  Predestination.  25 

issue  in  a  mere  cloud,  or  evaporate  altogether.  They  have 
voted  the  one  idea  to  be  solid  and  philosophical,  the  other 
to  be  empty  and  delusive.  But  I  cannot  see  how  they  are 
justified  in  thus  setting  up  one  of  these  ideas  to  the  exclu 
sion  of  the  other.  Express  the  idea  of  causation  as  you  will, 
whether  as  the  perception  of  an  abstract  truth  that  there 
must  be  a  ca^ise  of  all  events,  or  simply  as  the  observation 
of  the  fact,  that  all  events  are  connected  with  certain  ante 
cedents  as  the  condition  of  their  taking  place1 — what  is  it, 
after  all,  but  a  truth  so  far  as  it  goes,  and  so  far  as  we  per 
ceive  or  observe  it  to  be  such  ?  The  reason  desiderates  a 
cause  of  anything  that  takes  place,  says  one  philosopher, 
putting  it  as  the  perception  of  an  abstract  truth  ;  but  this 
necessity  is  not  to  be  acknowledged  in  any  more  unlimited 
sense  than  that  in  which  it  is  perceived.  In  the  case  of 
events  in  nature,  the  axiom  reigns  supreme,  and  is  not  in 
terfered  with;  but  when  we  corne  to  moral  events  or  actions, 
.it  is  there  met  by  an  innate  perception — viz.  that  of  origin 
ality  which  is  just  as  rational  as  the  other.  Another  philo 
sopher  says  that  we  observe  causation  as  a  fact.*  We  do ; 
but  though  we  observe  it  in  nature,  we  do  not  certainly 
observe  it  in  will ;  and  observation  can  only  speak  to  those 
cases  to  which  it  extends.  The  consideration  of  ourselves 
as  agents  presents  another  truth  to  us — viz.  that  of  origin 
ality  in  our  acts ;  and  this  instinct  or  perception  must  be 
taken  into  account  as  a  philosophical  premiss.  How  should 
we  have  the  idea  of  the  will  as  being  self-moving  and  self- 
determining  at  all  in  the  way  in  which  we  have  it,  unless 
there  were  truth  in  the  idea  ?  For  nature  does  not  deceive 
us  and  tell  us  falsehoods,  however  it  may  tell  us  imperfect 
truths.  And  though  it  may  be  said  that  all  that  we  mean 
by  the  will's  self-determination,  is  that  we  act  with  will  as 
distinct  from  compulsion,  however  that  will  may  have  been 
caused  ;  this  is  not  true  upon  any  natural  test ;  for,  put  this 
distinction  before  any  plain  man,  and  he  will  feel  it  as  an 
interference  in  some  way  with  his  natural  consciousness,  and 
will  reject  the  idea  of  an  externally-caused  will,  as  not  pro 
perly  answering  to  his  instinct  on  this  subject.  And  if  it 
1  The  former  is  Edwards's,  the  latter  Mr.  Mill's  position.  NOTB  V. 


2 5  Examination  of  the  CHAP,  n. 

be  argued  that  we  cannot  have  this  sense  of  originality  or 
self-determination  in  the  will,  because  all  that  we  are  ac 
tually  conscious  of  is  our  will  itself,  the  fact  that  we  decide 
in  one  way  or  another,  and  not  the  cause  of  it,  whether  in 
ourselves  or  beyond  us  ;  it  is  sufficient  to  say  that  this  sense 
or  perception  of  originality  is  not  professed  to  be  absolute 
or  complete,  but  that  it  is  still  a  sense  or  perception  of  a 
certain  kind.  There  is  a  plain  instinct  in  us,  a  perception 
of  a  truth,  in  this  direction  ;  and  that  being  ^the  case,  to  say 
that  it  is  not  apprehension  and  does  not  arrive  at  a  positive 
conclusion  or  point,  is  to  say  no  more  than  may  be  said  of 
many  other  great  ideas  of  our  intelligent  nature,  such  as  that 
of  substance,  cause,  infinity. 

There  being  these  two  counter  ideas,  then,  with  respect 
to  the  necessity  of  a  cause ;  as  on  the  one  hand  we  demand 
a  cause,  and  on  the  other  reject  it;  neither  of  these  can  be 
truths  absolute  and  complete  ;  and.  therefore,  neither  of 
them  a  basis  for  an  absolute  and  complete  theory  or  doctrine 
to  be  raised  upon  it,  So  far  as  the  maxim  that  there  must 
be  a  cause  of  every  event  is  true,  so  far  it  is  a  premiss  for 
a  scheme  of  fatalism.  But  it  is  not  true  absolutely,  and 
thus  no  absolute  system  of  this  kind  can  be  founded  upon 
it.  Did  the  fatalist  limit  himself  to  a  conditional  incom 
plete  conclusion,  i.e. — for  this  would  be  all  that  it  would 
come  to  in  such  a  case — to  a  mystery  on  this  subject,  no  one 
could  object.  But  if  he  raises  a  definite  scheme,  his  con 
clusion  exceeds  his  premiss. 

The  same  may  be  said  of  any  absolute  doctrine  of  Pre 
destination  drawn  from  the  attribute  of  the  Divine  Power, 
or  the  idea  of  God  as  the  cause  of  all  things.  There  is  an 
insurmountable  contradiction  between  this  idea  and  that  of 
freewill  in  the  creature ;  for  we  cannot  conceive  how  that 
which  is  caused  can  itself  be  a  first  cause,  or  a  spring  of 
motion  to  itself.  And  therefore  the  idea  of  Divine  Power 
leads  to  predestination  as  its  result.  But  what  is  this  truth 
of  the  Divine  Power  or  Omnipotence,  as  we  apprehend  it  ? 
Does  it  belong  to  the  class  of  full  and  distinct,  or  of  incom 
plete  truths  ?  Certainly  to  the  latter,  for  there  appears 
at  once  a  counter  truth  to  it,  in  the  existence  of  moral  evil 


CHAP.  IT.       Argument  for  Predestination.  27 

which  must  be  referred  fco  some  cause  other  than  (rod,  as 
well  as  in  that  sense  of  our  own  originality  to  which  I  have 
just  alluded.  The  Divine  Omnipotence,  then,  is  a  truth 
which  we  do  not  understand—  mysterious,  imperfect  truth  ; 
and,  therefore,  cannot  be  used  by  the  predestinarian  as  the 
premiss  of  an  absolute  doctrine,  but  only  as  that  of  an  in 
definite  or  conditional  one. 

The  two  ideas  of  the  Divine  Power  and  freewill  are,  in 
short,  two  great  tendencies  of  thought  inherent  in  our  minds, 
which  contradict  each  other,  and  can  never  be  united  or 
brought  to  a  common  goal ;  and  which,  therefore,  inasmuch 
as  the  essential  condition  of  absolute  truth  is  consistency 
with  other  truth,  can  never,  in  the  present  state  of  our 
faculties,  become  absolute  truths,  but  must  remain  for  ever 
contradictory  tendencies  of  thought,  going  on  side  by  side 
till  they  are  lost  sight  of  and  disappear  in  the  haze  of  our 
conceptions,  like  two  parallel  straight  lines  which  go  on  to 
infinity  without  meeting.  While  they  are  sufficiently  clear, 
then,  for  purposes  of  practical  religion  (for  we  cannot  doubt 
that  they  are  truths  so  far  as  and  in  that  mode  in  which  we 
apprehend  them),  these  are  truths  upon  which  we  cannot 
raise  definite  and  absolute  systems.  All  that  we  build  upon 
either  of  them  must  partake  of  the  imperfect  nature  of  the 
premiss  which  supports  it,  and  be  held  under  a  reserve  of 
consistency  with  a  counter  conclusion  from  the  opposite 
truth.  And  as  I  may  have  occasion  hereafter  to  use  it,  I 
may  as  well  say  here  that  this  is  what  I  mean  by  the  dis 
tinction  between  absolute  truths,  and  truths  which  are 
truths  and  yet  not  absolute  ones — viz.,  that  the  one  are  of 
that  kind  which  is  distinct  and  consistent  with  other  truth  ; 
the  other  of  the  kind  which  is  indistinct,  and  especially  such 
truth  as  has  other  truth  opposed  to  it,  and  which  is  there 
fore  obviously  but  half-truth. 

I  will  add  as  a  natural  corollary  from  this  relation  of  these 
two  ideas,  that  that  alone  is  a  genuine  doctrine  of  freewill 
which  maintains  such  a  freewill  in  man  as  is  inconsistent 
with  our  idea  of  the  Divine  Power.  There  is  a  kind  of 
freewill  which  is  consistent  with  this  idea.  All  men. 
whatever  be  their  theory  of  the  motive  principle  of,  admit 


2  8  Examination  of  the  CHAP,  n. 

the  fact  of,  the  human  will ;  that  we  act  willingly  and  not 
like  inanimate  machines  ;  nor  does  the  necessitarian  deny, 
that  the  human  will  is  will,  and  as  far  as  sensation  goes 
free,  though  he  represents  it  as  ultimately  moved  from 
without.  Here,  then,  is  a  sort  of  freewill  which  is  consistent 
with  the  idea  of  the  Divine  Power.  But  this,  as  was  above 
explained,  is  not  such  a  freewill  as  meets  the  demands  of 
natural  consciousness,  which  is  satisfied  with  nothing  short 
of  a  characteristic  of  will,  which  comes  into  collision  with 
our  idea  of  the  Divine  Power — viz.,  originality. 

Again,  the  objection  against  the  doctrine  of  freewill, 
that  it  would  remove  human  actions  from  the  Divine  Pro 
vidence,1  and  so  reduce  this  whole  moral  scheme  of  things 
to  chance,  has  an  immediate  answer  in  the  very  nature  of 
the  truth  as  here  described.  Undoubtedly  there  is  a  con 
tradiction  in  supposing  that  events  really  contingent  can 
be  foreseen,  made  the  subjects  of  previous  arrangement, 
and  come  into  a  scheme  of  Providence  ;  and  though  this 
is  sometimes  met  by  the  answer  that  the  Divine  foresight 
is  the  sight  of  the  events  as  such,  and  not  in  their  causes 
only,  and  that  therefore  contingent  events  can  be  foreseen 
by  God  as  being  events,  which  however  future  to  us,  are 
present  to  His  eternal  eye ;  it  must  be  owned  that  such  a 
foresight  as  this  is  a  contradiction  to  our  reason2,  and  that 

1  If  the  will  of  man  be  free  with  no  use  to  direct  and  regulate  perfect 

a  liberty  ad  utrumlibet,  and  if  his  accident. — Edwards  '  On  Freedom  of 

actions  be  the  offspring  of  his  will,  the  Will,'  part  3,  sect.  4. 

such  of  his  actions  which  are  not  yet  2  That  no  future  event  can  be 

wrought,  must  be  both  radically  and  certainly  foreknown  whose  existence 

eventually  uncertain.  It  is  therefore  is  contingent  and  without  all  neces- 

a  chance  whether  they  are  performed  sity,  may  be  proved  thus :  it  is  im- 

or  no.  ...  So  that  any  assertor  of  possible  for  a  thing  to  be  certainly 

self-determination  is  in  fact,  whether  known  to  any  intellect  without  evi- 

he  mean  it  or  no,  a  worshipper  of  the  dence  .  .  .    But   no  understanding, 

heathen  lady  named  Fortune,  and  an  created  or  uncreated,  can  see  evi- 

ideal  deposer  of  Providence  from  its  dence  where  there  is  none  .  .  .  But 

throne.— Toplady,  vol.  vi.  p.  90.  if  there  be  a  future  event   whose 

If  it  be  said  that  volitions  are  existence  is  contingent  without  all 

events  that  come  to  pass  without  necessity,  the   future    existence   of 

any  determining  cause,  that  is  most  the  event  is  absolutely  without  evi- 

palpably  inconsistent  with  all  use  of  dence.— Edwards,    '  On  Freedom  of 

laws  and  precepts;  for  nothing  is  Will,'  part  2,  sect.  12. 
more  plain  than  that  laws  can  be  of 


CHAP.  ir.       Argument  for  Predestination.  29 

therefore  an  answer  wbich  appeals  to  it,  to  solve  the  con 
tradiction  of  freewill  to  Providence,  only  gets  rid  of  one 
contradiction  by  another.  Allowing,  however,  the  contradic 
tion  between  Providence  and  freewill  to  remain,  what  comes 
in  the  way  of  argument  from  it  ?  All  imperfect  truths  run 
into  contradictions  when  they  are  pursued.  Thus,  a  great 
philosopher  has  extracted  the  greatest  absurdities  out  of 
the  idea  of  material  substance  ;  and  the  idea  of  infinity  is 
met  by  the  objection  that  all  number  must  be  either  odd  or 
even.  In  the  same  way  freewill,  when  pursued,  runs  into 
a  contradiction  to  Providence,  but  this  does  not  show  that 
it  is  false,  but  only  that  it  is  imperfect  truth. 

The  same  mode  of  treatment  applies  to  the  great  prin 
ciple  of  religion  (substantially  the  same  with  that  of  the 
Divine  Power)  that  God  is  the  Author  of  all  good,  if  used 
as  a  basis  of  an  absolute  doctrine  of  predestination.  Un 
doubtedly  from  this  principle  the  doctrine  of  irresistible 
grace  follows ;  for  according  to  it  man  derives  all  his  good 
ness  from  a  source  beyond  himself ;  and  with  this  doctrine 
of  grace,  predestination.  But  what  kind  of  a  truth  is  this 
principle  that  God  is  the  Author  of  all  good  ?  an  absolute 
or  an  imperfect  truth  ?  Plainly  the  latter.  There  is,  indeed, 
a  principle  of  humility  in  our  nature,  whether  belonging  to 
us  as  fallen  creatures,  or  necessary  to  the  very  relation  of 
dependence  implied  in  created  being,  which  leads  us  to  dis 
own  any  source  of  good  within  ourselves.  The  enlightened 
moral  being  has  an  instinctive  dread  of  appropriating  any 
good  that  he  may  see  in  himself  to  himself.  This  is  a  great 
fact  in  human  nature.  Our  hearts  bear  witness  to  it.  We 
shrink  from  the  claim  of  originating  good.  If  the  thought 
rises  up  in  our  minds,  we  put  it  down,  and  are  afraid  of 
entertaining  it.  As  soon  as  we  have  done  a  good  action, 
we  put  it  away  from  us  ;  we  try  not  to  think  of  it.  Thus 
praise  is  a  mixture  of  pleasure  and  pain :  the  first  motion 
in  our  minds  of  pure  pleasure  is  immediately  checked  by 
fear :  we  are  afraid  of  the  consciousness  of  being  praised, 
and  wish  to  cast  it  out  of  our  minds.  The  general  manners 
of  society,  the  disclaiming  of  merit  which  always  takes 
place  as  a  matter  of  form,  the  readiness  to  give  place  to 


Examination  of  the 


CHAP.  jr. 


others,  bear  witness  to  a  great  principle  of  humility  in 
human  nature,  by  which  it  is  ever  ejecting  the  source  of 
o-ood  from  itself,  and  falling  back  on  some  source  external 
and  unknown.  The  act  of  prayer  is  a  witness  to  the  same 
principle  ;  for  we  pray  to  God  for  moral  and  spiritual  good 
ness,  for  conversion  and  renewal  both  for  ourselves  and 
others.  Our  very  moral  nature  thus  takes  us  out  of  ourselves 
to  God,  referring  us  to  Him  as  the  sole  and  meritorious 
cause  of  all  moral  action  ;  while  it  takes  upon  itself  the 
responsibility  of  sin.  This  constitutional  humility,  this 
fixed  tendency  of  our  minds  to  an  external  source  of  good, 
expressed  in  the  formal  language  of  theology,  becomes  the 
doctrine  of  irresistible  grace,  from  which  that  of  predestina 
tion  immediately  follows.  But  is  there  not  a  counter 
principle  to  this  co-existing  with  it  in  our  nature,  a  princi 
ple  of  self-appreciation  and  self-respect,  whereby  we  are  able 
to  contemplate  ourselves  as  original  agents  in  good  actions  ? 

Let  us  turn  now  from  philosophical  to  theological  pre 
destination,  or  to  the  doctrine  of  predestination  as  resting  on 
scriptural  grounds.  It  must,  I  think,  be  admitted  accord 
ing  to  the  argument  stated  in  the  last  chapter,  that  the 
predestinarian  draws  his  conclusion  naturally  from  the 
doctrine  of  original  sin  ;  while  at  the  same  time,  that 
conclusion  must  be  allowed  to  be  repugnant  to  natural 
reason  and  justice.  For  there  is  no  man  of  ordinary  moral 
perception,  who,  on  being  told  of  a  certain  doctrine  which 
represented  God  as  ordaining  one  man  to  eternal  life,  and 
ordaining  another  to  eternal  punishment,  be  fore  either  had 
done  a  single  act  or  was  born,  would  not  immediately  say 
that  God  was  represented  as  acting  unjustly.  There  re 
mains,  however,  for  extricating  us  from  this  dilemma  an 
examination  of  the  sense  and  manner  in  which  the  church 
imposes,  and  in  which  we  hold,  the  doctrine  of  original  sin. 

From  the  doctrine  of  the  fall,  then,  which  represents 
man  as  morally  impotent,  unable  by  nature  to  do  any  good 
thing,  a  lost  and  ruined  being,  the  conclusion  is  undoubtedly 
a  legitimate  one,  that  if  he  is  to  be  restored,  he  must  be 
restored  by  some  power  quite  independent  of  and  external 
to  him,  or  by  that  act  of  grace  which  divines  call  irre- 


CFAP.  ii.       Argument  for  Predestination.  31 

sistible.  But  to  what  kind  of  truth  does  the  doctrine  of 
the  fall  belong  ?  Tt  is  evident  on  the  mere  statement  of 
it,  that  it  is  not  a  truth  which  we  hold  in  the  same  manner 
in  which  we  do  the  ordinary  truths  of  reason  and  experience. 
Because  it  is  met  immediately  by  a  counter  truth.  Man 
kind  has  a  sense  of  moral  power,  of  being  able  to  do  good 
actions  and  avoid  wrong  ones,  which,  so  far  as  it  goes, 
contradicts  the  doctrine  of  the  fall.  For  so  far  as  it  is  true 
that  we  can  do  what  we  ought  to  do,  our  nature  is  not 
fallen ;  it  is  equal  to  the  task  imposed  upon  it ;  and  it  is 
our  own  personal  fault,  and  not  our  nature's,  if  it  is  not 
done.  The  conclusion,  then,  of  the  necessity  of  an  irre 
sistible  grace  to  produce  a  good  life,  has  in  the  doctrine  of 
the  fall  not  a  complete,  but  an  imperfect  premiss,  and 
must  follow  the  conditions  of  that  premiss.  The  doctrine 
of  the  fall  is  held  under  a  reserve  on  the  side  of  the  con 
trary  truth ;  the  doctrine  of  irresistible  grace,  then,  must 
be  held  under  the  same  reserve.  So  far  as  man  is  fallen, 
he  wants  this  grace  ;  but  so  far  as  he  is  not  fallen,  he  does 
not  want  it.  One  inference,  then,  from  one  part  of  the 
whole  premiss  lies  under  the  liability  to  be  contradicted  by 
another  from  another  part ;  and  the  legitimate  issue  is  no 
whole  or  perfect  conclusion,  but  only  a  conditional  and 
imperfect  one. 

The  predestinarian,  however,  neglects  this  distinction, 
and  upon  an  imperfect  basis  raises  a  definite  and  complete 
doctrine.  Or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  he  does  not  see 
that  the  basis  is  imperfect.  He  does  not  consent  to  hold 
ing  the  doctrine  of  the  fall  with  this  reserve,  but  imagines 
he  has  in  this  doctrine  a  complete  truth  ;  and  he  proceeds  to 
use  it  as  he  would  any  ordinary  premiss  of  reason  or  experi 
ence,  and  founds  a  perfect  argumentative  structure  upon  it. 

Thus  much  for  the  structure  of  the  doctrine  of  predes 
tination,  as  raised  on  the  basis  of  original  sin.  And  the 
same  answer  may  be  made  to  the  defence  of  the  justice  of 
the  doctrine  on  the  same  ground  ;  to  the  argument  that, 
inasmuch  as  all  mankind  deserve  eternal  punishment  ante 
cedently  to  actual  sin,  it  cannot  be  unjust  to  consign  a 
portion  of  them  antecedently  to  it. 


Examination  of  the 


CHAP.  n. 


Undoubtedly  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  represents  the 
whole  human  race  as  subject  to  the  extreme  severity  of 
Divine  wrath  in  consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam.  It  has 
two  ways  or  forms  in  which  it  represents  this.  The  doctrine 
is  sometimes  so  expressed  as  to  represent  mankind  as  being 
actually  parties  to  the  sin  committed  by  Adam,  and  so 
condemned,  on  a  principle  of  natural  justice,  for  a  sin 
which  is  their  own.  All  men  are  said  to  have  sinned  in 
Adam,  and  Adam,  or  the  old  man,  is  spoken  of  as  the  root 
or  principle  of  evil  in  every  human  being.  Sometimes  it 
is  so  expressed  as  to  represent  mankind  as  punished,  on  a 
principle  of  vicarious  desert,  for  the  sin  of  their  first  parent, 
regarded  as  another  person  from  themselves.1  But  which 
ever  of  these  two  modes  of  stating  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin  is  adopted,  it  is  evident  that  in  dealing  with  it,  we  are 
dealing  with  a  mystery,  not  with  an  ordinary  truth  of 
reason  and  nature.  If  we  adopt  the  former  mode,  it  is 
contradictory  to  common  reason,  according  to  which  one 
man  cannot  be  thus  the  same  with  another,  and  commit  a 
sin  before  he  is  born.  If  we  adopt  the  latter,  it  is  contra 
dictory  to  our  sense  of  justice,  according  to  which  one  man 
ought  not  to  be  punished  for  another  man's  sin.  Under 
either  form,  then,  we  are  dealing  with  a  mystery,  and  that 
which  is  described  in  this  doctrine  as  having  taken  place 
with  respect  to  mankind,  has  taken  place  mysteriously,  not 
after  the  manner  of  common  matter  of  fact. 

And  this  distinction,  it  must  be  observed,  is  necessary 
not  only  to  guard  what  we  build  upon  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin,  but  for  the  defence  of  the  doctrine  itself.  This 
doctrine  is  sometimes  called  an  unjust  one,  and  this  charge 
of  injustice  is  sometimes  met  by  an  attempt  to  reduce  and 
qualify  the  statement  itself  of  the  doctrine  ;  as  if  it  attri- 

1  Quantomagis  prohiberi  [a  bap-  propna  sed  aliena  peccata  (Cyprian, 

tismo]  non  debet  [infans]qui  recens  Ep.  ad  Fidum,  64.  ed.  Oxon.)     The 

natus  nib.il  peccavit,  nisi  quod  se-  more  common  and  recognised  mode 

cundum  Adam  carnaliter  natus  con-  however  of  expressing  the  doctrine 

tagium  mortis  antiques  prima  nativi-  is  that  which  represents  mankind  as 

tate  eontraxit,  qui  ad  remissam  pec-  having  sinned  in  Adam,  and  having 

catorum  accipiendamhocipsofacilius  been  parties  in  the  act.  —  NOTE  VI. 
accedit,   quod  illi  remittuntur  non 


CHAP.  IT.       Argument  for  Predestination.  33 

buted  only  negative  consequences  to  the  sin  of  Adam — a 
loss  of  perfection,  a  withdrawal  of  some  supernatural  aids. 
But  such  a  qualification  of  the  doctrine  is  contrary  to  the 
plain  language  of  Scripture,  as  well  as  that  of  catholic 
writers.  The  proper  defence  of  the  doctrine  is  not  a  limi 
tation  of  its  statements,  but  a  distinction  as  to  the  sense 
in  which  these  statements  are  to  be  held.  When  this 
distinction  has  been  drawn,  objectors  may  exhibit  as  forci 
bly  and  vividly  as  they  will  the  paradoxical  nature  of  these 
statements  ;  they  gain  nothing  by  doing  so.  We  may  be 
asked  how  it  is  possible  that  (rod  should  be  angry  with 
innocent  infants,  should  condemn  persons  before  they  are 
born  to  the  torments  of  hell  and  other  like  questions ;  but 
with  the  aid  of  this  distinction  it  is  easy  to  see  that  such 
objections  suppose  an  entirely  different  mode  of  holding 
such  statements  from  that  which  every  reasonable  believer 
adopts.  We  are  not  to  measure  these  mysterious  conse 
quences  of  the  sin  of  Adam  by  human  analogies,  as  if  the 
act  of  Grod  in  visiting  the  sin  of  Adam  upon  all  mankind 
were  like  the  act  of  a  human  monarch  who  punished  a 
whole  family  or  nation  for  the  crime  of  one  man.  They 
are  of  the  order  of  mysterious  truths,  and  represent  modes 
of  Divine  dealing  which  are  beyond  the  sphere  of  our 
reason.1 

Upon  the  premiss,  then,  contained  in  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin,  that  all  mankind  deserve  eternal  punishment 
antecedently  to  actual  sin,  it  is  correctly  argued  that  it 
cannot  be  unjust  to  consign  a  portion  antecedently  to  it. 

1  Le  peche  originel  est  folie  de-  bien  loin  de  1'inventer  par  ses  voies, 

vant  les  homines;  mais  on  le  donne  s'en  eloigne  quand  on  lelui  presente. 

pour  tel.  Vous  ne  me  devez  done  — Pascal  (ed.  Fauge:es),  v.  ii.  p.  106. 
pas  reprocher  le  defaut  de  raison  en  Nous  ne  concevons  ni  1'etat  glo- 

cette  doctrine,  puisque  je  le  donne  rieux  d'Adam,  ni  la  nature  de  son 

pour  etre  sans  raison.     Mais  cette  peche,  ni  la  transmission  qui  s'en  est 

foiie  est  plus  sage  que  toute  la  sa-  faite  en  nous.     Ce  sont  choses  qui  se 

gesse   des   homines  ;    sapientius  est  sont  passees  dans  I'&tat  d'une  nature 

hominibus.    Car,  sans  cela,  que  dira-  toute  differente  de  la  notre,   et  qui 

t-on  qu'est  l'homme  ?    Tout  son  6tat  passent  notre  capacit6  presente. — p. 

depend  de  ce  point   imperceptible.  369. 

Et  comment  s'en  fut-il  aper9u  par  sa  Jeremy  Taylor  loses  sight  of  this 

raison,  puisque  c'est  une  chose  au-  principle  of  interpretation  in  his  ar- 

dessus  de  sa  raison  ;  et  que  sa  raison,  gument  on  Original  Sin. — NOTE  VII. 


-4  Examination  of  the  CHAP.  ir. 

But  it  must  be  remembered  what  kind  of  a  premiss  this  is. 
If  it  is  a  truth  of  revelation  that  all  men  deserve  eternal 
punishment  in  consequence  of  the   sin  of  Adam,  it  is  a 
truth  of  our  moral  nature  equally  certain,  that  no  man 
deserves  punishment  except  for  his  own  personal  sin.   And 
the  one  is  declared  in  revelation  itself  as  plainly  as  the 
other ;  for  it  is  said,  <  The  soul  that  sinneth,  it   shall  die  : 
the  son  shall  not  bear  the  iniquity  of  the   father,  neither 
shall  the  father  bear  the  iniquity  of  the  son  ;  the  righteous 
ness  of  the  righteous  shall  be  upon  him,  and  the  wicked 
ness  of  the  wicked  shall  be  upon  him.' '     It  is  a  truth, 
then,  of  reason  and  Scripture  alike  that  no  man  is  respon 
sible  for  another's  sin  :  and  so  far  as  this  is  true  at  all,  it 
is   universally   true,2   applying  as  much  to  the    case  of 
Adam's  sin,  as  to  that  of  any  other  man.    For  though  God 
suspends  the  operation  of  general  laws  on  occasions,  such 
laws  are  only  modes  of  proceeding  in  the  physical  world. 
Moral  truths  do  not  admit  of  exceptions.     The  premiss, 
then,  on  which  we  proceed  in  this  question  is  a  divided 
one  ;  and  if  the  predestinarian  from  one  part  of  it  concludes 
the  justice  of  his  doctrine,  his  opponent  can,  from  the 
other,  conclude  the    contrary.      If  the    mystery    of  our 
responsibility  for  the  sin  of  Adam  justifies  his  scheme,  the 
truth  of  our  exclusive  responsibility  for  our  own  sins  con 
demns  it. 

Both  in  structure  and  defences,  then,  the  doctrine  of 
predestination  rests  on  an  imperfect  premiss,  and  can  only 

1  Ezek.  xviii.  20.  our  father's  sins  to  us,  unto  eternal 

2  Jeremy  Taylor's  argument  is       damnation  ;  and  is  it  otherwise  in 
sound  so  far  as  he  insists  that  the       this  only?' — Vol.  ix.  p.  383. 

case  of  original  sin  should  not  be  It  is  evidently  wrong  to  treat  the 

treated  as  an  exception  to  God's  or-  case  of  original  sin  as  an  exception, 

dinary  justice.     *  When  your  lord-  in  one  particular  instance,  to  God's 

ship  had  said  that  "my  arguments  ordinary  justice;  for  there  can  be 

for  the  vindication  of  God's  goodness  no  justifiable  exception  to  the  rule 

and  justice  are  sound  and  holy,"  your  of  justice.     All  God's  acts  must  be 

hand  run  over  it  again,  and  added  just.     It  must  be  treated  as  a  mys- 

"  as  abstracted  from  the  case  of  ori-  tery,  something  unknown,  and  against 

ginal  sin."     But  why  should  this  be  which,  on  that  account,  we  can  bring 

abstracted  from  all  the  whole  eco-  no  charge  of  injustice.     For  before 

nomy  of  God,   from  all  His  other  we  can  call  an  act  unjust,  we  must 

dispensations  ?     Is  it  in  all  cases  of  know  what  the  act  is. 
the  world  unjust  for  God  to  impart 


CHAP.  n.       Argument  for  Predestination.  35 

be  held  as  imperfect  truth  ;  for  we  cannot  build  more  upon 
a  basis  than  it  can  bear,  and  from  what  is  conditional  and 
incomplete  extract  what  is  absolute  and  determinate.  But 
the  predestinarian  holds  the  premiss  itself  as  complete  and 
perfect,  overlooking  the  contrary  one  to  which  it  is  opposed  ; 
and  therefore  raises  upon  it  a  complete  and  determinate 
doctrine.  He  does  not  consider,  in  the  first  instance,  that 
the  fall  of  man  is,  however  clearly  revealed  to  us,  but  one 
side  of  the  whole  truth  as  regards  human  nature ;  that  it 
is  mysterious,  as  distinguished  from  intelligible  truth.  He 
should  revise  the  whole  sense  and  manner  in  which  he  holds 
this  doctrine. 

To  turn  from  reasoning  to  Scripture.  Predestination 
comes  before  us  in  Scripture  under  two  aspects,  as  a  truth 
or  doctrine,  and  as  a  feeling,  and  under  both  the  conclusion 
is  of  that  indeterminate  character  which  has  been  described 
here  as  its  proper  and  legitimate  one. 

1.  The  general  conclusion  of  Scripture  on  this  question, 
considered  as  a  question  of  abstract  truth,  is  indeterminate. 
There  exists  undoubtedly  in  Scripture,  as  was  observed  in 
the  last  chapter,  a  large  body  of  language  in  which  man  is 
spoken  of  as  a  lost  and  ruined  creature,  and  impotent  by 
nature  for  good.  And  in  this  state  he  is  pronounced  to  be 
saved  by  an  act  of  Divine  grace  alone.  And  this  language, 
as  has  been  explained,  is  substantially  the  assertion  of  pre 
destination  ;  because  we  have  only  to  add  to  it  the  acknow 
ledged  truth  of  God's  eternal  predetermination  of  all  His 
acts,  in  order  to  make  it  such.  And  in  addition  to  this 
general  body  of  language,  particular  passages  (such,  espe 
cially,  as  the  eighth  and  ninth  chapters  of  the  Epistle  to 
the  Komans)  assert  the  express  doctrine  of  predestination 
in  such  a  way  that  we  cannot  escape  from  their  force  except 
by  a  subtle  and  evasive  mode  of  explanation,  which  would 
endanger  the  meaning  of  all  Scripture.  The  terms  elect 
and  predestinated  in  Scripture  mean,  according  to  their 
natural  interpretation,  persons  who  have  been  chosen  by 
God  from  all  eternity  to  be  called,  justified,  or  made  righ 
teous,  and  finally  glorified.1  But  Scripture  is  two-sided  OP 

1  NOTE  VIII. 

D  2 


36  Examination  of  the CHAP.  IT. 

this  great  question.  If  one  set  of  passages,  taken  in  their 
natural  meaning,  conveys  the  doctrine  of  predestination, 
another  conveys  the  reverse.  The  Bible,  in  speaking  of 
mankind,  and  addressing  them  on  their  duties  and  respon 
sibilities,  certainly  speaks  as  if  all  had  the  power  to  do 
their  duty  or  not,  when  laid  before  them  ;  nor  would  any 
plain  man  receive  any  other  impression  from  this  language, 
than  that  the  moral  being  had  freewill,  and  could  determine 
his  own  acts  one  way  or  another.  So  that,  sometimes 
speaking  one  way,  and  sometimes  another,  Scripture,  as  a 
whole,  makes  no  assertion,  or  has  no  determinate  doctrine 
on  this  subject. 

To  some  persons,  perhaps,  such  an  estimate  of  the 
general  issue  of  Scripture  language  on  this  subject  may 
seem  derogatory  to  Holy  Scripture  ;  because  it  appears,  at 
first  sight,  to  be  casting  blame  upon  language,  to  say  that 
it  is  self-contradictory;  the  form  of  such  an  assertion 
suggesting  that  the  expression  of  something  definite  was 
aimed  at,  but  that  the  language  fell  short  of  its  aim.  But 
it  will  not,  upon  consideration,  be  found  that  any  such 
consequence  attaches  to  this  estimate  of  Scripture  language. 
For  though  Scripture  is  certainly  said  not  to  be  consistent, 
and,  therefore,  not  to  give  support  to  a  determinate  doctrine 
of  predestination,  it  is  not  said  that  the  expression  of  any 
determinate  doctrine  was  designed.  And,  therefore,  the 
assertion  made  is  not  that  Scripture  has  fallen  short  of  an 
object  which  it  aimed  at ;  rather,  it  is  quite  consistent  with 
Scripture  having  most  completely  and  successfully  attained 
its  object. 

Were  the  nature  of  all  truth  such  as  that  it  could  be 
expressed — that  is,  put  into  statement  or  proposition,  to 
the  effect  that  such  is  or  is  not  the  case,  explicitness  and 
consistency  would  be  always  requisite  for  language ;  because 
real  expression  is  necessarily  explicit  and  consistent  with 
itself.  All  intelligible  truths— matters  of  fact,  for  example 
— are  capable  of  expression ;  and  therefore,  in  the  case  of 
such  truths,  explicit  statement  is  necessary,  and  contradic 
tion  is  ruinous.  But  it  is  not  the  case  that  all  truth  can 
be  expressed.  Some  truths  of  revealed  religion  cannot  be 


CHAP.  ir.        Argument  for  Predestination.  37 

stated  without  contradiction  to  other  truths,  of  which 
reason  or  the  same  revelation  informs  us,  and,  therefore, 
cannot  be  stated  positively  and  absolutely  without  be 
coming,  in  the  very  act  of  statement,  false. 

The  truth  of  absolute  predestination  cannot  be  stated 
without  contradiction  to  the  Divine  justice  and  man's  free 
agency.  It  belongs,  then,  to  that  class  of  truths  which 
does  not  admit  of  statement.  It  is  an  imperfect  truth — 
that  is,  a  truth  imperfectly  apprehended  by  us.  There  is 
a  tendency,  as  has  been  said,  to  a  truth  on  this  subject, 
but  this  tendency  never  becomes  a  conclusion  ;  and  an  idea 
which  is  true,  as  far  as  it  does  advance,  never  does  advance 
to  any  natural  limit.  The  intellect  stops  short  and  rests 
in  suspense,  not  seeing  its  way,  and  the  line  of  thought, 
though  it  may  admit  of  such  a  completion  as  will  make  it 
a  truth,  is  not  a  truth  yet.  and  cannot  be  made  a  propo 
sition. 

But  with  respect  to  this  kind  of  truth  which  is  only 
in  tendency,  and  does  not  admit  of  statement,  if  anything 
is  to  be  said  at  all,  such  contradictory  or  double  language 
only  can  be  employed  as  Scripture  does  employ  on  the 
subject  of  predestination.  Consistent  language  would  do 
more  than,  indeed  the  very  reverse  of  what  was  wanted, 
inasmuch  as  it  would  state  positively.  Inconsistency  could 
certainly  be  avoided  by  saying  nothing  at  all,  but  that 
mode  of  avoiding  inconsistency  could  not  be  adopted  here, 
because  there  is  a  defective  and  incomplete  truth  to  be 
expressed  in  some  such  way  as  is  practicable.  Something, 
therefore,  is  to  be  said.  But  to  say  something,  and  yet  on 
the  whole  to  make  no  positive  statement,  to  express  suit 
ably  such  indeterminate  truth,  what  is  to  be  done  but  first 
to  assert  the  truth  and  then  by  counter  statement  to  bring 
round  indefiniteness  again  ;  thus  carrying  thought  a  certain 
way  without  bringing  it  to  any  goal,  and  giving  an  incli 
nation  and  a  direction  to  ideas  without  fixing  them. 

2.  Predestination  comes  before  us  in  Scripture  as  a 
feeling  or  impression  upon  the  mind  of  the  individual. 
All  conscious  power,  strength,  energy,  when  combined  with 
a  particular  aim,  tend  to  create  the  sense  of  a  destiny — 


3  8  Examination  of  the  CHAP.  IT. 

an  effect  with  which  we  are  familiar  in  the  case  of  many 
remarkable  persons.  A  man  who  feels  in  himself  the 
presence  of  great  faculties  which  he  applies  to  the  attain 
ment  of  some  great  object,  not  unnaturally  interprets  the 
very  greatness  of  these  faculties  as  a  providential  call  to 
such  an  application  of  them,  and  a  pledge  and  earnest  of  a 
successful  issue.  Thus,  in  proportion  to  the  very  strength 
and  energy  of  his  own  will,  he  regards  himself  as  but  a 
messenger  from,  an  instrument  of,  a  Higher  Power ;  he 
sees  in  himself  but  a  derived  agency,  an  impulse  from 
without.  It  seems  necessary  that  he  should  refer  those 
extraordinary  forces,  which  he  feels  working  within  him, 
to  some  source  beyond  the  confines  of  his  own  narrow 
existence,  and  connect  them  with  the  action  of  the  invisible 
Supreme  Power  in  the  universe.  He  is  in  a  sense,  in  which 
other  persons  are  not,  a  mystery  to  himself ;  and  to  account 
for  so  much  power  in  so  small  and  frail  a  being,  he  refers 
it  to  the  unknown  world  in  which  reside  the  causes  of  all 
the  great  operations  of  nature.  This  is  the  way  in  which 
he  expresses  his  own  sense  and  consciousness  of  remarkable 
powers ;  he  would  have  regarded  an  ordinary  amount  of 
power  as  his  own,  but  because  he  has  so  much  more,  he 
alienates  it,  and  transfers  it  to  a  source  beyond  himself. 
Thus  heroes  and  conquerors  in  heathen  times  have  some 
times  even  imagined  themselves  to  be  emanations  from 
the  Deity.  But  a  common  result  has  been  the  idea  of  a 
destiny,  which  they  have  had  to  fulfil.  And  this  idea  of  a 
destiny  once  embraced,  as  it  is  the  natural  effect  of  the 
sense  of  power,  so  in  its  turn  adds  greatly  to  it.  The  per 
son  as  soon  as  he  regards  himself  as  predestined  to  achieve 
some  great  object,  acts  with  so  much  greater  force  and 
constancy  for  the  attainment  of  it ;  he  is  not  divided  by 
doubts,  or  weakened  by  scruples  or  fears ;  he  believes  fully 
that  he  shall  succeed,  and  that  belief  is  the  greatest  assist 
ance  to  success.  The  idea  of  a  destiny  in  a  considerable 
degree  fulfils  itself. 

The  idea  of  destiny,  then,  naturally  arising  out  of  a 
sense  of  power,  it  must  be  observed  that  this  is  true  of  the 
moral  and  spiritual,  as  well  as  of  the  natural  man,  and, 


CHAP.  ii.        Argument  for  Predestination.  39 

applies  to  religious  aims  and  purposes,  as  well  as  to  those 
connected  with  human  glory.  A  strong  will  in  moral  things, 
a  determination  to  resist  the  tendencies  of  corrupt  nature, 
a  sustained  aim  at  the  perfect  life — this  whole  disposition 
of  mind  does,  if  recognised  and  contemplated  in  himself  by 
the  possessor,  in  proportion  to  its  extent  create  a  sense  of  a 
spiritual  destiny  ;  and  the  Christian  in  his  own  sphere,  as 
the  great  man  of  the  world  in  his,  feels  himself  marked  out 
for  a  particular  work  and  the  final  reward  which  is  to  follow 
it.  According  to  his  calculation  of  his  resources  is  his 
conviction  that  he  shall  attain  his  object ;  and  from  the 
calculation  that  ne  will,  the  sense  that  he  is  destined  to 
succeed,  almost  immediately  arises.  Not  that  this  result 
need  take  place  in  all  Christian  minds,  for  there  are  dif 
ferences  of  natural  character  as  well  as  of  moral  power 
which  would  affect  it.  Some  minds  are  constitutionally 
more  self-contemplative  than  others,  and  have  before  them 
their  own  condition  and  prospects,  while  others  pursue  the 
same  actual  course  with  less  of  reflection  upon  themselves 
as  agents.  So  far,  however,  as  a  man  thinks  definitely  of 
himself  and  of  his  own  spiritual  strength,  and  so  far  as  the 
result  of  the  inspection  is  satisfactory,  this  will  be  the 
result.  He  perceives  in  himself  now  that  which  must 
ultimately  overcome,  and  looks  forward  to  the  issue  as  to 
the  working  out  of  a  problem,  the  natural  fruit  of  moral 
resources  already  in  his  possession.  Nor  need  this  result 
be  confined  to  remarkable  and  eminent  Christians.  What 
ever  be  the  degree  and  standard  of  goodness  before  the 
mind,  so  far  as  a  man  definitely  recognises  in  himself  the 
capacity  for  attaining  it,  so  far  he  will  have  the  sense  of 
being  marked  out  for  its  attainment. 

And  it  is  evident  that  one  whole  side  of  Scripture  en 
courages  Christians  in  this  idea.  In  the  first  place,  without 
imposing  as  necessary,  Scripture  plainly  sanctions  and  en 
courages  that  character  of  mind  which  is  self-contemplative, 
or  involves  reflection  upon  self,  our  own  spiritual  state  and 
capacities.  The  more  childlike  temper  has  doubtless  its 
own  praise  ;  but  the  other  is  also  set  forth  in  Scripture  as  a 
temper  eminently  becoming  a  Christian.  Indeed,  placed  as 


4Q  Examination  of  the  CHAP.  n. 

we  are  here,  with  an  unknown  future  before  us,  of  good  or 
evil,  and  possessed  by  nature  of  the  strongest  self-love  and 
desire  for  our  own  ultimate  good,  is  it  to  be  said  for  a 
moment,  that  we  ought  not  to  think  of  ourselves,  our  pro 
spects,  the  object  of  our  existence,  and  our  amount  of  re 
sources,  the  degree  of  our  strength  and  ability  to  achieve 
it  ?  Certainly,  such  a  consideration  is  highly  befitting  our 
state,  and  suitable  to  a  Christian  man.  And  accordingly 
the  New,  as  distinguished  from  the  Old  Testament,  appears 
specially  to  encourage  this  peculiar  tone  of  mind,  and  to 
direct  men  more  to  reflection  upon  themselves  ;  it  recom 
mends  a  grave  foresight,  a  prudential  regard  to  our  own 
ultimate  happiness;  it  promotes  a  deep  moral  self-interested- 
ness  and  spirit  of  calculation.  The  eye  of  the  soul  is  turned 
inward  upon  itself  to  think  of  its  own  value,  and  estimate 
its  own  capacities,  and  prospects.  '  Which  of  you  intending 
to  build  a  tower,  sitteth  not  down  first  and  counteth  the 
cost,  whether  he  have  sufficient  to  finish  it  ?  Or  what  king 
going  to  war  with  another  king,  sitteth  not  down  first  and 
consult eth  whether  he  be  able  with  ten  thousand  to  meet 
him  that  cometh  against  him,  with  twenty  thousand.'  l 
But  if  a  man  makes  the  estimate  which  is  here  recom 
mended  to  him,  and  if  he  conscientiously  finds  it  a  favour 
able  one — i.e.  if  he  feels  himself  possessed  of  strong  moral 
purpose  and  will,  what  is  to  prevent  him  from  thinking 
that  he  is  destined  to  the  end,  with  a  view  to  which  the 
estimate  is  made?  That  he  is  marked  out  by  Providence 
to  build  this  tower  and  conquer  this  foe  ?  History  and 
experience  show,  that  the  human  mind  is  so  constituted  as 
to  receive  this  impression. 

Accordingly,  Christians  are  addressed  in  the  New  Tes 
tament  upon  this  supposition.  It  is  one  of  the  first  lessons 
which  the  Gospel  teaches  us,  that  the  ends  which  earthly 
greatness  proposes  to  itself,  are  but  shadows  of  those  to 
which  Christians  are  called  ;  that  the  conquest  of  sin  is  the 
true  glory  of  man,  and  the  heavenly  his  true  crown.  The 
Christian,  therefore,  is  addressed  as  one  predestined  to 
eternal  glory.  He  is  encouraged  to  regard  himself  as  a 
1  Lukexiv.  28,  31. 


CHAP.  ir.        Argument  for  Predestination.  41 

favourite  of  Heaven  singled  out  from  the  world,  and 
stamped  from  the  very  commencement  of  his  course,  with 
the  token  of  future  triumph.  The  resolution  to  obtain  the 
spiritual  crown  is  supposed  to  impart  to  him  the  same 
sense  of  a  destiny,  that  the  consciousness  of  a  commanding 
mind  imparts  to  the  man  of  the  world  ;  and  the  life  eternal 
is  represented  as  an  end  assured  to  the  individual  before 
the  foundation  of  the  world.  His  life  in  this  world  is  de 
scribed  as  a  passage,  laborious  and  painful  indeed,  but  still 
conducting  him  by  a  sure  succession  of  steps  to  this  end. 
It  obstructs  and  postpones  rather  than  involves  any  real 
hazard  to  his  spiritual  prospects  ;  the  goal  is  pledged,  and 
he  has  only  to  go  forward  till  he  reaches  it,  putting  aside 
the  hindrances  as  they  arise.  Life  is  to  him  a  purgatorial 
rather  than  a  trial  state,  purifying  him  by  affliction,  and 
exercising  him  by  conflicts,  through  all  which,  however,  he 
passes  steadily  onward  with  the  seal  of  God  upon  him, 
marking  him  infallibly  from  the  very  beginning  as  His 
own.  Nor  is  this  position  confined  to  a  few  eminent  saints, 
but  supposed  to  be  the  position  of  all  Christians,  who, 
whatever  be  the  differences  among  themselves,  are  all  saints 
in  comparison  with  the  world  around  them.  This  is  the 
natural  construction  of  the  language  of  S.  Paul ;  and  as 
this  idea  of  a  destiny  is  the  result  of,  so  in  its  turn  it 
strengthens,  the  moral  energies  of  the  Christian.  The 
conviction  that  he  is  marked  out  for  a  heavenly  crown, 
elevates  and  inspires  him  in  the  pursuit  of  it. 

This  is  '  the  godly  consideration  of  predestination,'  re 
commended  in  the  seventeenth  Article  of  our  Church.  The 
sense  of  predestination  which  the  New  Testament  en 
courages  is  connected  with  strength  of  moral  principle  in 
the  individual ;  the  Christian  being  supposed  always  to  be 
devoted  to  his  calling,  so  much  so  that  he  is  even  by  anti 
cipation  addressed  as  if  he  were  dead  to  carnal  desires,  and 
in  the  enjoyment  of  the  new  and  heavenly  life.  But  no  idea 
can  be  more  opposed  to  Scripture,  or  more  unwarrantable, 
than  any  idea  of  predestination  separated  from  this  con 
sciousness,  and  not  arising  upon  this  foundation  ;  the  notion 
x>f  the  individual  that,  on  the  simple  condition  which  he 


42  Examination  of  the  CHAP.  n. 

cannot  violate,  that  of  being  the  particular  person  which 
he  is,  he  is  certain  of  salvation.  It  is  not  to  the  person 
simply  as  such,  but  to  the  person  as  good  and  holy,  that 
eternal  life  is  ordained.  Does  a  man  do  his  duty  to  God 
and  his  neighbour  ?  Is  he  honest,  just,  charitable,  pure  ? 
If  he  is,  and  if  he  is  conscious  of  the  power  to  continue  so, 
so  far  as  he  can  depend  on  this  consciousness,  so  far  he  may 
reasonably  believe  himself  to  be  predestined  to  future  hap 
piness.  But  to  suppose  that  a  man  may  think  himself 
predestined,  not  as  being  good,  but  as  being,  whether  good 
or  bad,  himself,  is  a  delusion  of  the  devil,  and  the  gross 
fallacy  of  corrupt  sects,  that  have  lost  sight,  first  of  duty, 
and  next  of  reason,  and  have  forgotten  that  the  government 
of  the  world  is  moral.  The  doctrine  of  predestination  is 
thus,  in  effect,  a  profitable  or  a  mischievous  doctrine, 
according  to  the  moral  condition  of  those  who  receive  and 
use  it.  It  binds  and  cements  some  minds,  it  relaxes  and 
corrupts  others.  It  gives  an  energy  to  some,  a  new  force 
of  will,  bringing  out  and  strengthening  high  aims;  it 
furnishes  an  excuse  to  others,  already  disinclined  to  moral 
efforts,  to  abandon  them,  and  follow  their  own  worldly  will 
and  pleasure. 

The  above  remarks  will  supply  a  ground  for  judging  of 
the  doctrine  of  assurance  ;  assurance  being  nothing  else  but 
the  sense  of  predestination  here  spoken  of.  It  is  evident, 
in  the  first  place,  that  assurance  ought  not  to  be  demanded 
as  a  state  of  mind  necessary  for  a  Christian  ;  for  it  can 
only  arise  legitimately  upon  a  knowledge  of  our  own  moral 
resources  and  strength  ;  and  there  is  nothing  to  compel  a 
Christian  to  have  this  knowledge.  He  may  innocently  be 
without  it.  He  may  do  his  duty  without  reflecting  upon 
himself  as  an  agent  at  all ;  and  if  he  does  think  of  himself, 
he  may  innocently  make  an  erroneous  estimate  of  his  own 
strength.  It  sometimes  happens  that  at  the  time  of  trial 
a  man  finds  that  he  has  more  strength  than  he  counted 
upon,  and  is  surprised  at  his  own  easy  victory.  Nor  should 
it  be  forgotten  that  the  principle  of  humility  in  man  is  one 
which  tends  to  an  under-estimate  of  his  own  power  and 
resources ;  and  though  to  carry  it  to  this  extent  is  not  per- 


CHAI>.  ii.       Argument  for  Predestination.  43 

fection  in  respect  of  truth  and  knowledge,  yet  our  moral 
nature  is  so  fine  and  intricate,  that  it  must  be  owned  that, 
in  the  case  of  many  minds,  there  is  a  sort  of  perfection  in 
this  very  imperfection  :  and  one  would  not  wish  them  to 
estimate  themselves  correctly ;  if  they  did,  we  should  feel 
the  absence  of  something,  and  a  certain  indefinable  grace 
which  attached  to  them  would  be  missed.  This  is  one  of 
those  results  which  flow  from  the  variety  which  marks  the 
Divine  creation  and  constitution  of  the  world,  whether 
physical  or  moral.  Some  characters  are  designed  to  raise 
our  affections  on  one  plan,  others  on  another ;  some  are 
formed  to  inspire  what  is  commonly  called  love,  others 
respect,  principally  ;  both  being  only  different  forms  of  the 
scriptural  principle  of  love.  These  are  diversities  of  His 
instituting  who  is  Himself  incomprehensible,  and  who  has 
made  man  a  type  in  some  measure  of  Himself;  with  a 
moral  nature  which  cannot  be  reduced  to  one  criterion  of 
right,  but  which  attains  perfection  in  different  forms,  and 
satisfies  our  moral  sense,  under  modes  which  we  cannot 
analyse,  but  to  which  that  moral  sense  responds.  For 
human  goodness  is  not  a  simple  thing,  but  a  complex  ;  nor 
is  it  a  measurable,  but  an  indefinable  thing ;  attaining  its 
perfection  often  by  seeming  excesses,  incorrectnesses  in  the 
latter,  and  faults  transmuted  by  the  medium  of  the  general 
character  into  virtues.  The  stronger  mind  confides  in,  the 
more  amiable  one  distrusts,  itself.  Both  are  good  accord 
ing  to  their  respective  standards,  and  therefore,  on  a  prin 
ciple  of  variety,  such  difference  is  desirable.  It  is  desirable 
also,  on  another  ground — viz.  that  different  instruments 
are  wanted  by  Providence  to  execute  its  designs  in  the 
world.  Large  and  difficult  objects  can  only  be  achieved  by 
men  who  have  confidence  in  themselves,  and  will  not  allow 
obstacles  to  discourage  them  ;  and  a  sense  of  destiny  helps 
these  men.  The  tie,  on  the  other  hand,  of  mutual  confi 
dence,  is  aided  by  self-distrust.  Did  none  confide  in 
themselves,  there  would  be  none  to  command  ;  but  those 
who  do  so,  are  at  the  same  time  constitutionally  slow  to 
obey. 

Accordingly  the  doctrine  of  assurance  does  not  neces- 


44 


Examination  of  the 


CHAP.    II. 


sarily  go  along  with  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  because 
it  does  not  follow  that  if  a  particular  person  is  predestined 
to  eternal  life  that  therefore  he  should  have  the  inward 
sense  or  feeling  that  he  is.  The  Divine  decree  may  be 
conducting  him  by  sure  steps  all  his  life  through  to  final 
glory,  and  he  may  not  be  aware  of  it ;  for  the  only  condition 
necessary  to  being  one  of  the  elect,  is  goodness  ;  and  a  good 
man  may  act  without  contemplating  himself  at  all,  or,  if 
he  does,  he  may  distrust  himself.  Predestinarians  accord 
ingly,  both  Augustine  and  his  school,  and  modern  ones, 
have  disowned  the  doctrine  of  assurance,  so  far  as  it  is 
maintained  in  it  that  assurance  is  necessary  for  a  Christian.1 

Secondly,  assurance  separated  from  a  good  life,  and  the 
consciousness  of  resolution  to  persevere  in  it,  is  unreasonable 
and  wicked.  Thirdly,  assurance  united  with  both  of  these 
and  arising  upon  this  foundation,  is  legitimate. 

The  sense  or  feeling,  then,  of  predestination  is,  as  has 


1  As  to  what  follows  in  your  let 
ter,  concerning  a  person's  believing 
himself  to  be  in  a  good  state,  and  its 
being  properly  of  the  nature  of  faith; 
in  this  there  seems  to  be  some  real 
difference  between  us.  But  perhaps 
there  would  be  none,  if  distinctness 
were  well  observed  in  the  use  of 
words.  If  by  a  man's  believing  that 
he  is  in  a  good  estate,  be  meant  no 
more  that  his  believing  that  he  does 
believe  in  Christ,  love  God,  &c. ;  I 
think  there  is  nothing  of  the  nature 
of  faith  in  it ;  because  knowing  or 
believing  it  depends  on  our  imme 
diate  sensation  or  consciousness,  and 
not  on  Divine  testimony.  True  be 
lievers  in  the  hope  they  entertain  of 
salvation,  make  use  of  the  following 
syllogism,  whosoever  believes  shall  be 
saved.  I  believe,  therefore,  fyc.  As 
senting  to  the  major  proposition  is 
properly  of  the  nature  of  faith,  be 
cause  the  ground  of  my  assent  to 
that  is  Divine  testimony,  but  my  as 
sent  to  the  minor  proposition,  I 
humbly  conceive,  is  not  of  the  na 
ture  of  faith,  because  that  is  not 


grounded  on  Divine  testimony,  but  on 
my  own  consciousness.  The  testimony 
that  is  the  proper  ground  of  faith 
is  in  the  word  of  God,  Eom.  x.  17., 
'  Faith  cometh  of  hearing,  and  hear 
ing  of  the  word  of  God.'  There  is 
such  a  testimony  given  in  the  word 
of  God,  as  that  '  he  that  believeth 
shall  be  saved.'  But  there  is  no  such 
testimony  in  the  word  of  God,  as 
that  such  an  individual  person,  in 
such  a  town  in  Scotland  or  in  New 
England,  believes.  There  is  such  a 
proposition  in  Scripture,  as  that 
Christ  loves  those  that  love  Him,  and 
therefore  this  every  one  is  bound  to 
believe  or  affirm.  Believing  thus  on 
Divine  testimony  is  properly  of  the 
nature  of  faith,  and  for  any  one  to 
doubt  of  it,  is  properly  of  the  hein 
ous  sin  of  unbelief.  But  there  is  no 
such  proposition  in  the  Scripture, 
nor  is  it  any  part  of  the  gospel  of 
Christ,  that  such  an  individual  per 
son  in  Northampton  loves  Christ. — 
Edwards,  '  On  the  Eeligious  Affec  • 
tions,'  Letter  2.  to  Mr.  Gillespie. 


CHAP.  ii.       Argument  for  Predestination.  45 

been  shown,  both  sanctioned  and  encouraged  in  the  New 
Testament.  But  while  this  is  plain,  it  is  also  obvious  that 
this  is  only  one  side  of  the  language  of  the  New  Testament. 
There  is  another  according  to  which  all  Christians,  what 
ever  be  their  holiness,  are  represented  and  addressed  as 
uncertain,  and  feeling  themselves  uncertain,  of  fiDal  salva 
tion.  They  are  exhorted  to  '  work  out  their  own  salvation 
with  fear  and  trembling';1  to  'give  diligence  to  make 
their  calling  and  election  sure  ' ; 2  and  S.  Paul  himself  the 
great  preacher  of  predestination,  who,  if  any,  had  the  right 
to  feel  himself  ordained  to  eternal  life,  and  who  said  that 
there  '  was  laid  up  for  him  a  crown  of  righteousness,' 3  also 
tells  us  of  his  careful  self-discipline, '  lest  that  by  any  means 
when  he  had  preached  to  others,  he  himself  should  be  a 
castaway.' 4  Indeed  to  anyone  who  will  fairly  examine 
the  nature  of  this  feeling  of  destiny  which  we  have  been 
considering,  and  how  far  and  in  what  mode  it  is  entertained, 
when  it  is  entertained  rationally,  it  will  be  evident  that  it 
is  not  by  any  means  an  absolute  or  literal  certainty  of  mind. 
It  is  not  like  the  perception  of  an  intellectual  truth.  It  is 
only  a  strong  impression,  which  however  genuine  or  rational, 
and,  as  we  may  say,  authorised,  issues,  when  we  try  to  follow 
it,  in  obscurity,  and  vanishes  in  the  haze  which  bounds  our 
mental  view,  before  the  reason  can  overtake  it.  Were  any 
of  those  remarkable  men  who  have  had  it,  asked  about 
this  feeling  of  theirs,  they  would  confess  it  was  in  them  no 
absolute  perception  but  an  impression  which  was  consistent 
with  a  counter  feeling  of  doubt,  and  was  accompanied  by 
this  latent  and  suppressed  opposite  in  their  case. 

Whether  regarded,  then,  as  a  doctrine,  or  a  feeling, 
predestination  is  not  in  Scripture  an  absolute,  but  an  in 
definite  truth.  Scripture  has  as  a  whole  no  consistent 
scheme,  and  makes  no  positive  assertion ;  it  only  declares, 
and  bids  its  readers  acknowledge,  a  mystery  on  this  subject. 
It  sets  forth  alike  the  Divine  Power,  and  man's  freewill, 
and  teaches  in  that  way  in  which  alone  it  can  be  taught, 
the  whole,  and  not  a  part  alone  of  truth. 

1  Phil.  ii.  12.         2  2  Peter  i.  10.  s  2  Tim.  iv.  8.       «  1  Cor.  ix.  27. 


46  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CUAP.  m. 


CHAPTER   III. 

THE   PELAGIAN    CONTROVERSY. 

FROM  a  general  introductory  statement  and  examination  of 
the  argument  of  predestination,  I  turn  now  to  the  history 
and  formation  of  this  doctrine  as  exhibited  in  S.  Augustine's 
writings.  And  as  the  Augustinian  scheme  of  predestination 
rests  upon  the  basis  of  original  sin,  the  inquiry  will  suitably 
commence  with  an  account  of  the  latter  doctrine.  I  shall 
therefore  devote  the  present  chapter  to  a  general  sketch  of 
the  Pelagian  controversy  : — First,  the  mode  in  which  it 
arose  ;  secondly,  the  main  arguments  involved  in  it ;  and, 
thirdly,  its  bearing  upon  the  leading  doctrines  of  Christi 
anity.  Antagonist  systems  moreover  throw  light  upon  each 
other,  and  an  inquiry  into  the  doctrines  of  S.  Augustine 
will  be  aided  by  a  previous  account  of  the  system  of 
Pelagianism. 

I.  It  may  seem  at  first  sight  unnecessary  to  inquire  into 
the  mode  in  which  the  Pelagian  controversy  arose,  because 
it  appears  enough  to  say  that  one  side  maintained,  and  an 
other  denied,  the  fall  of  man.  But  the  doctrine  of  the  fall 
though  substantially,  did  not  expressly  or  by  name,  form 
the  original  subject  of  dispute,  but  was  led  up  to  by  a 
previous  question. 

It  has  been  disputed  whether  the  Augustinian  system 
was  a  reaction  from  the  Pelagian,  or  the  Pelagian  from 
the  Augustinian.  Historical  evidence  favours  the  latter 
assertion.1  But  the  dispute,  whichever  way  decided,  is  not 
an  important  one.  The  controversy  between  these  two  was 
contained  in  an  elementary  statement  of  Christian  doctrine, 
which,  as  soon  as  it  came  to  be  examined  intellectually, 
was  certain  to  disclose  it.  The  language  by  which  the 
Christian  church  has  always  expressed  the  truths  of  man's 
freewill  and  Divine  grace  has  been,  that  the  one  could  do 
no  good  thing  without  the  aid  of  the  other,  nihil  bonum 

1  NOTE  IX. 


CHAP.  nr.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  47 

sine  gratia.  This  formula  satisfied  the  simplicity  of  the 
primitive  church  as  it  has  satisfied  the  un  controversial  faith 
of  all  ages ;  and  no  desire  was  felt  for  further  expression 
and  a  more  exact  truth.  But  it  is  evident  that  this  state 
of  theology  on  this  subject  could  not  last  longer  than  the 
reign  of  a  simpler  faith.  When  minds  began  to  reason 
upon  this  formula  and  analyse  it  logically,  it  lost  its  finality, 
and  the  combination  of  grace  and  freewill  divided  into 
two  great  doctrines  of  an  absolute  power  of  freewill  and  an 
absolute  power  of  grace. 

For  was  the  grace  here  asserted  to  be  necessary  for  do 
ing  any  good  thing,  a  grace  which  assisted  only  the  human 
will  or  one  which  controlled  it  ?  If  it  was  the  former,  it 
depended  on  some  action  of  the  human  will  for  being 
accepted  and  used,  which  action  therefore  could  not  be  said 
without  contradiction  to  be  dependent  upon  it.  Assist 
ing  grace,  then,  must  be  used  by  an  unassisted  will,  and 
there  must  be  some  motion  of  the  human  will  for  good  to 
which  Divine  grace  did  not  contribute,  but  which  was 
original  and  independent  in  the  person  who  accepted  and 
availed  himself  of  that  grace.  Take  two  men  who  have 
both  equal  grace  given  to  them,  but  of  whom  one  avails 
himself  of  this  grace,  while  the  other  does  not.  The  differ 
ence  between  these  two  is  not  by  the  very  supposition,  a 
difference  of  grace ;  it  is  therefore  a  difference  of  original 
will  only ;  and  in  one  there  has  been  a  self-sprung,  inde 
pendent  act  for  good,  which  there  has  not  been  in  the  other. 
But  how  great,  how  eventful  a  function  thus  attached  to 
the  unassisted  human  will  ?  It  decided  the  life  and  con 
duct  of  the  man,  and  consequently  his  ultimate  lot,  for 
happiness  or  misery.  That  difference  between  one  man 
and  another  in  consequence  of  which  one  becomes  a  child 
of  God  and  daily  grows  in  virtue  and  holiness,  and  the 
other  becomes  a  servant  of  sin,  is  no  difference  into  which 
grace  even  enters,  but  one  of  natural  will  only.  Indeed, 
was  not  the  unassisted  human  will,  according  to  this  doc 
trine,  more  than  a  real  agent,  the  chief  agent  in  the  work 
of  virtue  and  piety  ?  For  the  general  sense  of  mankind 
has,  in  the  case  of  any  joint  agency,  assigned  the  part  of 


48  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  nr. 

chief  agent  to  the  one  that  uses  and  turns  to  account  the 
action  of  the  other.  If  one  man  furnishes  another  with 
the  means  and  resources  for  any  undertaking,  and  the  other 
applies  them  to  it,  both  indeed  COD  tribute  action ;  but  the 
latter  is  the  chief  contributor,  and  would,  in  ordinary 
language,  be  called  the  doer  of  the  work.  Thus  to  the 
act°of  learning  a  teacher  and  a  learner  both  contribute, 
the  one  by  giving  information,  the  other  by  apprehending 
it ;  but  the  act  of  learning  is  the  learner's  rather  than 
the  teacher's  act.  Apply  this  distinction  to  the  case  of 
the  human  will  using  the  assistance  of  Divine  grace  for  the 
work  of  a  holy  life.  While  the  giver  and  the  user  of  that 
assistance  are  both  agents  in  that  work,  the  user  is  the 
principal  one.1  In  cases  where  the  use  of  means,  if  sup 
plied,  takes  place  easily  and  as  a  matter  of  course,  the 
result  may  be  properly  referred  to  the  supplier  rather  than 
the  user  of  them.  But  the  act  of  the  will  in  using  grace 
is  no  easy  or  matter-of-course  one,  but  involves  much  effort 
and  self-denial. 

The  combination  of  grace  with  freewill  thus  issued  in 
the  assertion  of  an  independent  freewill  on  the  one  hand, 
while  this  logical  result  was  avoided  on  the  other,  only  by 
a  recourse  to  the  opposite  extreme.  It  was  seen  that  an 
assisting  grace  could  only  be  protected  by  making  it  some 
thing  more  than  assisting,  and  that  the  will  must  have  the 
credit  of  the  unassisted  acceptance  and  use  of  it,  unless  it 
were  controlled  by  it.  The  original  formula,  therefore, 
issued  on  this  side  in  the  doctrine  of  a  controlling  and 
irresistible  grace  ;  and  upon  these  two  interpretations  of  the 
primitive  doctrine  rose,  with  their  respective  accompani 
ments  and  consequences,  the  Pelagian  and  Augustinian 
systems. 

Pelagianism  then  started  with  the  position,  that,  how«- 
ever  necessary  Divine  assistance  might  be  for  a  good  work 
as  a  whole,  there  was  at  the  bottom  a  good  act  or  move- 

1  '  Nam  quando  ad  eundem  actum  tis,  sine  qua  non  potest  fieri,  sed  illi 

liberum  concurrunt  plura  sine  quibus  quse  nutu  suo  totam  machinam  ad 

libertas  agendi  in  actum  suum  exire  motum   impellit,    aut   otiosam   esse 

non   potest,   non   illi   causse   tribui  sinit.' — Jaiisen,  De  Grat.  Christi,  p. 

debet  exercitium  actus  aut  volunta-  935. 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  49 

ment,  which  the  human  will  was  able  to  and  must  perform 
without  Divine  assistance.  And  this  position  supplies  the 
clue  to  the  solution  of  the  Pelagian's  apparently  contradic 
tory  language  about  grace.  The  Pelagian  asserts  the  ability 
of  nature  at  one  time  ;  he  asserts  the  necessity  of  grace  at 
another.1  Now  his  opponent  explained  this  apparent  in 
consistency,  by  saying  tha.t  by  grace  he  meant  nature ;  that 
he  used  the  word  dishonestly  in  a  sense  of  his  own,  and 
only  included  in  it  the  natural  will  and  endowments  of 
man,  which,  as  being  Divine  gifts,  he  chose  to  call  gracs.2 
And,  in  the  same  way,  he  was  charged  with  meaning  by 
grace  only  the  outward  means  of  instruction  and  edifica 
tion,  whicli  (rod  had  given  to  man  in  the  Bible  and  else 
where,  as  distinct  from  any  inward  Divine  influence.  This 
is  the  explanation  of  the  Pelagian  grace,  as  Lex  et  Natura, 
which  we  meet  so  often  in  S.  Augustine.  But  with  all 
deference  to  so  great  a  name,  I  cannot  think  that  this 
adverse  explanation  is  altogether  justified  by  the  language 
of  the  Pelagians  themselves.  A  verbal  confusion  of  nature 
with  grace  is  undoubtedly  to  be  found  there  ;  nor  is  such 
a  confusion  in  itself  unpardonable.  In  one  sense  nature  is 
grace ;  freewill  itself,  and  all  the  faculties  and  affections  of 
our  nature  being  the  gifts  of  (rod ;  while,  on  the  other 
hand,  grace  may  not  erroneously  be  called  nature,  inas 
much  as  when  received,  it  becomes  a  power  which  we  have, 
and  which  belongs  to  us ;  especially  acting,  as  it  does,  too, 
through  the  medium  of  our  natural  faculties,  our  conscience, 
and  good  affections.  And  in  this  sense  of  nature,  the 
Pelagians  asserted  that  nature  was  able  to  fulfil  the  law — 
Posse  in  natura3 — a  statement,  which  so  understood,  is  no 

1  Anathemo   qui   yel   sentit  vel  effectu  locamus. — De  Grat.  Christi. 

dicit  gratiam  Dei   non   solum   per  n.  5. 

singulas  horas,  aut  per  singula  mo-  2  De  Natura  et  Gratia,  n.  12.  59. ; 

menta,  sed  ttiam  per  singulos  actus  De  Grat.  Christi,  n.  3. 

nostros    non    esse    necessariam. —  3  To  the  objection  of  the  Catholic, 

Pelagius  ap.  Aug.  De  Grat.  Christi,  '  Protest  quidern  esse,  sed  per  gra- 

n.  2.     He  repeats  the  same  state-  tiam  Dei,'  Pelagius  replies,  'Ego  ne 

ment  often. — De  Grat.  Christi,  n.  5.  abnuo  qui  rem  confifcendo,  confitear 

29.  33.;  Contra  Duas.  Ep.  1.  4.  n.  13.  necesse   est   et  per   quod  res  effici 

On  the  other  hand  he  says,  Passe  in  potest ;  an  tu  qui  rem  negan^o,  et 

naturd,   velle   in   arbitrio,    esse  in  quicquid   illud   est,   per    quod    res 


cO  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  JIT. 

more  than  a  truism;  nature  comprehending,  in  this  sense 
of  the  word,  all  the  moral  power,  from  whatever  quarter, 
of  which  a  man  is  possessed,  grace  included.  Again,  the 
Pelagian,  in  his  explanations  of  grace  and  its  operations, 
certainly  dwells  most  commonly  on  the  outward  helps  which 
revelation  and  Providence  afford  to  man  in  the  path  of 
obedience.  But  while  he  is  so  far  open  to  the  charge  of 
his  opponent,  it  does  not  appear  that  he  limits  the  idea 
of  grace,  either  to  nature  in  the  sense  of  the  powers  with 
which  man  was  originally  endowed  at  his  creation,  or  to 
the  outward  he]ps  of  the  Divine  law.  On  the  contrary,  he 
includes  in  it  those  internal  Divine  impulses  and  spiritual 
assistances  commonly  denoted  by  the  word.1  This  is  the 
natural  interpretation  of  his  language  ;  nor  is  there  any 
thing  in  his  argument,  as  a  controversialist,  to  require  the 
exclusion  of  such  grace.  The  Pelagian  maintained  the 
power  of  the  human  will ;  but  if  he  admitted  the  need  of 
the  Divine  assistance  at  all  to  it,  as  he  did  in  the  shape  of 
the  created  affections,  and  general  endowments  of  our 
nature,  there  was  no  reason  why  he  should  limit  such  assist 
ance  to  that  creative  one.  The  distinction  of  prior  and 
posterior,  grace  creative  and  grace  assisting  the  creature 
already  made,  was  of  no  importance  in  this  respect.  There 
was  no  difference,  again,  in  principle  between  inward  and 
outward  grace  ;  and  any  one  who  acknowledged  Divine 
assistance,  by  means  of  instruction,  warning,  and  exhorta 
tion  addressed  to  us  from  without,  would  have  no  difficulty 
in  acknowledging  it  in  the  shape  of  spiritual  incitement 
and  illumination  carried  on  within.  The  clue,  then,  to  the 
solution  of  the  Pelagian's  apparently  contradictory  lan 
guage  respecting  grace,  is  rather  to  be  found  in  the  logical 
necessity  there  was  for  an  unassisted  act  of  the  human 
will,  in  accepting  and  using  Divine  assistance.  Admitting 
Divine  grace  to  be  wanted,  but  regarding  the  use  of  it  as 

efficitur   procul    dubio    negas  .  .  .  Natura  et  Gratia,  n.  11. 
Sive  per  gratiam,  sive  per  adjuto-  *  '  Sanctificando,  coercendo,  pro- 

rium,    siye    per    misericordiam,   et  vocando,  illuminando.' — Op.  Imp.  1. 

quicquid  illud  est  per  quod  esse  homo  3.  c.  1 06.     '  Bum  nos  multiformi  et 

sine  peccato  potest,  confitetur,  quis-  ineffaLili  dono  gratiae  ccelestis  illu- 

quis    rem    ipsam    confitetur.' —  De  minat.' — De  Grat.  Christi,  c  7. 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  5 1 

independent  of  grace,  claiming  some  real  power  for  un 
assisted  nature,  though  not  all,  he  was  led  into  a  double 
and  inconsistent  language,  which  sometimes  asserted  the 
necessity  of  grace,  and  sometimes  the  ability  of  nature 
alone. 

Indeed,  it  is  clear  from  the  argument  of  the  book  De 
Gratia  Christi,  that,  whatever  objection  Augustine  may 
raise  to  the  Pelagian  doctrine  of  grace,  on  the  ground  that 
grace  in  it  only  means  Lex  et  Natura,  his  main  objection 
to  that  doctrine  is,  not  that  it  maintains  an  external  grace 
as  distinguished  from  an  internal,  or  a  grace  creative  as 
distinguished  from  additional  to  created  nature,  but  that 
it  maintains  a  grace  which  depends  entirely  on  an  in 
dependent  act  of  the  will  for  its  acceptance  and  use,  as  dis 
tinguished  from  a  grace  which  supplies  that  act  and  secures 
its  own  use.  Pelagius  defines  what  the  function  of  grace 
in  his  idea  is,  and  he  confines  it  to  that  of  assisting  the  power 
of  the  natural  will — possibilitatem  adjuvat1;  the  phrase 
supposes  a  foundation  of  independent  power  in  the  will,  to 
which  grace  is  an  addition.  Augustine,  on  the  other  hand, 
says  it  is  more  than  this,  and  condemns  this  definition  as 
insufficient  and  insulting  to  the  Divine  Power.  This  is 
the  question,  then,  to  which  the  whole  argument  is  sub 
stantially  reduced,  and  on  which  the  whole  book  hinges  ; 
and  it  is  one  concerned,  not  with  the  circumstances,  so  to 
speak,  of  grace,  as  the  other  distinctions  were,  but  with 
its  substantial  nature,  its  relation  to  the  human  will ; 

1  '  Nos  sic  tria  ista  distinguimus,  ipsam  possibilitatem  gratise  susead- 

et  certum  velut  in  ordinem  digesta  juvat  semper  auxilio.' — Pelagius  de 

partimur.     Primo  loco  posse  strttui-  Lib.  Arb.  apud  Aug.  de  Grat.  Christi, 

mus,     secundo    velle,    tertio    esse.  n.  5. 

Posse  in  natura,  velle  in  arbitrio,  Thus  Julian :  '  Adsunt  tamen  ad- 

esse  in    effectu  locamus.     Primum  •  jutoria   gratiae   Dei    quse   in   parte 

illud,  id  est,  posse,  ad  Deum  pro-  virtutis  nunquam  destituunt  volun- 

prie  pertinet,  qui  illud  creaturse  suse  tatem:  cujus  licet  innumerge  species, 

contulit :  duo  vero  reliqua,  hoc  est,  tali  tamen  semper  moderatione  ad- 

velle  et  esse  ad  hominem  referenda  hibentur,  ut  nunquam  liberum  arbi- 

sunt,  quia  de  arbitrii  fonte  descen-  trium  locopellant,  sed  prsebeant  ad- 

dunt.    Ergo  in  voluntate  et  in  opere  minicula,quamdiueisvoluerit  inniti ; 

bono  laus  hominis  est ;  imo  et  homi-  cum  tamen  non  opprimant  reluctan- 

nis  et  Dei,  qui  ipsius  voluntatis  et  tern  animum.' — Op.  Imp.   1.  iii.  c. 

operis  possibilitatem  dedit,  quique  114. 

B  2 


The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  m. 


whether  that  relation  is  one  of  dependence  upon  the  will 
for  its  use,  or  not.1  This  is  the  ultimate  difference  between 
the  two  ;  and  it  must  be  seen,  that  it  does  make  all  the 
difference  in  the  nature  and  quality  of  Divine  grace. 

The  charge  against  the  Pelagian  that  he  held  human 
merit  always  to  precede  grace,  appears  to  be  alike  without 
satisfactory  foundation.  He  disowned  the  position  him 
self2,  nor  was  it  necessary  for  his  argument,  Grace  is, 
indeed,  sometimes  taken  in  a  final  sense,  for  the  designed 
effect  of  assisting  grace  ;  and  stands  for  an  ultimate 
spiritual  habit,  as  when  we  speak  of  the  graces  of  the 
Christian  character,  the  grace  of  charity,  and  the  like  ; 
and  in  that  sense,  if  the  human  will  is  to  have  any  share 
in  the  matter,  grace  must  be  the  consequence  in  part  of 
human  merit.  As  the  crown  of  human  efforts,  it  supposes 
such  efforts  having  been  made.  But  it  would  be  absurd 
to  maintain  that  grace,  in  the  sense  of  assisting  grace, 
requires  a  previous  effort  of  the  human  will  for  obtaining 
it,  and  that  the  individual  must  show  goodness  before  he 
receives  the  Divine  assistance  to  be  good.  All  Christians 
allow  that  such  grace  is  given  to  sinners  in  the  very  depth 
of  their  sin,  and  in  order  to  draw  them  away  from  it  :  nor 
does  the  admission  at  all  affect  the  Pelagian  position  of 
the  independent  power  of  the  will  ;  for  this  would  be 
exerted  in  the  acceptance  and  use  of  such  grace.  I  will 
add  that  this  distinction  between  the  grace  which  crowns 
and  that  which  stimulates  the  efforts  of  the  will  explains 

1  Bradwardine  and  Jansen  thus  —  Pelagius     ap.    Aug.    De    Gratia 

understand  the  Pelagian  doctrine  of  Christi,    c.    22.     Augustine   argues 

grace:  '  Non  enim  existimandum  est  incorrectly  from  this  passage  that 

solam  legera  atque  doctrinam  esse  Pelagius  holds  that  merit  must  pre- 

ppssibilitatis  adjutorium.  .  .  .  Pela-  cede  grace;  whereas  he  only  sa^-s  it 

giaiiijtnotus  indeliberatos  bonus  sub  may,  —  that  grace  may  be  obtained 

gratia   complexi    sunt  :     nam   sive  by   merit,   or  good  works.     On  the 

motus  illos  a  Deo  conditos  inseri,  other  hand  Pelagius  at  the  Synod  of 

si  vemente  per  istam  gratiam  pulsata,  Diospolis  '  damnavit  eos  qui  decent 

ultenus  naturaliter  a  corde  proficisci  gratiam  Dei  secundum  merita  nostra 

decernerent,    eorum    causam  Deum  dari.'  —  De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  3.,  and 

adjuvantem  esse  sentiebant'  Jansen,  Ben.  Ed.  preface,  c.  1  0.—  Nor  is  there 

De  Grat.  Christi,  p.  127.     NOTK  X.  anything  in  the  Pelagian  statements 

'Ostendit    quomodo    resistere  to   show  that  assisting   grace    was 

aebeamus  Diabolo,  si  utique  subditi  considered  to  wait  till  human  merit 

simus  Deo,  ejusque  faciendo  volun-  earned  it. 
tatem  divinam  mereamur  gratiam.' 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  53 

the  apparently  contradictory  language  used  by  divines  to 
explain  the  combination  of  freewill  with  grace ;  sometimes 
the  commencement  of  the  spiritual  life  being  attributed 
to  the  human  will  and  its  completion  to  grace,  and  some 
times  its  completion  being  attributed  to  the  human  will 
and  its  commencement  to  grace.  Under  both  modes  of 
speaking,  the  power  of  the  human  will  is  secured :  but 
under  the  one  the  will  uses  an  assisting,  under  the  other  it 
earns  a  crowning  grace.1 

Thus  apparently  sound  and  forced  upon  reason  by  the 
necessity  of  the  case,  this  position  of  an  ultimate  unassisted 
strength  in  the  natural  will,  was,  nevertheless,  the  root  of 
all  the  errors,  the  extravagances,  and  the  impieties  of 
Pelagianism.  It  was  a  position  logically  true,  indeed,  and 
such  as  could  not  be  denied  without  admitting  the  alter 
native  of  irresistible  grace  or  necessitarianism.  Nor  had  it 
been  maintained  with  due  modesty  and  reserve,  as  being 
one  side  of  the  whole  mysterious  truth  relating  to  human 
action,  would  it  have  been  otherwise  than  orthodox.  But 
to  maintain  absolutely  and  definitely  an  ultimate  power  in 
the  human  will  to  move  aright  independently  of  God,  was 
a  position  untrue,  and  shocking  to  natural  piety ;  a  separa 
tion  of  the  creature  from  the  Creator,  which  was  opposed 
to  the  very  foundation  of  religion.  And  to  proceed  to 
argue  upon  such  a  truth,  and  develop  it,  as  if  it  were  a 
complete  and  ascertained  premiss,  upon  which  a  system 
could  be  erected,  was  to  mistake  its  nature,  and  to  run 
at  once  into  obliquity  and  error.  But  this  was  what  the 
Pelagians  did.2  For  from  this  position  the  conclusion  was 

1  The   general  language  of   the  opem.' — Ep.    Prosperi   inter    Aug. 

Pelagians  allows  an  initiative  grace  Ep.  225.  '  Quod  enim  dicitur.  Crede 

(provocans,  excitans),  and  maintains  et  salvus  eris  ;   unum   horum   exigi 

a  crowning  will :  '  Quod   possumus  asserunt,  aliud  offerri ;  ut  propter  id 

bonum  facere  illius  estqui  hoc  posse  quod  exigitur  si  redditum  fuerit,  id 

donavit ;    quod   vero    bene   agimus  quod  offertur  deinceps  tribuatur.' — 

nostrum  est.' — De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  Ep.    Hilarii    apud  Aug.  Ep.   226. 

4.     The  Semipelagians  speak  of  an  Julian  the  Pelagian  speaks  of  a  cer- 

initiative  will  and  a  crowning  grace:  tain  state  of  perfection  as  a  crowning 

'  Priorem  volunt   obedientiam  esse  grace :  '  ut  hoc  ipsum  non  peccare 

qxiam  gratiam,  ut  initium  salutis  ex  prsemium    censeamus.' — Op.     Imp. 

eo  qui  salvatur,  non  ex  eo  creden-  Contra  Jul.  1.  2.  c.  166. 
dum  sit  stare  qui  salvat,  et  voluntas  2  '  Quod  possumus  omne  bonum 

hominis  divinse   gratiae  sibi  pariat  facere,  dicere,  cogilare,  illius  est  qui 


54  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  m. 

immediately  drawn  that  every  man  had  the  power  of 
fulfilling  the  whole  law.  The  will  was  able  to  make  use 
of  grace  ;  but  every  man,  as  the  Divine  justice  required, 
had  sufficient  grace  given  him.  For  confining  sometimes, 
as  a  matter  of  language,  the  term  grace  to  such  higher 
grace,  or  grace  par  excellence,  as  was  given  under  the 
gospel, — such  grace  as  facilitated  goodness  rather  than  was 
necessary  for  it 1 ;  the  Pelagians  held  really  that  every  one 
had  in  the  sense  of  natural  or  other  endowments,  provi 
dential  aids,  spiritual  impulses,  sufficient  Divine  assistance 
or  grace  to  enable  him  to  do  his  duty.  Every  man,  there 
fore,  having  sufficient  grace,  and  the  absolute  power  to  use 
it,  had  the  power  to  fulfil  the  whole  law. 

The  doctrine  of  the  perfectibility  of  man  in  this  life 
was  held,  indeed,  by  the  opponents  of  Pelagius,  as  well  as 
by  himself,  but  upon  a  totally  different  ground  from  that 
on  which  he  based  it.  Augustine  maintained  that  no 
limits  were  to  be  put  to  the  power  of  Divine  grace ;  but 
that  it  might  please  Grod  in  a  particular  instance  so  to 
control  and  direct  all  the  motions  of  a  human  will,  that 
the  person  might  even  in  this  life  become  perfect.2  The 
admission,  however,  is  made  with  much  hesitation ;  he 
confesses  such  a  case  would  be  a  miracle,  as  being  contrary 
to  all  the  established  laws  of  the  operation  of  grace  ;  and, 
what  is  most  important,  he  rests  the  possibility  of  it  solely 
upon  the  ground  of  grace,  or  the  Divine  power.  Pelagius, 
on  the  other  hand,  naturalised  this  perfectibility,  making 
it  part  of  the  constitution  of  man,  and  drawing  it  from  the 

hoc  posse  donavit:  quodverobcne  vel  implere  per  gratiam.'— Pelagius  de 

agimus,  vel  loquinmr,  vel  cogitamns  Lib.  Arb.  ap.   Aug.  Epist.   186.  n. 

nostrum  est,  quia  haec  omnia  vertere  35. 

m  malum  possumus.'— Pelagius,  ap.  '  Sed  formidantes  multitudinem 

Aug.  De  Gratia  Christian.  5.  Christianam,    Pelagianum    verbum 

1  'In  omnibus  est  liberum  arbi-  supponitis,  et  quserentibus  a  nobis, 

trram,  sequaliter  per  naturam,  sed  quare  moxtuus  sit  Christus,  si  natura 

m  sobs  Christiani  s  juvatur  a  gratia.'  vel  lex  efficit  justos  ;  respondetis  ut 

-Letter  of  Pelagius  to  Innocent,  ap.  hoc  ipsum  facilius  fieret,  quasi  posset, 

Aug.  de  Gratia  Christi,  n.  33.  quamvis  difficilius  fieri  tamen,  sive 

'  Ideo   Dei    gratiam    hominibus  per  naturam  sive  per  legem.' Op 

dan  ut  quod  facere  per  liberum  ju-  Imp.  Contra  Jul.  1.  2.  c.  198 
bentur    arbitrium   facilius    possint  2  NOTE  XI 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  55 

essential  power  of  the  human  will.1  However  rare,  there 
fore,  its  attainment  might  be,  perfection,  upon  his  system, 
was  attainable  by  everyone  :  indeed  some  he  asserted  had 
actually  attained  it :  an  assertion  from  which  S.  Augustine 
shrank.  The  possibility  admitted  in  theory,  his  practical 
belief  withdrew  the  admission,  and  bound  man,  as  long  as 
he  remains  in  this  mortal  state  to  sin,  obliged  to  cry  with 
the  Apostle  '  who  shall  deliver  me  from  this  death  ? '  and  by 
the  simple  profession  of  4  having  no  sin '  infallibly  con 
victed  of  falsehood  and  pride. 

The  original  position  respecting  the  will  thus  led  im 
mediately  to  the  other  great  question :  and  we  find  our 
selves  thrown  at  once  on  the  great  subject  of  the  Pelagian 
controversy.  Such  a  doctrine  of  the  power  of  the  human 
will  was  evidently  opposed  to  the  doctrine  of  the  fall : 
for  such  a  will  was  evidently  not  a  corrupt,  but  a  sound 
will,  inasmuch  as  it  could  perform  its  proper  function.  It 
may  be  doubtful,  therefore,  whether  Pelagius  in  the  first 
instance  meant  to  attack  the  catholic  doctrine  of  the  fall ; 
he  certainly  showed  reluctance  to  come  into  express  col 
lision  with  it,  and  resisted  the  logical  strain  upon  him : 
his  attitude  was  at  the  first  a  defensive  rather  than  aggres 
sive  one,  as  if,  provided  the  church  would  let  him  hold 
what  he  considered  to  be  the  plain  facts  of  human  nature, 
he  did  not  wish  to  interfere  with  any  received  doctrine  : 
and  his  answers  at  the  Synod  of  Diospolis2  are  perhaps  too 

1  '  Ante  omnia  interrogandus  est  ergo  cum  peecato  esse;  et  jam  pec- 
qui  negat  hominem  sine  peecato  esse  catum  non  erit,  si  illud  debere  con- 
posse,  quid  sit  quodcunque  peccatum,  stiterit.  Aut  si  hoc  etiam  dici  ab- 
quod  vitari  potest,  an  quod  vitari  non  surdum  est,  confiteri  necesse  est 
potest.  Si  qxiod  vitari  non  potest,  debere  hominem  sine  peecato  esse, 
peccatum  non  est ;  si  quod  vitari  po-  et  constat  eum  non  aliud  debere 
test,  potest  homo  sine  peecato  esse  quam  potest.  .  .  .  Iterum  quse- 
quod  vitari  potest.  .  .  .  Iterum  rendum  est  quomodo  non  potest  homo 
quserendum  est  peccatum  voluntatis  sine  peecato  esse,  voluntate  an  na- 
an  necessitatis  est.  Si  necessitatis  tura.  Si  natura,  peccatum  non  est ; 
est,  peccatum  non  est;  si  voluntatis  si  voluntate,  perfacile  potest  voluntas 
est,  vitari  potest.  .  .  .  Iterum  voluntate  mutari.' — Pelagius  ap. 
quserendum  est,  utrumne  debeat  Aug.  De  Perfectione  Justitise,  c.  2. 
homo  sine  peecato  esse.  Proeul  du-  3.  6. 

bio  debet.     Si  debet,  potest ;  si  non  2  Benedictine  Editor's  preface  to 

potest,    ergo  nee  debet ;    et  si  nee  Augustine's  Antipelagian  Treatises, 

debet  homo  esse  sine  peecato,  debet  c.  x. 


5  6  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP,  m. 

summarily  attributed  to  duplicity  rather  than  a  real  in 
disposition  to  advance  beyond  his  original  statements, 
though  his  disciple  Celestius  had  been  bolder.  But  the 
assertion  of  such  a  freewill  as  Pelagius  asserted  was  m 
itself  a  denial  of  the  fall,  and  therefore  necessarily  carried 
him,  whatever  his  direct  intention  at  first  was,  to  the 
express  denial  of  that  doctrine.  And  thus  the  question 
assumed  that  shape  in  which  it  has  come  down  to  us  in 
the  Pelagian  controversy. 

II.  With  this  introduction,  then,  I  come  to  my  second 
head,  and  shall  endeavour  to  state  in  succession,  and  with 
such  explanation  as  may  be  necessary,  the  main  positions 
and  arguments  involved  in  that  controversy  ;  and  which 
may  be  conveniently  placed  under  three  general  heads — 
the  power  of  the  will,  the  nature  of  virtue  and  vice,  and 
the  Divine  justice. 

1.  The  first  and  most  obvious  argument  against  the 
doctrine  of  the  corruption  of  human  nature,  was  contained 
in  that  power  of  the  will  which  has  been  just  now  described. 
Here  nature  seemed  to  bear  testimony  to  its  own  com 
petency,  and  the  doctrine  of  its  corruption  to  be  contra 
dicted  by  a  plain  fact ;  for  we  are  conscious  of  freewill, 
power  of  choice,  and  self-determination.  The  Pelagians 
appealed  to  these  instinctive  convictions,  and  pointed  out 
their  contrariety  to  the  doctrine  of  a  captive  and  corrupted 
nature.  Nor  was  their  argument  unsound  had  they  been 
content  to  direct  it  against  an  absolute  doctrine  of  human 
corruption  and  captivity.  But  they  pressed  it  too  far  and 
lay  more  weight  upon  it  than  it  could  bear.  They  fancied 
themselves  in  possession  of  the  whole  ground  because  they 
had  this  sense  of  freedom  on  their  side.  But  S.  Augustine 
could  appeal,  on  the  other  side,  to  a  representation  of 
human  nature,  which  carried  with  it  its  own  evidence,  and 
met  a  response  in  the  human  heart — 'To  will  is  present 
with  me,  but  how  to  perform  that  which  is  good  I  find  not. 
For  the  good  that  I  would  I  do  not,  but  the  evil  which 
I  would  not  that  I  do.  ...  I  see  a  law  in  my  members, 
warring  against  the  law  of  my  mind,  and  bringing  me 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy. 


57 


into  captivity  to  the  law  of  sin.'  !  The  sense  of  freedom  is 
a  true  part  of  human  nature ;  but  there  is  also,  on  the 
other  side,  a  sense  of  captivity  :  and  as  Pelagius  appealed 
to  one  side  of  our  consciousness,  Augustine  appealed  to  the 
other. 

The  conscience  of  every  enlightened  man,  as  all  con 
fess,  bears  witness  to  the  presence  of  sin.  But — more  than 
this — the  enlightened  conscience  bears  witness  to  a  certain 
impossibility  of  avoiding  sin  altogether.  It  is  true  we  are 
conscious  of  freewill,  and  feel  we  have  the  power  of  doing 
right  and  abstaining  from  wrong  on  each  occasion.  Nay, 
the  very  sense  of  sin  depends  upon  this  sense  of  the  power 
to  avoid  it;  for  we  do  not  feel  responsible  for  what  we 
cannot  help.  But  with  this  sense  of  freedom  there  is  also 
a  certain  sense  of  necessity —  a  perception  that  sin  is  not 
wholly  avoidable  in  this  present  state  of  our  nature.  We 
cannot  imagine  an  enlightened  conscience  in  which  there 
would  not  be  this  inward  sense :  no  good  man  could  ever 


1  '  In  mediiim  procedit  homo  ille 
qui  clamat,  "  Non  quod  volo  facio 
bonum,  sed  quod  nolo  malum  hoc 
ago."  '—Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  18.  '  Qui 
per  legem  quam  vidit  in  membris 
suis  repugnautem  legi  mentis  suse 
et  captivantem  se  sub  lege  peccati, 
clamat,  "  Non  quod  volo,"  &c.  Si 
habet  liberum  arbitrium,  quare  non 
facit  bonum  quod  vult?'— L.  3.  c. 
112.  Augustine,  assuming  this 
captivity  as  an  evident  fact,  proves 
original  sin  from  it:  'Nam  si  pecca- 
tum  non  pertransisset,  non  omnis 
homo  cum  lege  peccati  quse  in  mem 
bris  est  nasceretur.' — L.  2.  c.  63. 
1  Homo  qui  non  cogitas  ubi  sis,  et 
in  diebus  malis  tanquam  in  bonis 
ceecus  extolleris  ;  quando  erat  libe 
rum  arbitrium,  nondum  homo  vani- 
tati  similis  factus  erat.' — L.  3.  c. 
110.  'Quidicit,  "Quod  nolo  malum, 
hoc  ago,"  responde  utrum  necessita- 
tem  non  habeat.' — L.  5.c.  50.  'Non 
ei  possibilitatis  inanitas,  sed  neces- 
sitatis  inerat  plenitudo.' — L.  5.  c.  59. 


The  Pelagians  interpreted  this 
text  as  referring  to  the  force  of  cus 
tom,  'Ille  enim  in  membris  legem 
consuetudinem  malam  vocabat,  quae 
ab  eruditis  etiam  seculi  dici  solet 
secunda  natura.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  I.e. 
69.  An  interpretation  which  Augus 
tine  turned  against  them,  as  com 
mitting  them  to  the  admission  that 
sin  might  be  necessary,  and  yet  real 
sin,  and  so  to  the  principle  of  origi 
nal  sin.  '  Nam  et  ille  qui  dicit, 
"  Non  quod  volo,  ago,"  certe  secun- 
dum  vos  necessitate  consuetudinis 
premitur  :  hanc  autem  necessitatem, 
ne  liberum  auferatis  arbitrium,  eum 
sibi  voluntate  fecisse  contenditis,  et 
tale  aliquid  in  natura  humana  factum 
esse  non  creditis.' — L.  4.  c.  103.  ; 
also  1.  1.  c.  105.;  1.4.  c.  91.  'The 
body  of  this  death  was  interpreted 
of  the  guilt  of  past  sin.'  '  Quis  me 
liberavit  a  reatu  peccatorum  meorum 
quse  commisi,  cum  vitari  potuisseut.' 
—Op.  Imp.  1.  1,  c.  67. 


^ 8  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  nr. 

possibly  think  that  he  could  be  without  serious  sin  in  this 
world.  This  sense  of  a  law  working  for  evil  in  our  nature 
is  a  consequence  and  a  part  of  goodness ;  and  conscience 
witnesses  to  opposite  perceptions  which  it  cannot  harmonise. 
Experience,  indeed,  shows  the  great  improbability  of  perfec 
tion  in  this  life,  but  the  enlightened  conscience  speaks  to 
its  impossibility,  because  it  sees  a  law  of  our  present  nature 
to  which  it  is  opposed.  Experience  shows  that  men  never 
have  been  perfect,  but  not  that  they  could  not  be  :  but  the 
enlightened  conscience  would,  upon  the  mere  hearing  of 
some  or  other  human  being  who  was  perfect,  justify  the 
setting  down  the  assertion  as  in  itself  absurd  and  incredible; 
containing,  according  to  the  Scriptural  criterion,  its  own 
refutation,  '  If  we  say  we  have  no  sin,  we  deceive  ourselves, 
and  the  truth  is  not  in  us.'  But  what  is  this  but  a  sense 
of  necessity  on  the  side  of  evil ;  for  if  it  is  simply  absurd 
that  the  state  of  man  in  this  life  should  not  be  sinful,  it 
must  be  necessary  that  it  should  be. 

From  this  sense  of  freedom  on  the  one  side,  and  of 
captivity  on  the  other,  proceeds  that  mixture  and  opposi 
tion  in  our  nature,  that  whole  ambiguous  state  of  mind  of 
which  man  is  so  deeply  conscious  in  moral  action  ;  that 
subtle  discord  in  the  will ;  that  union  of  strength  and 
weakness.  Take  the  case  of  any  action  above  the  standard 
of  ordinary  practice  that  a  man  may  propose  to  himself  to 
do  ;  with  what  a  mixture  of  feelings  does  he  approach  it  ? 
He  feels,  on  the  one  hand,  that  he  is  certainly  able  to  do  it, 
and  can  exert  a  force  over  himself  sufficient  for  the  pur 
pose  ;  and  he  prepares  for  the  turning  point  of  a  resolve 
under  this  impression.  On  the  other  hand,  the  level  of 
ordinary  practice  pulls  him  down,  and  the  weight^of  habit 
rests  upon  him.  Nature  falls  back,  the  will  is  unnerved, 
and  invincible  repugnance  and  disinclination  contradict  his 
natural  sensations  of  moral  power.  He  doubts  the  sincerity 
of  these  sensations,  as  if,  however  innate,  they  were  specious 
and  deceptive.  Can  he,  then,  really  do  the  good  act  ?  Has 
he  freewill  or  not  ?  He  alternates  between  both  impres 
sions,  unable  to  deny  his  freedom,  yet  apparently  unable 
to  use  it,  feeling  no  constraint,  yet  inferring  from  the  diffi- 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  59 

culties  of  the  case  some  unfelt  one,  existing  too  deep  in 
nature  for  actual  apprehension,  and  only  showing  itself  in 
its  effects.  Such  is  the  inward  struggle  of  the  imperfect 
moral  agent  described  by  St.  Paul. 

Take,  again,  the  known  power  of  custom  over  the  will. 
A  man  under  the  most  inveterate  bad  habit,  has  on  every 
successive  occasion  the  feeling  of  a  power  to  do  the  action 
opposed  to  it.  However  long  and  uniformly  he  may  have 
acted  on  the  side  of  his  habit,  the  very  next  time  he  has 
to  act  he  appears  to  himself  to  be  able — though  it  be  no 
more  than  naked,  bare,  ability — still  able,  I  say,  to  do  what 
he  has  never  yet  done.  But  it  is  evident  that  such  an  idea 
of  power  is  not  to  be  taken  as  a  certain  exponent  of  the 
fact.  There  is  an  idea  of  power,  indeed,  which  represents 
faithfully  the  reality,  a  conscious  strength  of  purpose,  which 
is  generally  the  result  of  moral  preparation.  But  this  is 
altogether  a  distinct  sort  of  conviction  from  that  mere  sense 
of  bare  ability  to  do  a  thing  which  is  now  referred  to. 

The  sense  of  freedom  then  in  our  nature,  with  whatever 
force  and  vividness  it  may  appeal  to  us,  is  not  to  be  relied 
upon  absolutely,  as  if  it  represented  our  whole  state.  A 
larger  insight  into  ourselves,  a  general  survey  of  facts,  mo 
difies  the  result  of  the  impression,  and  does  not  sanction 
the  profession  of  absolute  power.  But  the  Pelagian  relied 
upon  this  sense  of  bare  ability,  as  if  it  were  an  infallible 
footing  for  the  most  complete  conclusion,  and  betrayed  that 
want  of  due  and  circumspect  distrust  which  never  forsakes 
the  true  philosophical  mind,  that  knows  how  nature  abounds 
in  pitfalls  to  catch  the  unwary ;  and,  however  considerate 
of,  is  ever  jealous  of,  appearances.  He  trusted  with  blind 
confidence  a  single  impression  and  instinct,  so  blindly 
indeed,  as  to  put  aside  the  plainest  facts,  when  they  inter 
fered  with  it. 

For  nothing  can  show  more  strongly  the  reckless  and 
hasty  faith,  which  the  Pelagians  reposed  in  this  one  impres 
sion,  than  that  they  supported  it  against  the  most  palpable 
facts  connected  with  nature  and  habit ;  arguing,  that  sin  not 
being  a  substance,  but  only  an  act  which  took  place  and 
was  then  over,  could  not  by  any  amount  of  repetition  affect 


60  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  m. 

this  power  and  impair  freewill1  ;  but  that  a  man  after  any 
amount  and  duration  of  sin,  had  as  much  freewill  as  ever. 
The  reason  was  that,  as  I  have  just  stated,  the  sense  of  bare 
ability  continues  in  spite  of  any  length  of  habit;  on  which 
sense  the  Pelagian  absolutely  relied.  But  this  was  not  a 
reasonable,  but  a  fanatical2  doctrine  of  freewill ;  a  gross 
delusion,  belonging  to  that  class  and  rank  of  absurd  ideas 
upon  which  corrupt  and  fantastic  sects  arise ;  forsaking  the 
broad,  inclusive  ground  of  truth  for  some  narrow  conceit, 
some  one  notion  to  which  everything  gives  way,  and  which, 
losing  by  such  exclusiveness  all  its  original  share  of  truth, 
becomes  a  shadow  and  a  lie.  This  was  a  departure  from  the 
first  principles  of  morals,  as  attaching  no  consequences 
within  the  soul  itself  to  moral  evil,  which  is  thus  repre 
sented  as  passing  off,  and  leaving  no  trace  behind.  The 
moral  being  incurred,  indeed,  the  external  consequence  of 
liability  to  punishment,  but  was  not  in  himself  impaired  by 
sin ;  remaining  the  same  as  before.  But  it  is  the  internal 
consequences  of  sin,  which  fasten  the  idea  of  sin,  as  being 
such,  upon  us,  and  make  us  regard  it  as  the  real  evil  it 
is.  Take  away  these  consequences,  and  sin  is  little  more 
than  a  shadow  which  just  rests  a  moment  on  the  soul,  and 
is  then  gone.  It  ceases  to  be  a  serious  thing,  it  ceases  to 

1  '  Liberum    arbitrium    et    post  gius  ap.  Aug.  De  Nat.  et  Grat.  n. 

peccata  tarn  plenum  est  quam  fuit  21.     '  Materiam  peccati  esse  vindic- 

ante  peccata.' — Julian  ap.  Op.  Imp.  tarn,  si  ad  hoc  peccator  infirmatus 

1.1.  c.   91.     'Nos  dicimus  peccato  est  ut  plura  peccaret.' — n.  24. 
hominis  non  naturae  statum  mutari  2  It  was  perhaps  an  ironical  charge 

sed  meriti  qualitatem,  id  est  et  in  against  the  Pelagians  that  they  held 

peccato  hanc  esse  liberi  arbitrii  na-  '  etiam  parvulos  propria  per  liberum 

turam,   per  quam  potest   a  peccato  arbitrium   habere  peccata.     .     .     . 

desinere,  quae  fuit  in  eo  ut  posset  a  Ecce  inquiunt,  Esau  et  Jacob  intra 

justitia  deviare.' — c.  96.     '  Primo  de  viscera  materna  luctantur,  et,  dum 

eo  disputandum  est  quod  per  pecca-  nascuntur,  alter  supplantatur  ab  al- 

tum  debilitata  dieitur  et  immutata  tero,  atque  in  pede  prsecedentismanu. 

natura.     Unde  ante  omnia  quseren-  consequent!  s  ettenentis  inventa,  per- 

dum  puto  quid  sit  peccatum,  sub-  severans  quodammodo  lucta  convin- 

stantia  aliqua,  an  omnino  substantia  citur.     Quomodo  ergo  in  infantibus 

carens  nomen,  quo  non  res,  non  exis-  hsec  agentibus,  nullum  est  vel   ad 

tentia,  non  corpus  aliquid,   sed  per-  bonum  vel  ad  malum  proprise  volun- 

peram  facti  actus  exprimitnr.  Credo  tatis  arbitrium,  unde  prsemia  sive 

ita  est.     Et  si  ita  est  quomodo  potuit  supplicia  meritis  prsecedentibus  sub- 

humanam  debilitare  vel  mutare  na-  sequantur.' — Ep.  186.  n.  13. 
turam  quod  substaiitia  caret.'— Pela- 


CHAP.  ITT.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  61 

be  sin ;  its  very  substance  is  that  part  of  it  which  survives 
the  act,  and  its  continuance  is  its  existence.  The  Pelagian, 
then,  secures  his  unqualified  freewill  at  the  cost  of  the  very 
rudiments  of  morals  ;  his  theory  would  injure  the  moral  tone 
of  any  mind  that  received  it,  and  its  natural  effect,  if  it 
spread,  would  be  a  relaxation  of  the  religious  standard,  and 
a  lowering  of  the  sense  of  sin  in  the  world ;  showing  how 
impossible  it  is  to  carry  one  truth  to  an  excess  without  im 
pairing  another.  Those  who  will  not  allow  the  will  to  be 
the  less  free  for  any  amount  of  sin  must  accept  the  alterna 
tive,  that  sin  has  very  little  effect, — with  its  natural  corol 
lary,  that  that  which  has  so  slight  an  effect  cannot  be  a 
very  serious  matter  itself.  And  thus  an  unlimited  freewill 
can  only  be  maintained  by  abandoning  the  sanctity  of  moral 
principle. 

2.  The  argument  respecting  the  will  was  succeeded,  in 
the  Pelagian  controversy,  by  the  argument  respecting  the 
nature  of  virtue  and  vice.  How  could  there  be  such  a 
thing  as  hereditary  sin  ?  sin  transmitted  from  father  to 
son,  and  succeeded  to  by  birth  ?  How  were  moral  disposi 
tions  involved  in  the  operations  of  nature? 1  This  appeal  to 
reason  was  properly  answered  by  an  appeal  to  mystery — an 
answer,  however,  which  was  needlessly  perplexed  by  too 
minute  attempts  to  define  the  mode  of  the  transmission  of 
sin  ? 2  The  explanation  of  a  mystery  cannot  really  advance 
beyond  the  statement  of  it,  but  the  too  subtle  explainer 
forgets  his  own  original  admission  and  the  inherent  limits 

1  '  Amentissimum  est  arbitrii  ne-  hodie  conceptos  aiite  tot  secula  ha- 

gotium  seminibus  immixtum  putare.'  buisse  sensum,  judicium,  efficientiam 

— Julian,  Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  9.      'In-  voluntatis.' — L.  4.  104. 

justum   est   ut   reatus   per    semiria  2  Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  22. ;    1.  2.  c. 

traderetur.'— L.  3.  c.   11.     '  Habue-  123.;    1.   4.   c.   90—104.,  1.   6.;    c. 

runt  ergo  parvuli  voluntatem   non  9 — 23.     An  elaborate  attempt  at  an 

solum  antequam  nascerentur,  verum  explanation  of  this  difficulty,  by  the 

etiam  antequam  proavi  eorum  gene-  analogy   of  bodies,    quae  affieiendo 

rarentur  ;   et  usi   sunt  electionis  ar-  transeunt,  non  emigrando  (L  5.  Con- 

bitrio,  priusquam  substiintise  eorum  tra  Jul.  Pel.  n.  51.),  concludes  thus: 

semina    conderentxir.      Cur    itaque  '  Sic  et  vitia  cum  sint  in  subjecto  ex 

metuis  dicere,  in  eis  tempore  concep-  parentibus  tamen  in  filios,  non  quasi 

tuum  eorum  esseliberam voluntatem,  transmigratione  de  suo  subjecto  in 

qua  peccatum  non  trahant  naturalitei1  subjectum  alterum,  sed  affectione  et 

sad  sponte  committant ;  si  credis  eos  contagione  pertranseunt.' 


52  The  Pelagian  Controversy.          CHAP.  m. 

of  his  task,  and  imagines  himself  solving  what  is  inex 
plicable. 

But  the  question  of  transmitted  or  hereditary  sin  gave 
place  to  the  larger  question  of  necessary  sin.  Sin  was  re 
presented,  in  the  doctrine  of  the  fall,  as  attaching  to  human 
nature,  i.e.  as  necessary.  But  was  not  this  opposed  to  the 
self-evident  truth,  that  sin  must  be  voluntary  ?  *  To  deserve 
properly  praise  or  blame,  must  not  a  man  be  a  free  agent  ? 
and  was  he  a  free  agent  if  he  could  not  act  otherwise  than 
as  he  did  ?  The  Pelagian  thus  adopted,  as  a  plain  maxim 
of  reason,  and  a  fundamental  truth  of  morals,  the  position 
that  virtue  and  vice  derived  their  essential  characteristics 
from  the  power  of  the  individual  beforehand  to  choose  the 
one  or  the  other  ;  possibilitas  utriusque  partis;  that  an 
act  of  the  will,  to  be  good  or  bad,  must  be  a  decision  out 
of  a  neutral  or  undecided  state.2  The  Pelagian  controversy 
thus  took  up  the  question  of  the  conditions  of  virtue  and 
vice  ;  whether  virtue  or  vice  were  consistent  with  necessity 
or  repugnant  to  it,  whether  they  involved  in  their  own 
nature  the  trial  of  the  will  or  not. 

The  Pelagian,  then,  as  the  above  statement  shows,  ex 
pressed  himself  unguardedly  on  this  question,  and  exposed 
himself  immediately  to  the  irresistible  answer  of  S.  Augus 
tine,  that,  on  the  ground  he  adopted,  he  must  be  prepared 
to  deny  all  goodness  to  the  angels  in  heaven,  to  the  saints 
in  glory,3  and  even  to  God  Himself.  The  impossibility  of 
sinning  belonged  to  the  Divine  Being  as  His  nature,  and 
to  the  saints  and  angels  as  a  privilege  and  reward  ;  and 
therefore  were  contingency,  or  the  absence  of  necessity, 

1 '  Naturale  nullum  esse  peccatum  ex  utraque  parte  per   sequalia  mo- 

potest.' — '  Si  est  naturale  peccatum  menta  suspendere,  ut  voluntas  quan- 

non    est     voluntarium.'— '  Voluntas  turn  sit  ad  malum,  tantum  etiam  sit 

necessitati  non  potest  admoveri.'—  ad  bonum  libera.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c. 

'  Non  potest  velle  antequam  potuerit  112.  117.     'Sic  definis  liberam  vo- 

et  nolle.' — '  Suum  non  est  si  neces-  luntatem,  ut  nisi  utrumque,  id  est, 

sarium  est.'  et  bene  et  male  agere  possit,  libera 

2  Julian  :  '  Inculco  liberum  arbi-  esse  non  possit.' — L.  3.  c.  120. 
trium  nee  ob  aliud  datum  esse,  nee  3  '  Accedere   nobis   debet  virtus 

intelligi  in  alio  posse,  quam  ut  nee  major  in  przemio,  ut  rnalam  volun- 

ad  justitiam,    nee   ad   iniquitatem,  tatem   sic   non   haberemus,    ut  nee 

captiva  aliquis  voluntate  rapiatur.'  habere    possemus.      0   desideranda 

Augustine :  '  Libra  tua  quam  conaris  necessitas  ! ' — Op.  Imp.  1.5.  c.  61. 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  63 

essential  to  goodness,  neither  Grod,  nor  the  angels,  nor  the 
saints  would  be  good. 

Thus  easily  and  summarily  refuted,  however,  his  argu 
ment  involved  a  mixture  of  truth  and  error.  So  much 
must  be  conceded  to  the  Pelagian,  that  the  trial  of  the  will 
is  the  necessary  condition  of  the  highest  kind  of  virtue  that 
comes  within  our  cognisance  and  experience.  Of  the  Divine 
Nature,  as  being  beyond  our  comprehension,  we  cannot 
speak,  though  we  know  that  it  must  be  infinitely  good, 
while  it  must  also  be  without  trial.  But  the  assertion  is 
true  of  the  moral  creature  in  this  present  state.  For  what 
ever  may  be  the  sweetness  of  the  good  affections, — even 
though  we  could  imagine  them  from  the  first  in  full  pos 
session  of  the  mind,  and  so  powerfully  moving  it,  that  it 
felt  no  inclination  to  act  otherwise  than  as  they  dictated  ; 
even  though  we  could  imagine  such  an  uninterrupted  flow 
of  virtue  from  a  source  of  feeling, — such  a  result  could  not 
bear  a  comparison  with  the  victory  of  the  will.  The  good 
affections  are  aids  and  supports  to  goodness ;  aids  and  sup 
ports  indeed  not  casual  or  adventitious,  but  permanent, 
and  belonging  to  our  nature ;  yet  having  the  effect  of 
saving  pain  and  effort.  But  in  trial  we  have  to  act  with 
out  this  aid.  For  though  even  the  will  itself  cannot  be  said 
to  act  without  affection,  inasmuch  as  some  love  of  what  is 
good  appears  to  enter  as  an  ingredient  into  any  decision 
in  favour  of  it,  we  are  properly  said  to  act  from  the  will 
as  distinct  from  the  affections,  in  the  case  of  trial ;  such 
trial  being  in  truth  caused  by  the  balance  of  the  affections 
being  on  the  side  of  evil.  Trial,  therefore,  throws  the  man 
upon  himself  in  a  deep  and  peculiar  sense.  He  is  reduced 
to  the  narrowest  condition,  and  with  all  the  excesses  of  a 
bountifully  constituted  nature  cut  off,  sustains  from  ulti 
mate  conscience  and  the  bare  substance  of  the  soul,  the 
fight  with  evil.  But  such  a  combat  tests  and  elicits  an 
inner  strength  which  no  dominion  of  the  good  affections, 
however  continuous,  could  do.  The  greater  the  desertion 
of  the  moral  being,  and  his  deprivation  of  aids,  the  deeper 
appears  his  fidelity ;  the  triumph  is  greater  in  proportion 
to  the  scantiness  of  the  means  with  which  it  is  gained  ; 


64  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  ITT. 

and  in  this  adoption  of,  this  cleaving  to,  barren  good,  is  a 
depth  of  affection,  a  root  of  love,  contrasted  with  which,  all 
the  richness  of  the  untried  affections  is  a  poor  and  feeble 
offering  to  Grod. 

But  though  trial  is  the  necessary  condition  of  the  high 
est  kind  of  goodness  in  this  life,  it  is  not  the  necessary 
condition  of  all  goodness.  It  is  evident  that  we  recognise 
and  feel  toward,  as  goodness,  certain  moral  states  and  dis 
positions  which  have  not  been  the  result  of  trial,  but  are 
altogether  natural.  We  may  see  this  in  a  very  low  degree 
even  in  the  case  of  animals  of  the  gentler,  more  generous, 
and  confiding  character  who  engage  our  affections  in  con 
sequence,  and  towards  whom  we  instinctively  feel  as  pos 
sessing  a  kind  of  goodness.  But  the  good  natural  dispo 
sitions  of  moral  beings  deserve  a  serious  consideration.1 
For  though  it  may  be  doubted  whether  these  dispositions 
are  ever  sustained  entirely  without  trial  of  the  will,  and 
though  we  may  not  be  able  to  tell  in  a  particular  case, 
whether  what  appears  to  be  the  man's  natural  disposition 
has  not  been  formed  in  part  by  early  trial  and  past  moral 
acts,  still  the  general  sense  of  mankind  acknowledges  wnat 
are  called  good  natural  dispositions ;  that  some  persons 
have  by  nature  a  good  bias  in  one  or  other  direction,  are 
amiable,  courageous,  truthful,  humble  naturally,  or  have 
a  certain  general  happy  conformation  ;  that  tht-y  have,  that 
is,  by  nature,  not  only  the  power  to  act  in  a  certain  way, 
but  the  disposition  so  to  act  already  formed  within  them ; 
a  habit  implanted,  or,  as  the  schoolmen  say,  infused,  in 
distinction  to  being  acquired  by  acts.  But  it  would  be 
absurd  to  say  that  such  dispositions  as  these  were  not  vir 
tues,  and  that  such  natural  goodness  was  not  real  goodness. 
We  feel  towards  persons  who  possess  such  dispositions  as 
persons  of  a  particular  character,  which  character  is  good; 
nor  do  we  do  this  on  even  the  imaginary  supposition  that 
they  have  acquired  it  for  themselves,  the  existing  moral 

1  '  Cur  non  anmrimus  esse  quos-  in   setate  qua  usus  incipit  esse  ra- 

dam  natura  misericordes,  si  natura  tionis,    sicut   ipsa   ratio,     incipiunt 

quosdam   non    negamus    excordes  ?  apparere.'— Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  129. 
Stint  enim  nonnulla  congenita,  quse 


CHAP.  HI.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  65 

state  being  the  thing  we  attend  to  independent  of  any 
source  from  which  it  may  have  sprung.  The  system  of 
trial  and  probation  under  which  we  are  placed  is  thus  to 
some  extent  a  modified  one ;  not  throw 'ng  us1  wholly  upon 
ourselves,  to  work  our  way  up  to  the  virtuous  character  by 
the  power  of  the  mere  will,  but  more  or  less,  and  in  por 
tions,  endowing  us  with  it,  and  producing  in  us  to  begin 
with  the  ultimate  forms  of  moral  being. 

And  it  is  proper,  as  a  further  answer  to  the  Pelagian 
confined  idea  of  virtue,  to  add,  that  no  exact  limit  is,  to 
the  eye  of  reason  apparent,  to  the  operation  of  such  a 
power  of  infusing  virtue  into  the  human  soul.  It  would 
undoubtedly  be  something  like  a  contradiction  to  suppose 
that  the  distinctive  effect  of  trial  could  be  obtained  without 
trial  as  the  cause,  and  it  must  be  granted  that  there  must  be 
some  ultimate  difference  in  favour  of  that  virtue  which  is, 
over  that  which  is  not,  the  effect  of  trial.  But  there  is  no 
other  apparent  goal  to  an  untried  virtue.  We  know  that 
a  certain  excitement  of  the  feelings  produces  a  pleasure  in 
virtue,  and  that  particular  circumstances,  junctures,  appeals 
from  without,  act  with  an  exciting  power  upon  the  feelings, 
kindling  zeal,  enthusiasm,  and  love.  But  this  being  the 
case,  it  is  impossible  to  say  to  what  extent  this  system  of 
impulse  and  excitement  existing  in  our  constitution  might 
be  carried  ;  what  duration  these  conditions  of  mind  are  in 
themselves  capable  of,  and  whether  they  might  not  be 
made,  by  Divine  power  applying  a  fit  machinery  and  suc 
cession  of  exciting  causes,  permanent.  We  only  know 
that  such  a  system  would  not  serve  that  particular  end  for 
which  the  present  system  of  trial  is  designed. 

But  the  Pelagian  was  further  wrong.  As  trial  is  not 
the  necessary  condition  of  all  goodness,  so  it  is  not  the 
necessary  condition  of  the  highest  kind  of  goodness  always. 
The  system  of  probation  points  according  to  the  reason  of 
the  case,  to  its  own  termination.  It  is  designed  for  an 
end ;  but  the  end,  when  attained,  implies  the  cessation  of 
the  means.  There  is  a  plain  incongruity  in  the  perfected 
being  remaining  still  dependent  on  a  contingent  will,  and 
exposed  to  moral  risk  ;  i.e.  being  for  ever  on  his  trial.  A 

F 


56  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  m. 

time  must  come,  then,  when  this  will  cease,  when  there 
will  be  no  more  deciding  between  good  and  evil,  when  that 
power  of  choice  which  makes  our  virtue  here  will  be  over, 
and  the  goodness  of  the  moral  creature  will  be  necessary 
goodness,  from  which  he  will  not  be  able  to  depart  for 
evermore. 

And  this  consideration  is  much  confirmed  by  another. 
The  trial  of  the  will  is  undoubtedly  the  condition  here  of 
the  highest  kind  of  virtue  ;  but  it  must  be  admitted  at  the 
same  time  that  it  produces  this  virtue  in  an  incipient  and 
elementary  stage.  A  distinction  must  be  made  between 
trial  itself  and  its  effects.  The  undergoing  of  trial  is  the 
intensest  moral  act  we  know  of ;  but  when  we  leave  the 
primary  stage  of  resistance  made,  strength  manifested, 
and  difficulty  overcome,  and  look  for  the  results,  we  are 
disappointed.  Virtue,  which  is  the  result  of  this  process, 
and  arises  wholly  from  effort  or  self-discipline,  is  deficient 
in  its  crowning  characteristic — its  grace,  or  what  moralists 
call  its  beauty.  It  betrays  effort,  conscious  aim  and 
design  ;  is  practised  with  too  much  apparent  system  and 
method  ;  it  wants  ease  and  naturalness ;  and  is  more  or 
less  hard,  formal,  and  artificial,  and  to  a  spectator  unat 
tractive,  which  it  is  not  its  proper  nature  to  be.  Thus, 
take  a  person  of  an  ambitious  and  assuming  habit  of  mind 
originally,  who  has  come  to  the  resolution  to  cultivate 
humility ;  how  little  progress  does  he  appear  to  make  in 
the  task  compared  with  the  sincerity  of  his  intentions. 
Whatever  acts  he  may  do  in  conformity  with  his  design, 
and  however  he  may  succeed  in  imposing  on  himself  a  cer 
tain  general  line  of  behaviour,  something  is  wanting  to 
animate  it ;  the  vital  spirit  keeps  aloof,  and  some  envious 
influence  from  original  temper  still  works  below  to  mar 
the  growth  of  discipline.  Compare  this  acquired  virtue 
with  the  natural  virtue  of  humility  as  seen  in  any  one  of 
a  gentle  and  humble  disposition  by  nature,  how  imperfect, 
how  abortive,  does  the  result  of  human  effort  appear  by 
the  side  of  the  Divine  gift  ?  Were  present  effects  alone 
to  be  considered,  it  were  better  to  be  simply  shone  upon 
by  the  creative  grace  of  Grod,  and  without  labour  of  our 


CHAP.  in.         The  Pelagian  Controversy.  67 

own  to  receive  straight  from  His  hands  an  unearned  virtue. 
And  this  poverty  in  acquired  virtues  arises  from  the  very 
fact  that  they  are  acquired,  from  the  very  manner  of  their 
growth  and  formation.  It  is  essential  to  perfect  virtue 
that  it  should  he  truly  natural  and  part  of  ourselves ;  and 
self-discipline,  care,  and  culture,  much  as  they  can  do, 
cannot  make  a  nature.  For  though  custom  is  called  a 
second  nature  to  express  its  great  power,  it  only  in  truth 
renders  natural  or  easy  to  us  the  original  act  which  it 
adopts.  And  therefore  if  this  act  is  one  of  self-control,  or 
resistance  to  evil,  it  only  renders  resistance  to  evil  easy, 
not  goodness  itself  natural.  Custom,  in  short,  improves 
a  character  upon  its  own  basis,  but  does  not  give  a  new 
one,  or  make  a  man  what  Scripture  calls  a  new  creature. 
Nor,  in  fact,  do  we  see  it  perform  even  this  inferior  function 
perfectly.  For  it  must  be  asked,  with  all  the  correcting 
force  of  custom,  where  do  we  see  in  the  world  what  may, 
in  a  thorough  sense,  be  called  renovation  of  character  ? 
Nor  do  I  mean  an  eradication  wholly  of  wrong  tendencies, 
but  even  a  complete  and  successful  suppression  of  them 
existing.  A  serious  fault  originally  attaching  to  a  charac 
ter  assumes  in  some  persons  subtler  forms  and  a  more  dis 
creet  and  politic  bearing,  and  is  finely  trained  and  educated 
rather  than  really  resisted.  In  others  it  meets  a  resist 
ance  ;  but  where  is  it  suppressed,  so  that,  after  a  life  of 
self-improvement,  we  do  not  see  it  ?  The  possibility  of 
true  mora||  renovation  is  a  truth  of  faith  rather  than  of 
experience. 

But  such  being  the  defects  inherent  in  the  system  of 
trial,  if  virtue  is  ever  to  be  perfect  and  what  it  ought  to 
be,  it  must  be  removed  from  this  basis  altogether.  It  must 
in  a  future  state  become  in  a  way  indigenous  in  us.  It 
must  become  a  nature,  an  inspiration,  a  gift ;  be  cut  away 
completely  from  the  ground  of  effort ;  and  be  like  what 
we  call  natural  goodness  here,  though  with  this  important 
difference,  that  it  will  have  been  produced  by  trial.  That 
is,  to  become  what  it  ought  to  be,  it  must  become  ne 
cessary. 

The  highest  and  the  perfect  state  of  the  will,  then,  is 
F  2 


58  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  in. 

a  state  of  necessity  ;  and  the  power  of  choice,  so  far  from 
being  essential  to  a  true  and  genuine  will,  is  its  weakness 
and  defect.  What  can  be  a  greater  sign  of  an  imperfect 
and  immature  state  of  the  will  than  that,  with  good  and 
evil  before  it,  it  should  be  in  suspense  which  to  do  ?  That 
it  should  take  the  worse  alternative  is  its  prostration  ; 
but  that  it  should  be  even  undetermined  is  weakness. 
Even  with  the  good  action  done,  does  not  a  great  sense  of 
imperfection  attend  the  thought  that  it  was  but  an  instant 
ago  uncertain  whether  it  would  be  clone  or  not  ?  And,  as 
we  dwell  in  recollection  on  the  state  of  our  will  previous 
to  its  decision,  in  that  interval  of  suspense  in  which  we 
might  have  acted  in  one  way  or  another,  does  not  so  un 
steady  and  indeterminate  a  source  of  action  interfere  even 
with  the  comfort  of  certainty  which  is  derived  from  the 
action  as  being  done?  Is  not  the  circumstance  that  it  was 
but  just  now  uncertain  whether  it  would  be  done  or  not  a 
surviving  reflection  upon  the  agent  ?  Was  it  a  sort  of  luck 
that  he  did  it  ?  And  would  he  do  it  again  if  tried  again  ? 
We  have  indeed  at  first  an  idea  that  the  power  of  choice 
is  that  which  ennobles  and  dignifies  the  will,  and  that  the 
will  would  be  an  imperfect  one  without  it :  but  this  arises 
from  a  misconception.  The  power  of  choosing  good  or  evil 
is  indeed  that  which  ennobles  the  will  of  man  as  compared 
with  the  lower  wills  of  the  brute  creation ;  but  it  is  not 
therefore  the  perfection  of  man's  will.  If  we  imagine  it 
to  be  so,  we  appear  to  attach  this  value  to*  it,  for  this 
reason,  viz.,  because  a  power  in  the  will  of  determining 
itself  either  way  is  power,  and  we  suppose  power  to  be  an 
advantage.  But  power  is  not  itself  an  advantage.  In  our 
ordinary  mode  of  speaking,  indeed,  we  regard  it  as  such  ; 
because  we  ordinarily  associate  power  with  an  advantageous 
subject-matter,  or  think  of  it  as  the  power  to  do  things 
which  are  advantageous  to  ourselves.  But  power  in  itself 
is  neither  an  advantage  nor  the  contrary,  but  depends 
entirely  on  its  object,  or  that  which  it  has  the  power  to 
do,  for  being  the  one  or  the  other.  The  power  to  do  that 
which  is  injurious  to  oneself  is  a  disadvantage,  inasmuch 
as  it  involves  the  chance  of  injury ;  and  the  power  to  do 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  69 

evil  is  the  power  to  injure  oneself.  Such  power  has  no 
more  an  advantage  as  power  than  it  has  as  liability.  It 
is  true  that,  when  the  subject-matter  of  power  is  good,  then 
the  power  to  accomplish  it  has  an  excellence  as  power  ; 
that  is  to  say,  it  is  an  additional  advantage  that  the  good 
which  happens  to  us  is  from  ourselves,  and  not  from  an 
exteinal  source.  And  on  this  ground  the  attribute  of  power 
as  belonging  to  the  Supreme  Being  is  an  excellent  attri 
bute  :  it  being  an  excellence  that  the  good  which  He  enjoys 
comes  from  Himself,  and  not  from  any  other  source. 

The  actions,  again,  which  the  good  will  perform  in  a 
future  state  of  necessity  will  not  be  the  less  good  on  that 
account,  and  because  they  do  not  proceed  from  a  power  of 
choice.  It  is  true  that  in  one  sense  a  good  act  which 
proceeds  from  the  exercise  of  a  power  of  choice  is  more 
meritorious  than  one  which  proceeds  from  a  will  acting 
necessarily  right.  If  we  measure  the  merit  of  an  action 
by  the  degree  in  which  it  is  in  advance  of  the  general 
condition  of  the  agent,  then  undoubtedly  an  action  which 
proceeds  from  a  will  determined  necessarily  to  good  has  no 
merit,  because  it  is  simply  on  a  level  with,  and  not  at  all 
in  advance  of  such  a  will.  On  the  other  hand,  an  action 
which  proceeds  from  a  will  which  has  to  exert  a  power  of 
choice  in  order  to  compass  it,  has  merit,  because  it  is  in 
advance  of  such  a  will ;  inasmuch  as  the  certainty  of  an 
action  done  is  an  advance  upon  the  mere  power  of  doing  it. 
But  it  is  evident  that  that  which  is  here  spoken  of  is  not 
the  positive  merit  of  an  action,  but  only  a  relative  one  ; 
its  merit  as  compared  with  the  condition  and  ability  of  the 
agent.  A  will  which  acts  of  necessity  for  good  is  the  very 
strongest  will  on  the  side  of  good  ;  and  therefore,  compared 
with  the  ability  of  this  agent,  a  good  act  is  a  little  result. 
A  will  which  has  to  exert  a  power  of  choice,  and  use 
struggle  and  effort,  is  a  weaker  will ;  and  therefore  a  good 
action,  as  compared  with  the  ability  of  this  agent,  is  a 
greater  result.  The  superior  merit,  then,  of  a  good  act,  in 
this  case,  is  arrived  at  by  comparing  it  with  the  weakness 
of  the  agent ;  in  the  same  way  that  the  merit  of  a  work 
of  art  is  sometimes  arrived  at  by  comparing  it  with  the 


70  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  nr. 

inferiority  of  the  instrument  by  which  it  was  executed. 
It  is  a  merit,  therefore,  which  tells  against  the  perfection 
of  the  will,  and  not  in  its  favour.  The  act,  as  such,  if  we 
can  separate  the  act  from  the  will,  is  more  meritorious  ; 
but  that  very  superior  merit  of  the  act  is  gained  at  the 
cost  of  the  will,  from  which  it  proceeds.  The  act  is  better 
because  the  agent  is  worse. 

What  has  been  said  of  natural  or  necessary  goodness 
may  be  said  of  natural  or  necessary  evil.  Amid  the 
obscurity  which  attaches  to  this  class  of  questions,  some 
thing  to  which  mankind  had  borne  large  testimony  would 
be  relinquished  in  denying  the  existence  of  bad  natural 
dispositions.  And  the  system  of  trial  points  as  much  to  a 
necessary  evil  state  as  it  does  to  a  necessary  good  one 
as  its  termination.  It  must  be  added,  that  the  law  of 
custom  unhappily  produces  much  nearer  approaches  in 
this  life  to  a  necessary  state  in  evil  than  it  does  to  the 
same  in  good ;  furnishing  a  proof  of  the  compatibleness 
of  a  necessary  with  a  culpable  or  sinful  state,  to  which 
Augustine  often  appeals  in  defending  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin  against  the  Pelagian  objection  on  that 
head.1 

The  rational  doctrine,  then,  of  voluntariness,  i.e.  how 
far  the  trial  of  the  will  is  involved  in  the  nature  of  virtue 
and  vice  is  a  modified  one.  Freewill  and  necessity  have 
both  their  place  in  it,  nor  does  it  oppose  the  necessary  to 

1  '  Consuetude  fructus  est  volun-  quo  abstinere  liberum  fuit.' — L.  1.  c. 

tatis,  quoniam  ex  voluntate  gignitur,  105.     '"  Dicis  quod  contr.-mum  sit 

quse  tamen  id  quod  agit,  negat  se  necessitas  et  voluntas,  ita  ut  se  mu- 

agere  voluntate.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  tua  impugnatione  consumant ; "  inde 

103.      The    admission     of    Julian,  nos  arguens  quod  "  alterum  alterius 

'  Evenire    hominihus    affectionalem  subdamus  effectui,  dicentes  necessi- 

qualitatem,  atque  ita  inhserescere,  ut  tatem  de  fructibus  voiuntatis  exor- 

aut  magnis  molitionibus,  aut  nullis  tarn,"  cum  videas  necessitatem  con- 

separetur  omnino,'  and  the  Pelagian  suetudinis  fructum  esse  manifestis- 

interpretation  of  the  text  Quod  nolo  simum  voiuntatis.     Nonne  quod  tibi 

malum  hoc  ago,  on  the   ground  of  impossible  risum    est,      "sua    se 

custom,   were   thus  turned  to    the  voluntas   multiplication   delevit,  et 

account   of  original  sin.     '  Ac  per  sta'tum  proprium  operata  mutavit," 

hoc  etiam   secundum  vos  peccandi  quge  multiplicata  necessitatem  con- 

necessitas   unde   abstinere    liberum  suetudinis  fecit.'— Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c. 

non  est,  illius  peccati  poena  fait,  a  103. 


CHAP.  TIL          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  7 1 

the  voluntary.  But  the  Pelagian  adopted  an  extreme 
and  unqualified  doctrine  on  this  head  ;  throwing  every 
thing  upon  the  direct  choice  or  exertion  of  the  will,  and 
separating  absolutely  the  necessary  from  the  voluntary. 
Virtue,  in  the  heavenly  state,  then,  could  be  no  virtue  in 
his  eye^,  because  it  had  ceased  to  require  effort  and  choice. 
He  allowed,  so  far  as  his  language  went,  no  room  for  an 
ultimate  and  perfect  state,  and  established  an  eternal  rest 
less  contingency  in  the  moral  world.  Not,  however,  to 
fasten  this  extreme  meaning  upon  his  language,  which 
was  perhaps  hardly  intended,  inasmuch  as  the  Pelagian 
nowhere  denies  the  received  doctrine  of  a  future  state ; 
and  understanding  him  only  to  mean  that  a  man  could  not 
be  good  or  bad  in  this  life  except  by  his  own  individual 
choice,  his  position  is  still  a  narrow  and  one-sided  one. 
The  general  sense  of  mankind  is  certainly  on  the  side  of 
there  being  good  and  bad  natural  dispositions,  and  we 
attach  the  idea  of  goodness  to  generous  excitements  and 
emotions,  which  do  not  arise  from  any  effort  of  the  will 
but  spontaneously.  The  Christian  doctrine  of  grace  which 
makes  goodness  a  divine  gift  or  inspiration  is  thus  fully  in 
accordance  with  the  instincts  of  our  nature,  while  the 
Pelagian  doctrine,  which  reduces  all  virtue  to  effort  and 
discipline,  is  felt  as  a  confinement  and  an  artificial  limit 
in  morals. 

There  are,  however,  two  distinct  questions  properly 
involved  in  this  subject ;  one,  whether  the  trial  of  the  will 
is,  as  opposed  to  implanted  dispositions,  essential  to  the 
nature  of  virtue  or  vice ;  the  other  relating  to  the  deter 
mination  of  the  will  on  its  trial, — whether  its  self-deter 
mination  is  necessary  to  the  nature  of  virtue  and  vice  as 
distinct  to  its  determination  from  without.  The  Pelagian 
thought  it  essential  that,  for  this  purpose,  the  will  should 
determine  itself,  that  virtue  and  vice,  in  order  to  be  such, 
must  be  of  our  own  originating.  S.  Augustine  maintained 
a  goodness  and  a  sinfulness  to  which  the  will  was  deter 
mined  from  without.  Both  these  positions  are  true,  if 
held  together,  and  both  false  if  held  apart. 

3.  To  the  questions  of  the  power  of  the  will,  and  the 


7  2  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  nr. 

nature  of  virtue  and  vice,  succeeded  the  question  of  the 
Divine  justice. 

The  doctrine  of  original  sin  described  all  mankind  as 
punished  for  the  sin  of  Adam,  deriving  a  positive  sinful- 
ness,  and  even  a  necessity  to  sin,  a  slavery,  and  a  captivity 
from  it.  But  how  was  it  consistent  with  justice  that  one 
man  should  be  punished  for  the  sin  of  another  ;  that  man 
kind  should  be  created  guilty,  and  derive  from  one  par 
ticular  act  committed  before  they  were  born  a  positive 
necessity  to  sin  ?  1  The  objection  of  the  Pelagian  was  met 
in  two  ways  ;  first,  by  an  appeal  to  mystery  ;  and,  secondly, 
by  an  appeal  to  facts. 

1.  The  objection  that  it  was  contrary  to  the  Divine 
justice  to  punish  one  man  for  the  sin  of  another  was  met 
by  an  appeal  to  mystery,  and  the  answer  that  the  Divine 
justice  was  incomprehensible.  And  this  was  a  sound  and 
proper  answer,  but  the  form  in  which  it  was  put  was  not 
wholly  faultless. 

For  it  is  one  thing  to  say  that  the  Divine  justice  is 
incomprehensible,  and  another  thing  to  say  that  the  Divine 
justice  is  different  from  human  justice  ;  or  that  we  are  to 
have  a  different  idea  altogether  of  justice  as  a  human  and 
as  a  Divine  characteristic.  In  saying  that  the  Divine 
justice  is  incomprehensible  we  make  no  assertion  about  it 
at  all,  and  therefore  do  not  establish  any  contradiction 
between  it  and  our  natural  ideas  of  justice.  Having  con 
ceived  of  it,  so  far  as  we  conceived  of  it  at  all,  as  the 
ordinary  natural  quality  so  called,  we  only  cease  at  a 
certain  point  to  form  any  conception  about  it.  But  to 
say  that  the  Divine  justice  is  different  from  human  is  to 
confuse  our  moral  notions  altogether.  Pressed  by  the 
Pelagian  with  the  strong  testimonies  in  Scripture  to  the 
rule  of  natural  justice,  that  no  man  should  be  punished  except 

1  'Ais  credere  te  quidem  condi-  nuum  suarum  Deus;  et  quod  per- 

torem  Deutn,sed  malorum  hominum  suasit  diabolus  teuuiter.  solerter  et 

.  .  .  .  et    Dei   sanctitati   informa-  perseveranter  fingit  et    protegit  et 

tionem    sceleris    appulisti.      Great  format  Deus.   Et  fructum  ab  horaine 

igitur   malam    Deus   et  puniuntur  bonitatis   reposcit,    cui   malum   in- 

iniipcerites  propter  quod  fecit  Deus  ;  genuit  Deus.' — Julian,  ap.  Op.  Imp. 

et  imputat  hominibus   crinien   ma-  1.  3.  c.  124.  et  sea. 


CHAP.  in.         The  Pelagian  Controversy.  73 

for  his  own  sins,  S.  Augustine  properly  appealed  to  another 
set  of  texts  which  represented  God  as  visiting  the  sins  of 
the  fathers  upon  the  children1,  and  showed  that  Scripture 
asserted  an  incomprehensible  as  well  as  a  natural  justice. 
But  he  further  proceeded  to  explain  away  these  assertions 
of  the  rule  of  natural  justice  itself,  as  intended  to  apply  to 
human,  not  to  the  Divine  conduct.  The  rule  laid  down 
in  Deuteronomy,  that  the  4  fathers  shall  not  be  put  to  death 
for  the  children,  neither  the  children  for  the  fathers,  but 
every  man  for  his  own  sin2,"  was  interpreted  as  applying 
to  human  judges  only,  not  to  God,  who  was  altogether  free 
from  such  an  obligation.3  And  the  natural  rejoinder  of 
the  Pelagian,  that  God  was  not  less  just  than  He  wanted 
man  to  be,  was  overruled  by  the  argument,  that  God  did 
many  things  which  it  would  be  wrong  for  man  to  do.4 
But  such  an  argument  was  fallacious.  The  Being  who 
gave  life  has  a  right  to  take  it  away,  and  the  supremely 
good  Being  has  a  right  to  praise  Himself ;  but  the  differ 
ence  in  the  rightfulness  of  such  acts  in  the  case  of  God  and 
man  is  not  any  difference  of  the  moral  law  by  which  God 
and  the  creature  act,  but  a  difference  in  their  respective 
positions,  which  justifies  these  acts  in  God,  and  not  in  the 
creature.  Indeed,  the  chapter  in  Ezekiel  applies  the  rule 

1  Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  30.  aliquando  contra  quse  facienda  man  - 

-  Deut.  xxiv.  16.  davit.     Nee  opus  est  ut  multa  com- 

3  Augustine :    '  Aliter   mandavit  memorem.     Mandavit  liomini  Scrip- 
homini,  aliter  judicavit  ipse.' — Op.  tura  dicens  "  nou  te  laudet  os  tuum  " 
Imp.  1.   3.  c.  33.     Julian:   '  Si  quae  (Prov.  xxvii.  2),  nectamen  dicendus 
sunt  justa  a  nobis  fieri  velit,  et  ipse  est  arrogans   aut  superbus,  cum  se 
faciat  quod  injustum  est :  justiores  innumerabiliter  laudare  non  desinit.' 
nos,  quam  ipse  est,  cupit  videri;  imo  — c.  22.     '  Hoc  judicium  Deus  ho- 
non  justioies,  sed  nos  sequos,  et  se  minum  voluit  esse  non   suum,  qui 
iuiquum.' — Julian,   ap.  Op.  Imp.  1.  dixit,   Reddam   peccata   patrum   in 
3.  c.  24.  filios.    (Deut.  v.  9.)    Quod  etiam  per 

4  '  Hoc  quidem  prseceptum  dedit  hominem  i'ecit,  quando  per  Jesum 
hominibusjudicantibus,  ne  pater  pro  Nave  non  solum  Achan,  sed  etiam 
tilio,  vel  filius  pro  patre  moreretur.  filios  ejus  occidit;  vel  per  eundem, 
Caeterum  judicia  sua  Deus  non  alii-  filios   Canaanorum   etiam   parvulos 
gavit  hac  lege.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  12.  damnavit.' — c.  30.  '  Q,uis  enim  homo 
'  Non    est   legis    suae   prsevaricator  Justus  sinit  perpetrari  scelus  quod 
Deus   quando   aliud  facit  Deus   ut  habet  in  potestate  non  sinere  ?     Et 
Deus,  aliud  imperat  homini  ut  ho-  tamen  sinit  haec  Deus.' — c.  24. 
mini?' — c.  23.     'Facit  enim  Deus 


74  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  in. 

of  natural  justice  directly  to  the  Divine  conduct,  and 
represents  God  as  asserting  of  Himself,  that  He  punishes 
no  man  except  for  his  own  sins,  and  so  gives  no  ground 
whatever  for  such  a  distinction.  But  this  declaration  was  not 
allowed  its  obvious  interpretation,  as  stating  a  universal 
law  of  the  Divine  dealings,  but  only  a  special  prophetical 
one,  as  alluding  to  the  Divine  mercy  under  the  gospel 
dispensation  and  the  covenant  of  grace,1  under  wh'ich  the 
effect  of  original  sin,  the  punishment  of  mankind  for  the 
sin  of  their  first  parent,  was  removed. 

But  the  punishment  which  all  mankind  suffered  for  the 
sin  of  Adam  was  punishment  of  a  peculiar  kind ;  because 
it  was  not  only  pain  but  sin,  and  not  only  sin  but  captivity 
to  sin  and  inability  to  do  any  good  thing.  This  worst  and 
strongest  penalty,  then,  attaching  to  the  sin  of  Adam,  was 
defended  by  an  appeal  to  a  remarkable  law  of  (rod's 
judicial  administration,  discernible  in  his  natural  provi 
dence,  and  specially  attested  by  Scripture ;  the  rule,  >viz. 
of  punishing  sin  by  further  $\\\,peccatum  pcena  peccati, — 
a  rule  which,  in  the  present  instance,  only  received  a 
mysterious  application,  as  being  extended  to  the  case  of  a 
mysterious  and  incomprehensible  sin. 

S.  Augustine  argued,  then,  that  original  sin  was  real 
sin  in  the  being  in  whom  it  resided ;  and  being  such,  was 
justly  punishable  by  the  abandonment  of  the  person  guilty 
of  it,  to  sin ;  that  the  natural  man,  therefore,  could  not 
plead  his  want  of  moral  power  as  any  excuse  for  his  sins, 
any  more  than  a  man  in  common  life,  who  had  contracted 
a  bad  habit,  could  plead  the  dominion  of  that  habit  as 
such  an  excuse.  That  bad  habit  might  be  so  strong  that 
he  could  not  help  committing  the  sins  to  which  it  inclined 

1  '  Hsec  per  Ezechielem  proplie-  dicatur  .  .  .  .  "  Non  dicetur   in   Is. 

tarn  promissio  est  novi  Testament!,  rael"  recte  diceres, si  veros Israelites 

quam  non  intelligis,  ubi  Deus  re-  regenerates  videres    in   quibus  hoc 

generates   a   generatis    si    jam    in  non  dicetur.' — c.  39.  41.     Jeremiah 

majoribus  setatibus  sunt,  secundum  xxxi.  21 — 32.  is  adduced  to  confirm 

propria  facta  discernit.' — Op.  Imp.  this  interpretation.     '  In  diebus  illis 

1.   3.  c.   38.     '"Si   dicetur  amplius  non  dicent   ultra.     Patres  comede- 

parabola "  :  .  .  .  non     arguit    quia  runt,'  &c. — c.  84.     See  Contra  Jul. 

dicebatur,   sed    permittit    ubi    non  Pel.  1.  6.  n.  82. 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  75 

him  ;  but  he  was  responsible  for  those  sins,  in  that  he  was 
responsible  for  their  cause.  In  like  manner,  man  was 
responsible  for  the  sins  which  in  the  state  of  original  sin 
he  could  not  avoid,  in  that  he  was  responsible  for  original 
sin  itself.1 

Two  difficulties,  however,  presented  themselves  to  the 
application  of  such  a  law  to  the  case  of  original  sin.  In 
the  first  place,  though  it  is  true  that  all  sin,  so  far  as  it  is 
indulged,  predisposes  the  mind  to  further  sin,  or  creates 
a  sinful  habit,  this  effect  is  in  proportion  to  the  amount 
of  such  indulgence ;  and  it  is  only  extreme  indulgence 
that  produces  an  uncontrollable  habit,  or  a  loss  of  freewill : 
whereas  the  sin  of  our  first  parents,  to  which  this  extreme 
effect  was  attached,  was  but  a  single  sin,  and  not  appar 
ently  a  heinous  one.  But  the  sin  of  our  first  parents,  it 
was  replied,  was  neither  a  single  nor  a  light  one.  The 
outward  act  was  but  the  consummation  of  a  course  of 
inward  sin,  self-pleasing,  pride,  and  departure  from  God. 
And,  even  were  its  subject-matter  light,  the  sin  itself  was 
disobedience  ;  the  more  wanton,  that  there  was  no  strength 
of  passion  as  yet  in  man's  nature  to  excuse  it.  Who  would 
measure  the  greatness  of  a  first  sin  as  being  the  first,  a 
departure  from  created  rectitude,  the  primary  act  of  the 
will  for  evil,  to  which  no  previous  evil  predisposed  ?  But 
the  subject-matter  was  only  externally  light,  not  really, 
being  not  a  mere  fruit  of  a  tree,  but  good  out  of  their 
existing  state  of  union  with  God,  which  was  grasped  at ; 
showing  a  greediness  for  which  Grod  did  not  suffice  ;  and 
that  alien  good  being,  moreover,  the  presumptuous  position 

1  '  Sed  vos  ista  peccata  ex  illis  liberum  non  est,  illius  peccati  poena 

venire  peccatis  quse  nulla  necessitate  fuit  a  quo  abstinere  liberum   fuit, 

commissa  sunt,  in  illo   saltern  con-  quando  nullum  pondus  necessitatis 

ceditis,  qui  dicit,  "Quod  nolo  malum  urgcbat.      Cur    ergo    non    creditis 

hoc  ago."  Qui  enim,  ut  istam  patiatur  tantum  saltern  valuisse  illud  primi 

necessitatem,  non  nisi  peccandi  con-  hominis  ineffabiliter  grande  pecca- 

suetudine    premitur,   procul    dubio  turn,  ut  eo  vitiaretur  humana  natura 

priusquam  peccaret,  nondum  necessi-  tiniversa,  quantum    valet    nunc   in 

tate  consuetudinis  premebatur.     Ac  homine  uno  secunda  natura?  ' — Op. 

per  hoc,  etiam  secundum  vos,  pec-  Imp.  1.  i.  c.  105. 
candi     necessitas     unde    abstinere 


76  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  in. 

of  being  gods  themselves — a  pride  which  was  the  very 
counterpart  of  our  Lord's  humility,  who  emptied  Himself 
of  a  Divinity  which  was  His  right,  while  they  grasped  at  a 
divinity  to  which  they  had  none.1 

But,  however  serious  the  sin  of  our  first  parents  might 
be,  a  much  greater  difficulty  presented  itself  in  the  question 
how  individuals  could  be  responsible  for  a  sin  to  which  they 
were  not  themselves  personally  parties.  But  this  difficulty 
was  overruled  by  an  appeal  to  the  doctrine  of  original  sin 
itself,  which  rested  upon  Scripture,  and  the  very  foundation 
of  which  was,  that  all  men  had  in  some  sense  sinned  in 
Adam.  This  was,  indeed  a  mystery,  and  beyond  our  com 
prehension,  but  faith  accepted  it  as  true ;  and  if  true,  the 
basis  which  this  argument  required  was  supplied  to  it. 
Such  an  explanation  was  only  the  application  to  a  mys 
terious  subject-matter  of  a  law,  which  we  recognise  as  just 
in  that  sphere  of  providence  which  comes  under  our  know 
ledge.  We  see  the  justice  of  the  law  that  sin  hardens  the 
heart,  as  applied  to  the  case  of  actual  sin  because  we  know 
the  sin ;  we  see  a  justice  in  such  sin,  long  indulged,  leading 
to  actual  slavery  and  loss  of  freewill :  but  the  justice  of  this 
law  as  applied  to  the  case  of  original  sin  was  a  mysterious 
and  incomprehensible  justice,  that  which  is  its  subject- 
matter  being  a  mysterious  and  incomprehensible  sin. 

\Yhen  S.  Augustine,  however,  left  the  ground  of  mystery 
for  that  of  reasoning,  he  adopted  doubtful  positions.  The 
appeal  to  the  Divine  foreknowledge  of  men's  evil  lives, 
in  spite  of  which  He  creates  them,  as  a  defence  of  a  creation 

1  '  In  occulto  autem  mali  esse  9.  '  Tanto  graving  peccavit  quanto 

cceperunt,  ut  in  apertam  inobedien-  ibi  major  nou  peccandi  facilitas  erat, 

tiam  laberentur.'— De  Civit.  Dei,  1.  ubi  vitiata  natura  nondum  erat.'— 

xiv.  c.l 3.  et  seq.^  ^ Quantum  malum  Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  189.  '  Tanta  im- 

spla  inobedientia.'— De  Gen.  ad  pietate  peccavit  quantam  nos  metiri 

iteram,  1.  8.  c.  13.  'Noluithomo  atque  sestimare  non  possumus.'— 

inter  dehcias  paradisi  servare  jus-  Ibid.  1.  3.  c.  65.  'Illius  natura 

titiam.'— De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Remiss.  quanto  magis  sublimiter  stabat, 

1.  Z.  n.  55.  '  Quid  avanus  illo  cui  tanto  magis  graviter  occidit 

i)eus  sufficere  non  potuit.'— In  Ep.  Peccatum  quanto  incredibilius,  tanto 

Joannis  ad  Parthos,  Tr.  8.  n.  6.  damnabilius.'— Ibid.  1.  6.  c.  22.  See 

Kapere  voluerunt  divinitatem,  per-  Bull  on  the  State  of  Man  before  the 

iderunt  fehcitatem.'— In  Tr.  68.  n.  Fall,  vol.  ii.  (Oxford  ed.)  p.  64. 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy. 


77 


under  a  necessity  to  evil,  was  plausible 1 ;  but  there  is 
plainly  a  difference  between  exposing  men  to  the  risk,  and 
subjecting  them  to  the  certainty  of  moral  evil,  and  that 
evil  in  some  cases  eternal.  The  issue  being  alike  foreseen 
in  both  cases  ;  in  the  one  the  sinner  has  had  the  opportunity 
of  a  better  issue  given  him,  and  has  therefore  only  himself 
to  blame  for  the  worse  one  ;  in  the  other  he  has  had  no 
such  opportunity.  The  appeal  to  God's  natural  providence 
and  his  support  and  nourishment  of  evil  men  in  the  world 
as  an  analogous  case  to  the  creation  of  men  as  evil,  was 
still  more  incorrect.2 

2.  The  objection  to  the  punishment  of  mankind  for  the 
sin  of  Adam,  on  the  score  of  the  Divine  justice,  was  an 
swered  by  an  appeal  to  facts ;  an  appeal  which  divided  into 
two  great  heads — the  fact  of  sin,  and  the  fact  of  pain. 

First,  how  were  we  to  account  for  the  fact  of  sin,  as  it 

1  '  Ut  quid  creat  quos  impios 
futures  et  damnandos  esse  prsescivit.' 
—Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  48.,  vid.  119. 
121;  1.  5.  c.  13. 

The  argument,  however,  with  a 
modification,  may  claim  the  more 
recent  authority  of  Archbp.  Whately, 
who  says :  '  We  should  be  very 
cautious  how  we  employ  such  wea 
pons  as  may  recoil  upon  ourselves 
.  .  .  Why  the  Almighty  does  not 
cause  to  die  in  the  cradle  every 
infant  whose  future  wickedness  and 
misery,  if  suffered  to  grow  up,  He 
foresees,  is  what  no  system  of  re 
ligion,  natural  or  revealed,  will 
enable  us  satisfactorily  to  account 
for.'— Essays  on  S.  Paul,  p.  88.  But 
is  there  not  some  confusion  of 
thought  in  this  argument  ?  As 
stated  by  S.  Augustine,  it  is  inform 
absurd.  For  the  difficulty  in  the 
constitution  of  things  which  he  sets 
against  that  of  reprobation,  or 
creating  a  being  to  be  eternally 
miserable,  is  this,  that  God  foresees 
men's  evil  lives  and  their  judicial 
result,  and  i/et  creates  them.  But  if 
God  forsees  men's  evil  lives,  He  by 
the  hypothesis  creates  them,  and  it 


would  be  a  contradiction  that  He 
should  not.  Facts  cannot  first  be 
foreseen,  and  then  because  they  a,re 
foreseen  be  prevented.  Archbishop 
Whately,  however,  relieves  the  ar 
gument  from  this  absurdity,  by 
making  foresight  to  be  the  foresight 
"  of  men's  future  wickedness  and 
misery  if  suffered  to  grow  up"  But 
what  can  be  meant  by  the  foresight 
of  events  which,  by  the  very  suppo 
sition,  may  not  take  place  ?  This 
alleged  difficulty,  then,  in  the  con 
stitution  of  things,  cannot  be  stated 
without  a  great  absurdity  and  con 
tradiction  ;  whereas  the  difficulty  of 
God  creating  a  being  to  be  eternally 
miserable  is  as  plain  and  simple  a 
one  as  can  be  conceived. 

2  '  Sic  creat  malos  quomodo  pascit 
et  nutrit  malos.' — De  Nupt.  et  Cone. 
1.  2.  n.  32,  33.  Julian  :  '  Quod  pascit 
Deus  etiam  peccatores,  benignusque 
est  super  ingratos  et  malos  pietatis 
est  ejus  testimonium  non  maligni- 
tatis.  .  .  .  Vide  ergo  quarn  nescias 
quid  loqueris,  qui  de  exemplo  miseri- 
cordiae  voluisti  crudelitatem  pro- 
bare.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  64. 


7  8  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  m. 

met  us  in  the  world— the  universal  depravation  and  cor 
ruption  of  mankind?  could  we  account  for  this  by  chance, 
or  the  contingent  action  of  each  man's  freewill  ?  Or  did  it 
not  at  once  point  to  some  law  in  our  nature,  on  the  same 
principle  on  which,  in  the  physical  world  and  common  life, 
whenever  we  see  a  uniform  set  of  phenomena,  we  refer  them 
to  some  law  ? 

The  argument,  however,  for  original  sin  derived  from 
the  prevalence  of  actual  sin  in  the  world,  though  un 
doubtedly  sound  and  unanswerable,  requires  some  caution 
and  discrimination  in  the  use  of  it.  And  in  the  first  place 
it  must  be  observed  that,  when  we  examine  this  argument, 
we  find,  that  upon  a  nearer  view  it  divides  into  two  dis 
tinct  arguments,  depending  upon  two  different  kinds  of 
reasoning.  One  is  the  argument  simply  of  cause  and  effect. 
On  the  principle  that  every  event  must  have  a  cause,  actual 
sin  must  have  a  cause  anterior  to  itself,  from  which  it 
proceeds:  and  for  the  same  reason  that  this  cause  is  wanted 
itself,  another  cause  is  wanted  for  it,  and  so  another  and 
another  in  succession,  till  we  arrive  at  some  origin  or  first 
cause  of  sin.  But  this  origin  of  sin  cannot  be  in  the 
Divine  will,  it  must  therefore  be  in  the  human;  which 
ultimate  and  original  evil  in  the  will  is  what  is  signified 
by  original  sin. 

This  argument,  then,  for  original  sin,  does  not  at  all 
depend  on  the  amount  of  actual  sin  in  the  world,  but  would 
be  just  as  valid  on  the  supposition  of  one  sin,  as  on  that  of 
universal ;  original  sin  itself  following  from  the  simple  fact 
of  actual,  though  its  universality  depends  on  the  univer 
sality  of  actual.  And  the  validity  of  this  argument  depends 
on  the  validity  of  the  general  argument  of  cause  and  effect, 
or  upon  the  truth  of  the  axiom,  that  every  event  must  have 
a  cause, — an  axiom  which  I  discussed  in  the  last  chapter, 
when  I  defined  the  degree  and  measure  of  truth  which 
belonged  to  it.  It  will  be  enough  to  say  here  of  this 
rationale  of  original  sin,  that  it  is  a  wholly  philosophical, 
as  distinguished  from  a  scriptural  one  ;  because,  in  repre 
senting  original  sin  as  anterior  to  all  actual  sin,  it  repre 
sents  it  as  anterior  to  the  sin  of  Adam,  and  as  much  the 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  79 

condition  of  man  at  his  first  creation  as  it  ever  was  after 
wards.1 

The  other  and  the  more  common  argument,  is  the 
argument  of  probability, — that  it  is  contrary  to  the  doc 
trine  of  chances,  that  every  one  of  those  innumerable 
millions  that  have  lived  in  the  world  should  have  been  a 
sinner,  if  such  sin  had  depended  on  the  mere  contingency 
of  every  individual's  freewill ;  such  a  universal  fact  evi 
dently  proving  the  existence  of  some  law  of  sin  in  our 
nature.  But  the  correctness  of  this  argument  for  original 
sin  depends  on  the  sense  in  which  we  understand  sin  in  the 
preliminary  statement,  that  every  one  of  the  human  race 
has  been,  and  is,  a  sinner. 

If  by  sin  is  meant  here  the  absence  of  perfection  only — 
that  every  man  that  has  ever  lived  has  done  something 
wrong  in  the  course  of , his  life,  there  appears  to  be  nothing, 
even  in  a  universal  faultiness  of  the  human  race,  in  such  a 
sense,  more  than  may  be  accounted  for  on  the  principle  of 
each  man's  contingent  will,  or  that  requires  the  operation 
of  a  law.  For,  considering  the  length  of  human  life,  the 
constant  succession  of  temptations  in  it,  and  their  variety, 
the  multiplicity  of  relations  in  which  a  man  stands  to  others, 
all  of  which  have  to  be  fulfilled  in  order  to  constitute  him 
faultless,  is  there  anything  very  remarkable  in  the  coinci 
dence  that  every  man  should,  on  some  occasion  or  other  in 
his  life,  have  diverged  from  the  strict  duty  ?  If,  on  the  one 
hand,  it  may  be  said,  that  out  of  so  great  a  number  of  in 
dividuals  as  there  have  been  in  the  world  some  few  perfect 
men  might  have  been  calculated  upon ;  on  the  other  hand, 
it  may  be  said  that,  with  so  Vast  a  number  of  trials,  we 
could  not  calculate  any  one's  universal  success  under  them. 
The  chances  in  favour  of  cases  of  perfection  which  the 
number  of  individuals  in  the  world  presents,  are  met  by 
the  chances  against  it,  contained  in  the  number  of  trials 
in  the  life  of  each  individual. 

But  if  by  sin  we  understand  not  only  a  loss  of  perfection, 

1  Mr.  Coleridge,  in  his  '  Aids  to       his  usual  mixture  of  obscurity  and 
Keflection,'  adopts  this  rationale  of      power.     See  NOTE  XII. 
original  sin,  and  discusses   it  with 


8o  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  in. 

but  positive  depravity,  certainly  the  general  fact  of  sin  in 
this  sense  cannot  be  accounted  for  on  the  mere  principle 
of  contingency.  Supposing  ourselves  calculating  before 
hand  the  result  of  the  action  of  freewill  in  the  human  race, 
we  should  have  no  more  right  to  calculate  on  general  de 
pravity  and  wickedness  as  the  result,  than  on  general  piety 
and  virtue.  Undoubtedly  there  is  this  important  distinc 
tion  between  vice  and  virtue,  that  vice  is  pleasant,  and 
virtue  painful  at  the  time  ;  and  it  maybe  thought  perhaps 
that,  in  making  any  calculations  beforehand  as  to  the  con 
duct  of  mankind,  we  should  be  justified  in  expecting  that 
the  generality  would  do  what  was  easiest  at  the  time.  But 
if  anyone  will  examine  the  real  ground  on  which  he  forms 
this  expectation,  he  will  find  that  he  forms  it  upon  the 
experience  of  the  result,  and  not  upon  any  ground  of 
antecedent  calculation.  He  sees  that  this  is  the  general 
way  in  which  mankind  act,  and,  therefore,  he  imagines 
himself  expecting  it  beforehand.  But  it  is  evident  that, 
in  calculating  the  conduct  of  mankind  beforehand,  we 
should  have  no  more  right  to  calculate  on  a  general  pre 
ference  of  present  to  future  interests,  than  on  a  general 
contrary  preference.  The  choice  that  freewill  would  make 
in  the  matter  would  be  as  probable  one  way  as  another. 

Understanding  sin,  then,  in  the  sense  of  depravity  and 
wickedness,  the  general  fact  of  human  sinfulness  in  this 
sense  certainly  requires  some  law  of  sin  in  our  nature  as  its 
explanation ;  such  a  law  as  is  asserted  in  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin.  But  while  such  a  fact  must  be  allowed  as  a 
proof  of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  it  must  at  the  same 
time  be  remembered,  that  the  assertion  of  general  depravity 
and  wickedness  is  a  very  grave  assertion  to  make  respecting 
the  human  race.  It  is  an  assertion,  however,  which  rests 
on  a  ground  of  actual  observation  and  experience,  confirmed 
by  the  authority  of  Scripture,  and  is  true  in  two  different 
ways. 

First,  every  man  is  depraved  in  the  sense  of  having 
vile,  selfish,  and  proud  desires,  which  have  a  certain  power 
over  him,  and  occupy  and  fill  his  mind  with  sufficient 
strength  and  frequency  to  constitute  a  depraved  condition 


CHAP.  ni.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  8 1 

of  mind.  A  certain  tendency  to  evil  is  indeed  no  more 
than  what  is  necessary  to  constitute  a  state  of  trial,  and 
does  not  show  depravity  or  corruption  in  the  moral  being. 
But  it  is  evident  that  evil  desire,  in  the  degree  in  which 
it  exists  in  human  nature,  is  more  than  such  a  tendency  as 
this,  and  is  in  itself  a  disease  ;  inasmuch  as  men  feel  it  as 
something  sinful  in  itself,  independent  of  its  gratification. 
Test  even  the  best  of  men,  with  this  strength  of  evil  desire 
residing  in  him,  by  a  perfect  standard,  and  it  must  be  seen 
that  he  is  a  corrupt  being,  whom  we  can  only  think  of  at 
all  as  good  by  a  kind  of  anticipation,  regarding  this  as  a 
transient  condition  of  mind,  of  which  he  is  one  day  to  be 
relieved.  In  the  sense,  then,  of  having  concupiscence, 
which  hath  of  itself  the  nature  of  sin,  all  mankind  are 
depraved. 

Secondly,  the  generality  of  mankind  are  depraved  in 
the  sense  of  actual  bad  life  and  conduct ;  as  the  former  was 
a  fact  of  inward  experience,  this  latter  being  a  fact  of 
observation.  The  wickedness  of  the  generality  of  mankind 
was  acknowledged  even  by  the  heath  en,  and  has  been  gene 
rally  admitted.  It  is  proved,  therefore,  in  the  only  way  in 
which  a  general  fact  admits  of  being  proved,  viz.  by  large 
general  and  consentient  observation  ;  observation,  more 
over,  which,  when  once  made,  keeps  its  ground,  and  meets 
with  comparatively  little  contradiction.  It  is,  moreover, 
strongly  asserted  in  Scripture,  which  refers  to  it,  however, 
as  a  known  and  ascertained  fact,  rather  than  professes  to 
reveal  it  in  the  first  instance.  Such  being  the  case,  it  is 
evident,  even  supposing  particular  persons  should  say  that 
their  own  observation  had  been  otherwise,  that  their  indi 
vidual  testimony  is  no  counterbalance  to  the  general  obser 
vation  of  mankind.  And  though  the  reluctance  of  all 
persons  to  form  judgments  upon  their  relations,  friends,  and 
acquaintances  may  be  appealed  to,  as  counter-evidence  on 
this  subject,  it  should  be  remembered  that  a  judgment  of 
charity  does  not  supersede  that  of  observation. 

Secondly,  the  defence  of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  on 
the  ground  of  fact,  from  the  objection  urged  on  the  score 
of  the  Divine  justice,  appealed  straight  to  the  great  fact  of 

G 


g2  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  m. 

pain  and  misery  in  the  world.  How  was  this  to  be  accounted 
for  ?  It  could  not  be  accounted  for  on  the  ground  of  men's 
actual  sins,  because  it  was  evidently  a  part  of  the  present 
constitution  of  nature,  and  in  the  case  of  infants  preceded 
actual  sin.  Anyhow,  then,  we  were  in  a  difficulty  with 
respect  to  the  Divine  justice ;  for  if  we  gave  up  the  doctrine 
of  original  sin,  there  was  nothing  to  account  for  this  fact, 
and  the  charge  of  injustice  could  be  brought  against  God 
for  an  undeserved  infliction  of  pain.1 

The  argument,  however,  which  infers  sin  from  pain, 
should  be  used  with  caution ;  we  do  not  know  enough  of 
the  whole  scheme  of  things  to  decide  whether,  distinct  from 
judicial  grounds,  pain  may  not  be  necessary  simply  as  a 
preparation  and  training  for  a  higher  state  of  existence. 
That  kind  of  pain  which  is  involved  in  effort  and  the  over 
coming  of  difficulty  we  do  not  naturally  regard  as  at  all  of 
necessity  judicial;  and  S.  Augustine  exceeds  the  limits  of 
a  common  sense  judgment,  when  he  appeals  to  the  slow 
and  gradual  growth  of  the  understanding  in  man,  the  im 
becility  of  infancy,  and  the  difficulties  which  accompany 
the  progress  of  education,  as  evidences  of  the  Divine  wrath.2 
But  pain  of  the  positive  and  acute  kind  certainly  suggests 

1  S.  Augustine,  in  Op.  Imp.  1.1.  2  '  Sed  illi  parvuli  nee  flerent  in 

c,  92.,  1.  2.  c.  89.  104.  116.  124.  139.  paradise,   nee  muti  essent,   nee  ali- 

144.,  1.  3.  c.  7.  48.  89.  95.  154.  198.,  quando  uti  ratione  non  possent,  nee 

1.  5.  c.  1.,  1.  6.  c.  7-  9.,  and  passim,  morbis  affligerentur,  nee   a   bestiis 

refers  to  the  general  fact  of  human  laederentur  ....  nee  surgentes  in 

misery  as  a  proof  of  original  sin :  pueritiam    domarentur    verberibus, 

'  Teste  ipsa  generis  humani  miseria  aut  erudirentur  laboribus.'—Op.  Imp. 

peccatum    originale   monstratur.' —  1.  3.  c.  198.     '  Omnibus  cogenita  est 

L.  3.  c.  89.     '  Constat  mala  hujus  qusedam  tarditas  mentis,  qua  et  hi 

vitae     quibus    plenus    est    mundus  qui  appellantur  ingeniosi,  non  sine 

Manichaeos  cum  Catholicisconfiteri :  aliqua  laboris   serumna,    vel   quas- 

sed  undo  sint  haec  non  utrosque  idem  cunque   artes,   vel   eas   etiam   quas 

dicere :   quod  ea  Manichaei  tribuunt  liberales  nuncupant  discunt  .... 

alienee  naturae  malae,  Catholici  vero  Si   in   paradiso   aliquid  disceretur, 

et  bonae   et    nostrae ;    sed    peccato  quod  illi  vitas  esset  utile  scire,  sine 

vitiatse,  meritoque  punitae.'— L.  6.  c.  ullo  labore  aut  dolore  id  assequere- 

14.    'Si  parvuli  sine  ullius  peccati  tur  beata  natura,  vel  Deo  docente 

meritopremunturgravijugo,iniquus  vel  seipsa.  Unde  quis  non  intelligat 

est  Deus.' — L.  2.  c.  124.     '  Si  ergo  in  hac  vita  etiam  tormenta  discen- 

nulum  esset  in  parvulis  ex  origine  tium  ad  miserias  hujus  sasculi,  quod 

meritum  malum,  quicquid  mail  pati-  ex  uno  in  condemnationem  propaga- 

nntnr  esset  injustum.'— L.  3L  c.  204.  turn  est,  pertinere.' — L.  6.  c.  9. 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  83 

a  judicial  source  ;  nor  can  we  reflect  on  the  dreadful  forms 
of  misery  and  the  diseases,  bodily  and  mental,  which  attach 
to  human  nature,  without  being  led  instinctively  to  the 
idea  of  some  moral  evil  residing  in  that  nature.  It  admits 
perhaps  of  a  doubt,  whether  the  overwhelming  nature  of 
present  pain,  whether  as  a  sight  or  feeling,  does  not  dis 
order  us  as  judges  on  such  a  question ;  nor  can  we  say  for 
certain  that,  supposing  ourselves  to  be  looking  back  from 
the  immense  distance  of  a  happy  eternity  upon  the  pains 
of  this  mortal  life,  the  greatest  amount  of  these  might  not 
appear  so  small  in  comparison  with  the  happiness  which 
had  succeeded  them,1  that  they  might  be  regarded,  then, 
as  a  simple  preparation  for  and  introduction  to  futurityr 
and  accounted  for  on  that  ground,  superseding  the  judicial 
one.  The  common  spectacle  of  human  misery,  however, 
has,  in  fact,  impressed  the  religious  portion  of  the  world 
in  all  ages,  Christian  or  pagan,  in  the  latter  way  ;  and 
the  general  feeling  of  mankind  has  connected  it  with  some 
deep  though  undefined  root  of  sin  in  the  human  race. 

Thus  maintained  and  defended  on  the  several  grounds 
of  the  power  of  the  will,  the  nature  of  virtue  and  vice,  and 
the  Divine  justice,  the  Catholic  doctrine  of  original  sin 
adopted,  as  an  account  of  the  existence  of  evil,  a  middle 
ground  between  two  extreme  theories  on  either  side,  which 
prevailed  in  the  world.  According  to  the  Manichean  theory, 
evil  was  an  original  substance  in  nature,  coeval  with  the 
Divine.  It  was  therefore  an  ineradicable,  unconquerable 
thing ;  for  though  some  triumph  over  the  Gentes  tenebrarum 
was  talked  of,  a  part  of  the  Divine  nature  was  irrevocably 
polluted  in  the  contest.  The  practical  meaning  of  this 
theory  was,  that  the  world  was  a  mixture ;  that  good  and 
evil  had  gone  on  together  in  it  from  all  eternity,  and  would 
to  all  eternity  continue  to  do  so ;  that  things  were  what 
they  were,  and  that  there  was  no  altering  them  ; — much 
the  view  taken  by  practical  worldly  men,  who  cannot  per 
suade  themselves  to  believe  that  there  is  such  a  thing  as 

1  '  'Eo'Awi'  yap  VTTO  'xp.p\i.far<av  "Orav  ©eat)  fioipa  W/MTTJ 

'Ape«as  o\€ ov  tyri\6v.' 

PINDAB.  Olymp.  2. 

a  2 


84.  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  m. 

pure  good,  the  whole  of  experience  going  so  much  against 
it,  and  therefore  virtually  disbelieve  in  Him  who  is  abso 
lute  goodness.  The  other  extreme  theory  was  the  Pelagian, 
which  accounted  tor  the  universal  corruption  of  the  world 
simply  upon  the  ground  of  each  individual's  will ;  and  the 
practical  tendency  of  the  Pelagian,  as  of  the  Manichean 
theory,  was  to  carelessness  and  indifference  ;  attributing  too 
slight  a  power  to  sin  over  the  liberty  of  the  will,  and  so 
lowering  our  idea  of  the  nature  of  sin  ;  as  the  other  gave  it 
too  much,  and  so  abandoned  us  to  it.  Between  these  two 
theories  the  Church  has  taken  the  middle  line,  denying 
evil  to  be  original  in  the  universe,  but  asserting  it  to  be 
original  in  our  present  nature ;  giving  it  a  voluntary  be 
ginning  but  a  necessary  continuance,  and  a  descent,  when 
once  begun,  by  a  natural  law.  This  mixture  and  balance 
of  voluntariness  and  necessity  makes  up  the  doctrine  of 
original  sin ;  and  the  practical  impression  it  leaves,  is  that 
of  the  deep  and  awful  nature,  but  not  the  dominance  of  sin. 
And  thus  S.  Augustine  was  enabled,  in  answer  to  the 
Pelagian  charge  of  Manicheanism,  to  appeal  to  his  doctrine 
as  a  safeguard  against  that  system.  The  facts  of  the  world 
drove  the  Manichean  into  blasphemy  and  a  denial  of  the 
Divine  omnipotence  ;  but  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  ac 
counted  for  these  facts  in  a  way  which  saved  at  once  the 
Divine  justice  and  the  Divine  power.  It  attributed  evil, 
moral  and  physical,  to  the  wilful  act  of  man  ;  thus  separat 
ing  it  from  the  essence  of  his  nature,  and  dislodging  it  as 
a  substance  in  the  universe,  while  it  accounted  judicially 
for  the  pains  of  this  present  life.1  * 

III.  The  main  arguments  of  Pelagianism  being  stated 2, 
it  remains  to  notice  the  bearing  of  this  system  upon  the 
Catholic  doctrines  of  the  Original  State  of  man,  the  Incar 
nation,  and  the  Atonement. 

1.  Scripture  represents  the  original  state  of  man  as 
one  of  innocence  and  goodness,  and  as  blessed  with  a  cor- 

1  Op.  Imp.   1.    3.   c.    170—177.       Pelagian   interpreted   the   texts  of 
186.;  1.  4.  c.  2.;  1.   5.  c.  30.  56.;       Scripture  bearing  on  the  doctrine  of 

b-  c-  7-  9.  original  sin,  see  NOTE  XIII. 

2  -bor  the  mode   in  which   the 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  85 

responding  happiness.  He  comes  from  the  hands  of  his 
Maker  an  upright  being,  and  he  is  placed  in  the  garden  of 
Eden,  where  he  is  surrounded  with  all  that  can  please  the 
senses  and  satisfy  the  mind  of  a  creature  thus  constituted. 
And  revelation  is  here  confirmed  by  general  tradition.  The 
legend  of  the  golden  age  goes  back  to  a  primitive  state  of 
our  nature,  in  which  it  was  both  good  and  happy. 

Such  an  original  moral  disposition  of  man  again  involves 
a  certain  measure  of  stability  and  strength  in  the  formation 
of  it ;  such  a  character  implies  a  certain  degree  of  depth, 
with  which  it  is  stamped  upon  human  nature.  Jt  may  be 
said  that  a  being  is  good  till  he  has  sinned  ;  and  that,  con 
sequently,  if  he  is  endowed  simply  with  freewill  at  his 
creation,  he  is  created  a  good  being.  But  it  may  be 
doubted  whether  freewill  of  itself,  and  prior  to  its  deter 
mination  to  good,  can  be  called  goodness1 :  at  any  rate,  the 
possession  of  it  alone  affords  no  reason  for  a  state  of  good 
ness  lasting  beyond  the  first  moment  of  creation  ;  and 
therefore  we  are  evidently  intended  to  regard  man's  original 
state  of  uprightness  as  something  more  than  the  mere  state 
of  freewill.  Man's  uprightness,  however,  being  this  farther 
state,  whatever  we  may  call  it ;  the  support  and  continuance 
of  this  state  depended  upon  freewill  in  a  being  not  yet  per 
fected  but  on  his  trial.  It  thus  became  an  object  of  atten 
tion  in  Catholic  theology  to  define,  under  this  balance  of 
considerations,  with  as  much  accuracy  as  the  subject  ad 
mitted  of,  what  was  the  condition  of  Adam  before  the  fall, 
in  respect  of  goodness  on  the  one  side,  and  liability  to  sin 
on  the  other. 

On  the  one  hand,  then,  it  was  determined  that  Adam 
could  not  have  concupiscence  or  lust,  i.e.  the  direct  inclina 
tion  to  evil ;  that  positive  appetite  and  craving  for  corrupt 
pleasure  which  is  now  the  incentive  to  sin  in  our  nature ; 
for  this  would  be  to  make  no  difference  between  man  un- 
fallen  and  fallen.  There  was  no  positive  contrariety  as  yet 
between  the  flesh  and  the  spirit ;  and  the  inward  struggle, 
which  is  now  the  normal  condition  of  man,  was  alien  to  a 

1  An  rectus  erat  non  habens  bilitatem  ? — Op.  Imp.  5.  57.  See 
vvoluntatem  bonam  sed  ejus  possi-  NOTE  XIV. 


86  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  in. 

nature  made  harmonious  and  at  peace  with  itself.1  On  the 
other  hand,  Adam  must  have  had  a  tendency  of  some  kind 
toward  evil,  in  order  to  be  in  a  state  of  trial  at  all.2  There 
remained,  then,  the  conclusion,  of  an  indirect  or  distant 
tendency  to  evil  in  Adam.  A  regular  and  formed  virtuous 
habit  of  mind,  or,  as  S.  Augustine  calls  it,  a  goodivill,im- 
planted  in  him  to  begin  with  by  God,  intervened  between 
him  and  sin,  and  stood  as  a  barrier  against  any  strong  and 
disturbing  force  of  temptation.  Suppose  a  tendency  to 
evil  in  man,  with  simply  freewill  to  resist  it,  and  that 
tendency  is  at  once  a  strong  power  and  force  in  his  nature  ; 
but  suppose,  together  with  that  tendency  to  evil,  and  coeval 
with  it,  a  formed  and  set  habit  and  disposition  of  the  whole 
soul  to  good — suppose,  in  short  (allowing  for  necessary  dis 
tinctions),  a  character  equal  to  a  virtuous  character  which 
it  has  taken  time  and  effort  to  acquire,  existing  in  man  as 
the  gift  of  Grod,  at  the  moment  of  his  creation3,  and  it  is 
at  once  evident  that  the  evil  tendency  in  his  nature  is  at  a 
very  great  disadvantage  ;  because  it  starts  with  a  loss  of 
position,  and  opposes  an  antedated  strength,  a  created  pre 
cedence,  and  an  implanted  growth  of  goodness.  Evil  thus 
begins  its  course  under  a  righteous  oppression,  which  con 
fines  its  movements  and  keeps  it  at  a  distance  from  the 
centre  of  human  life  and  feeling  ;  its  invitations  are  faintly 
heard  from  the  extremities  of  nature,  a  solid  intervening 
formation  of  good  intercepting  them  before  they  arrive 
at  a  forcible  and  exciting  stage ;  and  sin,  yet  unknown  to 
conscience,  accompanies  human  nature,  like  a  dream,  with 
languid  and  remote  temptations,  while  good  occupies  the 
active  and  waking  man.  Such  a  state  may  be  partially 
understood  from  the  ordinary  case  of  any  one  who  has 
acquired  virtuous  habits  of  any  kind.  These  habits  do  not 

1  '  Haec  discordia  carnis  et  spiri-       semper,  sed  ex  ilia  se  in  malam  nullo 
tus  in  paradise,  si  nemo  peccasset,       cogente    mutaret,    sicut   et   factum 
absit  ut   esse  potuerit.' — Op.  Imp.       est.'— Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  61. 

1.  4.  c.  37.  s  « Ilia  itaque   perfectio   naturae 

2  '  Quasi  non  potuerit  Deus  ho-  quam    non    dabant    anni    sed    sola 
minem  facere  voluntatis   bonse,    in  manus  Dei,  non  potuit  nisi  habere 
qua  eum  tamen  permanere  non  co-  voluntatem    aliquam,    eamque    non 
geret  sed  in  ejus  esset  arbitrio  sive  malam.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  61. 

in  ea  semper  esse  vellet,  sive  non 


CHAP.  nr.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  87 

exclude  a  man  from  trial,  for,  however  firmly  rooted,  they 
have  still  to  be  sustained  by  the  effort  of  the  will.  Still,  in 
the  case  of  confirmed  virtuous  habits,  this  effort  is  an  easy 
and  unconscious  one,  not  anxious  or  laborious  ;  the  person, 
though  not  out  of  the  reach  of  evil,  is  separated  at  a  con 
siderable  interval  from  it,  and,  under  the  safeguard  of  his 
habit,  a  serene  precaution  has  to  defend  him  from  distant 
danger,  rather  than  positive  fear  from  a  near  and  immediate 
one.  Jn  the  same  way,  only  more  perfectly  than  in  any  case 
of  habit  of  which  we  have  experience,  the  first  man  was  pro 
tected  from  sin  by  an  implanted  holy  disposition  of  mind, 
and  habitual  inclination  to  good  imparted  to  him  at  his 
creation.  His  trial  lay  in  having  to  sustain  a  divinely  be 
stowed  defence  against  sin,  rather  than  engage  in  direct 
conflict  with  it ;  and  a  tranquil  precaution,  not  inconsistent 
with  the  happiness  of  paradise,  against  a  remote  issue  on 
the  side  of  evil,  had  it  been  adequately  maintained,  would 
have  effectually  preserved  him.1  He  had  by  his  created 
disposition  a  pleasure  in  goodness ;  and  that  pleasure  natu 
rally  preserved  him  in  obedience  without  the  need  of 
express  effort.  But  though  thus  held  to  obedience  by  the 
persuasive  tie  of  an  adequate  pleasure  and  delight,  man  was 
not  without  an  indefinite  principle  of  desire  in  his  nature, 
which  tended  to  pass  beyond  the  bounds  of  present  happi 
ness  in  quest  of  more.  Thus,  in  common  life,  persons  happy 
after  a  human  measure  in  their  present  situation  and  re 
sources,  still  carry  about  with  them  a  general  sense  of  a 
capacity  for  greater  happiness,  which  is  without  much 
difficulty  kept  under  and  controlled,  by  the  mind  simply 
sustaining  a  proper  estimate  of  the  resources  in  its  posses 
sion  and  applying  a  just  attention  to  the  enjoyment  of 
them ;  but  which  may  be  allowed  to  expand  unduly,  till  it 
impels  the  man  to  a  trial  of  new  and  dangerous  sources  of 
pleasure.  Happy  within  the  limits  of  obedience,  Adam 
was  still  not  out  of  the  reach  of  a  remote  class  of  invita 
tions  to  advance  beyond  the  precincts  of  a  sacred  sufficiency 
and  make  trial  of  the  unknown.  But  the  happiness  with 

''Pcense  illius   devitandse  qua      quilla  erat  cautio    non  turbulenta 
fuerat    [secutura     peccatum,    tran-       formido.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  14. 


88  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  in. 

which  Grod  had  connected  his  duty  could  have  easily,  with 
the  aid  of  an  unpainful  caution  of  his  own,  mastered  the 
temptation.1  Thus,  in  some  calm  interval,  produced  by 
sight  or  sound,  or  by  some  cheering  or  tranquillising  news, 
or  arising  in  the  mind  he  knows  not  how,  a  man  enjoys, 
amid  the  business,  anxiety,  and  turmoil  of  the  world,  a 
brief  repose  and  happiness  within  ;  which  does  not,  however, 
while  it  removes  to  the  distant  horizon  for  the  time  the 
evils  and  the  pains  of  life,  altogether  put  them  out  of  sight. 
Behind  him  are  the  sorrows  and  misfortunes  of  the  past, 
before  him  those  of  the  future.  He  is  not  unconscious  of 
either ;  but  they  yield  to  the  reign  of  the  present  hour, 
which  disables  and  unsubstantiates,  though  it  does  not 
suppress  them.  The  fulness  of  present  peace  occupies  the 
mind,  excluding  the  power  of  realising  anything  which  is 
not  in  harmony  with  it ;  and  evil  is  only  seen  as  a  distant 
shadow,  hovering  on  the  outside  of  things,  a  feeble  and 
inert  phantom  belonging  to  another  world  than  our  own, 
which  cannot  come  near  enough  to  hurt,  or  penetrate 
within  the  sphere  of  solid  things.  So,  from  some  inland 
scene  is  heard  the  distant  roar  of  the  sea,  or  from  some 
quiet  country  spot  the  noise  of  the  neighbouring  city  ;  the 
sounds  are  heard,  but  they  affect  the  mind  altogether 
differently  than  if  they  were  near.  They  do  not  over 
whelm  or  distract,  but  rather  mingle  with  the  serenity  of 
the  scene  before  us. 

This  implanted  rectitude  or  good  habit  it  was  which 
made  the  first  sin  of  man  so  heinous,  and  caused  that  dis 
tinction  between  it  and  all  the  other  sins  which  have  been 
committed  in  the  world.  For  the  first  sin  was  the  only  sin 
which  was  committed  against  and  in  spite  of  a  settled  bias 
of  nature  toward  good ;  all  the  sins  which  have  been  com 
mitted  since  have  been  committed  in  accordance  with  a 
natural  bias  toward  evil.  There  was  therefore  a  perversity 
in  the  first  sin  altogether  peculiar  to  it,  and  such  as  made 
it  a  sin  sui  generis.  S.  Augustine  is  accordingly  exact  in 

1  '  Bonse  igitur  voluntatis  factus  piens,  quod  sine  ulla  quamdiu  vellet 
oft  homo,  paratus  ad  obediendum  difficultate  servaret.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  5. 
Deo,  et  prseceptum  obedienter  acci-  c.  61. 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  89 

distinguishing  the  motive  to  the  first  sin  as  being  a  depraved 
will  as  contrasted  with  concupiscence  or  lust ;  by  a  depraved 
will  meaning  a  perverse  opposition  to  the  good  will  estab 
lished  in  the  first  man,  a  voluntary  abandonment  of  the 
high  ground  on  which  he  stood  by  nature,  a  violation  of 
his  own  created  inclination  to  good.1  A  kind  of  horror 
attaches  to  the  falls  of  saints,  when  those  who  have  main 
tained  a  high  and  consistent  course  of  holiness  commit 
some  deep  sin.  Such  sins  are  like  unaccountable  convul 
sions  in  nature,  and  our  moral  instincts  immediately  draw 
a  distinction  between  them  and  common  sins.  The  pecu 
liarity,  however,  of  the  sin  of  Adam,  exceeded  that  of  any 
sin  of  fallen  man,  in  that  it  was  the  sin  of  man  unfallen. 

It  may  be  added,  that  such  an  inspired  good  habit  or 
disposition  of  man  as  first  created  is  part  of  the  tradition  of 
the  golden  age.  A  certain  disposition  is  described  in  that 
legend  as  being  that  of  the  whole  human  race  at  the  com 
mencement  of  its  existence — an  original  moral  formation, 
like  the  creation  of  the  race  itself, — -and  it  is  described 
as  continuing  some  time ; — a  disposition  involving  general 
goodness  and  uprightness,  love,  gentleness,  serenity,  content. 
So  suitable  has  it  seemed  even  to  the  unenlightened  human 
mind  that  the  morning  of  a  world  of  moral  beings  should 
arise  in  light  and  purity, — that  the  creation  fresh  from  the 
Divine  hands  should  shine  with  the  reflection  of  the  Divine 
goodness,  and  bear  the  stamp  of  a  proximity  to  Grod, — that 
the  will  of  man  as  first  created  should  not  be  neutral  or 
indeterminate,  but  disposed  to  good.  Nor  have  the  defini 
tions  of  Catholic  theology,  however  elaborate  and  subtle  in 
form,  diverged  in  substance  from  the  ground  of  general 
tradition  and  natural  ideas. 

Scripture  and  common  tradition  thus  assert  a  paradisal 
life  as  the  original  state  of  man.  But  the  Pelagian,  in 
denying  the  fall,  rejected  Paradise  ;  as  he  would  not  admit 

1  '  Prsecessit  mala   voluntas,  et  vitiatem  venenosa  persuasione  ser- 

secuta  est  mala  concupiscentia  .  .  .  pentis,   ut   oriretur    cupiditas   quse 

•Voluntas  cupiditatem,  non  cupiditas  sequeretur  potius  voluntatem  quam 

voluntatem  duxit.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  resisteret    voluntati.' — Ibid.    1.    6. 

c.  71.  '  Voluntatem  ejus  prius  fuisse  c.  14. 


90  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  m. 

original  sin,  he  could  fall  back  on  no  antecedent  state  of 
innocence.  He  robbed  human  nature  of  the  glory,  the 
freshness,  and  the  beauty  of  its  first  creation,  reduced  the 
primitive  to  the  level  of  all  that  succeeded  it,  and  fixed  the 
present  facts  of  the  world  as  the  standard  of  our  nature. 
He  made  this  existing  state  of  sin  and  pain  coeval  with  the 
commencement  of  things ;  and  S.  Augustine  taunted  his 
opponents  with  the  '  Pelagian  Paradise.' *  Human  nature 
in  the  midst  of  trials  looks  back  with  consolation  to  the 
paradisal  state  as  a  sign  that  pain  is  the  accident  and 
happiness  the  law  of  our  being ;  and  were  the  rest  of  the 
Old  Testament  silent,  a  future  state  was  still  preached  to 
the  Jew  in  the  first  chapter  of  Genesis  ;  but  the  Pelagian 
cut  off  both  the  retrospect  and  the  pledge.  The  paradisal 
age  was  to  him  nothing  more  than  the  first  age  of  the  world, 
when  science,  art,  and  the  refinements  of  life  had  not  yet 
arisen,  and  man  was  simpler  than  he  was  afterwards,  only 
because  he  was  more  rude.  He  took  the  same  view  of  it 
that  a  human  philosopher  would  take  who  pictures  to  him 
self  the  primitive  state  of  man  simply  as  a  state  anterior 
to  civilisation2,  and  contrasts  it  with  the  law,  system,  and 
social  growth  of  a  more  advanced  age. 

And,  together  with  the  paradisal  life  in  general,  the 
created  goodness  of  the  first  man  fell  to  the  ground.  The 
idea  of  created  virtue  jarred  with  the  Pelagian  theory  of 
freewill,  according  to  which  virtue  was  no  virtue  at  all, 
unless  a  man  acquired  it  for  himself.  An  original  gift 
of  righteousness  was  thus  dismissed  as  a  contradiction,  and 

1  '  Naturara    humanam    a    Deo  ceret  irrisorem.  Veruntamen  eorum 

bono   conditam   bonam   magno    in-  qui   nos  noverunt,  nemo  miraretur, 

obedientise  peccato  fuisse  vitiatam,  si  adderetur  nomen  restrum  adtitu- 

Catholica  fides  dicit.  Sed  yos  qui  hoc  lum,  et  scriberetur.  Paradisus  Pela- 

negatis,  quaeso,  paulisper  Paradisum  gianorum.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  3.   c.  154. 

cogitate.  Placetne  vobis  ut  ponamus  Vide  1.   3.   c.   95.   147. ;  1.  6.  c.  25. 

.  .  .  innumerabiles    morbos,    orbi-  27.  28. 

tates,  luctus,  etc.  Certe  si  talis  2  '  Homines  fuisse  primitus  nu- 
paradisus  pingeretur  nullus  diceret  dos,quia  ad  solertisehumanseoperam 
esse  paradisum,  nee  si  supra  legisset  ut  se  tegerent  pertinebat,  quae  non- 
hoc  nomen  conscriptum  :  nee  diceret  dum  in  illis  fuit.' — Contra  Jul.  Pel. 
erasse  pectorem,  sed  plane  agnos-  1.  4.  n.  81. 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  91 

Adam  at  his  creation  was  considered  to  be  in  the  same 
condition  as  every  other  man  that  has  been  born,  and  to 
have  had  the  same  straggle  of  the  flesh  and  spirit.1 

2.  The  Pelagian  doctrine  had  an  important  bearing  on 
the  doctrine  of  the  Incarnation,  in  regard  to  the  manner  in 
which  our  Lord  was,  according  to  that  economy,  subject  to 
temptation  and  trial,  and  exposed  to  the  approaches  of  sin. 
Scripture  says  that  our  Lord  was  in  all  points  tempted  like 
as  we  are.  But  the  Church  has  not  considered  it  consistent 
with  piety  to  interpret  this  text  to  mean  that  our  Lord  had 
the  same  direct  propension  to  sin  that  we  have,  or  that 
which  is  called  by  divines  concupiscence.2  Such  direct 
appetite  for  what  is  sinful  is  the  characteristic  of  our  fallen 
and  corrupt  nature  ;  and  our  Lord  did  not  assume  a  corrupt, 
but  a  sound  humanity.  Indeed,  concupiscence,  even  prior 
to  and  independent  of  its  gratification,  has  of  itself  the 
nature  of  sin3 ;  and,  therefore,  could  not  belong  to  a  perfect 
Being.  Our  Lord  had  all  the  passions  and  affections  that 
legitimately  belong  to  man  ;  which  passions  and  affections, 
tending  as  they  do  in  their  own  nature  to  become  inordi 
nate,  constituted  of  themselves  a  state  of  trial ;  but  the 
Church  has  regarded  our  Lord's  trial  in  the  flesh  as  con 
sisting  in  preserving  ordinate  affections  from  becoming 
inordinate,  rather  than  in  restraining  desire  proximate  to 
sin  from  gratification.  So  mysterious  a  subject  precludes 

1  '  Quod  miserrimum  bellum  in-  est,  in  paradise  futuram  esse,  si  nemo 

troducere  conaris  in  illius  beatissimse  peccasset,  talemque  in  illo  fuisse  et 

pacis  et  libertatis  locum.' — Op.  Imp.  priusquam  peccaret ;  addis  ejus  con- 

1.  5.  c.  8.     '  Nos  autem  dicimus  tarn  ditioni  et  istam  miseriam  per  carnis 

beatum  fuisse  ilium  hominem  ante  spiritusque  discordiam.' — C.  16. 
peccatum,  tamque  liberse  voluntatis,  2  '  Christus   ergo    nulla    illicita 

ut  Dei  praeceptum  magnis   viribus  concupivit,  quia  discordiam  carnis  et 

mentis  observans,  resistentem  sibi  spiritus,  quse  in  hominis  naturam  ex 

carnem  nullo  certamine  pateretur,  prsevaricatione  primi  hominis  vertit, 

nee  aliquid  omnino  ex  aliqua  cupi-  prorsus    ille    non    habuit,    qui   de 

ditate  sentiret,  quod  nollet.' — L.  6.  Spiritu  et  Virgine  non  per  concupis- 

c.    14.     'Addo   ad   bonitatem   con-  centiam  carnis  est  natus.' — Op.  Imp. 

ditionis  Adse  quod  in  eo  caro  adver-  1.  4.  c.  57. 

sus  spiritum  non  concupiscebat  ante  3  Malum  esse  quamvis  mente  non 

peccatum :  tu  autem  qui  talem  dicis  consentiente,  vel  carne  tamen  talia 

carnis  concupiscentiam  qualis  nunc  concupiscere. — Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  59. 


92  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  nr. 

all  exactness  of  definition ;  yet  the  Church  expressed  a 
substantial  truth  of  morals,  as  well  as  one  of  faith  and 
piety,  when  she  guarded  the  person  of  our  Lord  from  the 
too  near  approaches  of  sin.  Desire  discloses,  on  a  nearer 
examination,  different  moral  complexions,  and  at  a  certain 
stage  is  seen  to  be  no  longer  a  neutral  thing.  Our  Lord, 
therefore,  had  not  the  whole  of  desire  assigned  to  Him,  but 
only  that  earlier  stage  of  it  which  is  consistent  with  a  sound 
nature ;  and,  together  with  a  true  trial,  a  true  sinlessness 
was  provided  for. 

But  S.  Augustine  had  to  contest  this  whole  question 
with  the  Pelagian  in  the  instance  of  our  Lord,  as  he  had 
contested  it  before  in  the  instance  of  Adam.  The  Pelagian 
who  attached  concupiscence  to  man  in  Paradise,  saw  no 
reason  against  attaching  it  to  the  humanity  assumed  by 
our  Lord.  Intent  on  effort  exclusively  as  the  test  of  good 
ness,  he  argued  that  it  was  this  very  strength  of  desire 
which  constituted  the  force  of  trial ;  and  that,  therefore, 
the  great  merit  of  our  Lord's  obedience  was  destroyed  by 
supposing  Him  to  have  been  without  it.1  Moreover,  He 
was  our  Model,  as  having  been  subjected  to  the  same  trials  ; 
but  if  His  desires  were  weaker  than  ours,  His  temptation 
had  been  less,  and  the  force  of  His  example  was  less  with 
it.2  But,  it  was  replied,  that  a  state  of  mind  which  kept 
off  the  approach  of  sin  was  a  higher  one  than  that  which 
resisted  it  near ;  that  the  merit  of  our  Lord's  obedience 

1  Julian:  ' Non qui virtute  judicii  blasphemous  conclusion  in  the  case 

delicta  vitasset ;  sed   qui   felicitate  of  our  Lord.     '  Ecce  quod  Christo 

carnis  a  nostrissensibus  sequestra tse,  conaris   importare   insane 

cupiditatem  vitiorum  sentire  nequi-  Tanto  quippe  in  eo  continentia  spiri- 

visset.'     Augustine  objects   to   this  tus  major  est,  quantomajorem  carnis 

mode  of  stating  the  Catholic  posi-  concupiscentinm  coerceret.' — C.  52. 
tion.     '  Sensissetenim  si  habuisset ;  2  '  Nunquam    commemorationem 

non  enim  sensus  ei  defuit  quo  earn  fecisset   exempli  :  quern    enim   ho- 

sentiret,  sed    voluntas    adfuit    qua  minibus    ostenderet   imitandum,   si 

non  haberet.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  48.  ilium  externse  carnis  natura  discre- 

And  he  observes  that  if,  according  visset.  .  .  Quanto  ei  rectius  diceret 

to  Julian's  argument,  the  merit  of  segritudo    peccantium    et   securitas 

virtue    lay   in   conquest,   it   would  coactorum ;    "  cum  valemus   omnes 

follow  that  where  the   virtue   was  recta   consilia   prsebemus    segrotis ; 

greatest,    the     passions     must    be  tu  si  sic  esses,  aliter  longe  longeque 

strongest ;  which  would   lead  to   a  sentires."  ' — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  86,  87. 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  93 

was  the  perfect  one  of  a  triumphantly  sustained  distance 
from  evil ! ;  and  that  the  force  of  example  did  not  depend 
on  the  identity  of  trial,  but  on  the  goodness  of  the  example 
itself,  as  was  evident  from  the  injunction  in  Scripture  to 
imitate  God.2  It  must,  indeed,  be  remarked,  on  this  reply, 
that  Scripture  rests  the  force  of  our  Lord's  example  ex 
pressly  on  the  ground  that  His  trial  was  like  our  own.  The 
Pelagian,  therefore,  was  right  in  insisting  on  this  similarity. 
But  he  proceeded  to  argue  from  it  upon  the  principles 
of  ordinary  logic,  and  his  conclusion  degraded  our  Lord's 
humanity,  and  endangered  that  balance  of  truths  on  which 
the  doctrine  of  the  Incarnation  rested.  The  doctrine  of 
our  Lord's  Divinity  modifies  the  truths  connected  with  His 
humanity  in  this  way,  that  He  who  was  both  God  and  man 
cannot  be  thought  of  even  as  man  exactly  the  same  as  if 
He  were  not  God.  And  the  truth  of  our  Lord's  trial  and 
temptation,  among  others,  is  in  this  sense  a  modified  one. 
To  carry  out,  therefore,  the  conception  of  a  human  trial 
to  the  full  in  the  instance  of  our  Lord,  without  respect  to 
other  truth,  was  to  trench  on  his  Divinity.  To  the  idea  of 
trial,  and  of  example  on  the  ground  of  trial,  pursued  ex 
clusively,  the  next  idea  is  that  of  peccability,  and  the  next 
that  of  simple  manhood.  It  was  consistent  with  such  ten- 

1  '  Dicimus  eum  perfectione  car-  tur  ut  iraitemur  te  ?  Nunquid  nos 

nis,  et  non  per  carnis  conciipiscen-  cle  Spiritu  Sancto  et  Virgine  Maria 

tiam  procreata  carne.  cupiditatem  nati  sumus?  Postremo  nunquid 

non  habuisse  vitiorum.  .  .  .  Illius  tantanobis  esse  virtus  potest  quanta, 

virtus  haec  erat  earn  non  liabere  ;  tibi  est,  qui  ita  homo  es,  ut  etiam 

nostra  virtus  est  ei  non  consentire.'  Deussis?  Ideone  non  debuitsicnasci 

— Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  48.  '  Sic  igitur  ut  hominibus  eum  nolentibus  imitari 

Christus  abstinuit  a  peccato,  ut  ab-  talis  excusatio  daretur  ?  Sicut  nobis 

stineret  etiam  ab  omni  cupiditate  ipse  Patrem  proposuit  imitandum, 

peccati :  non  ut  ei  existenti  resis-  qui  certe  homo  fuit Nee 

teret,  sed  ut  ilia  nunquam  prorsus  dicunt  ei,Tuproptereahoc  potesquia 

existeret.' — C.  58.  Deus  es.  .  .  Non  itaque  ideo  debuit 

*  '  Neque  negare  debemus  ejus  natus  de  Spiritu  Sancto  et  Virgine 

excellentiam,  neque  propter  hanc  Maria  habere  concupiscentiam,  qua 

excellentiam  nos  excusare,  ut  non  cuperet  mala,  etsi  ei  resistendo  non 

eum  pro  modo  nostro  studeamus  faceret,  ne  dicerent  ei  homines, 

imitari.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  89.  Habeto  prius  cupiditates  malas,  et 

'  Quid  enim,  homo  multum  lo-  eas  vince,  si  potes,  ut  te  imitari  nos- 

quens  et  parum  sapiens,  si  dicerent  tras  vincendo  possimus.' — Op.  Imp. 

homines  Christo,  Quare  nobis  jube-  1.  4.  c.  87. 


94  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  in. 

dencies  in  Pelagianism  that  our  Lord  did  not  stand  forth 
as  the  one  sole  example  of  perfect  obedience  in  that  system ; 
but  only  one,  though  the  principal  one,  of  a  succession  of 
perfect  men  that  had  appeared  in  the  world — extending 
from  Abel  and  Enoch  to  Simeon  and  Joseph,  the  husband 
of  Mary.1  An  extreme  idea  of  freewill  and  human  perfecti 
bility  was  in  truth  inconsistent  with  a  sound  doctrine  of 
the  Incarnation,  not  admitting  of  such  a  singularity  in  our 
Lord's  life  and  character  as  that  doctrine  involved. 

The  Pelagian,  indeed,  in  retaliation  for  the  charge  of 
degrading  our  Lord's  humanity,  charged  his  opponents  with 
unsubstantiating  it,  and  threw  back  upon  them  the  name 
of  Apollinarists,  as,  with  a  difference  of  temptation,  not  as 
signing  to  our  Lord  the  same  humanity  which  other  men 
have,  and  so  denying  His  true  assumption  of  our  nature. 
But  it  was  replied  that  our  Lord  took  on  Him  the  nature, 
but  not  the  sin  of  man.  He  even  charged  his  opponents 
with  Manicheanism,  as  denying  that  Christ  had  assumed 
our  flesh ;  but  the  same  answer  was  made,  that  the  flesh 
was  assumed,  but  not  the  corruption.  He  discovered, 
again,  in  the  Catholic  representation  of  our  Lord's  trial  in 
the  flesh,  a  combination  of  both  heresies  modified — a  semi- 
Apollinarism  in  a  soul  imperfectly  connected  with  the  flesh, 
a  semi-Manicheanism  in  a  flesh  imperfectly  connected  with 
the  soul  of  our  Lord.  But  it  was  replied,  as  before,  that 
the  soul  of  Christ  had  perfect  connection  with  the  flesh, 
but  not  with  its  corruption.2 

1  De  Natura  et  Gratia,  n.  42.  deri,  pro  anima  vero  ipsam   fuisse 
'  Incarnatio  Christi  justitiae  fuit      deitatem.     Quod  posteaquam  coepit 

forma  non  prima  sed  maxima,  quia  tarn  rationis  quam  evangelii  attesta- 

et  antequam  Verbum  caro  fieret,  et  tione  convelli  .  .  excogitavit  aliud 

in  Prophetis  et  in  multis  aliis  sane-  unde    ejus   hseresis,    quae    perdurat 

tis  fulsere  virtutes.'— Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  hactenus,  nasceretur  ;  et  dixit  ani- 

c-  188.  mam  quidem  humanam  in  Christo 

2  Julian  :    '  Hie   igitur   ut  adsit  fuisse  sed  sensus  in  eo  corporis  non 
toto  animo  lector  admoneo  :  videbit  fuisse,  atque  impassibilem  eum  pro- 
enim  Apollinaristarum  haeresim,  sed  nuntiavit  universis  extitisse  pecca- 
eam  Manichaei  per  te  adjectione  re-  tis.' — Op,  Imp.  1.  4.  c.  47. 

parari.      Apollinaris    primo    talem  '  Certe  hanc  vim  in   disputando 

mcarnationem,     Christi     induxisse  Apostolus  non  haberet  si  secundum 

iertur,  ut  diceret  solum  corpus  de  Manichseos    et     eorum     discipulos 

numana  substantia  assumptum  vi-  Traducianos,  carnem  Christi  a  na- 


CHAP.  in.         The  Pelagian  Controversy.  95 

3.  Pelagianism  was  fundamentally  opposed  to  the  doc 
trine  of  the  atonement ;  for  no  atonement  was  wanted  if 
there  had  been  no  fall.  And  this  was  the  chief  obstacle 
between  the  Pelagian  and  a  sound  doctrine  of  the  Incar 
nation.  The  design  of  the  Incarnation  was  to  remedy  the 
effects  of  the  fall ;  apart  from  which  object,  it  could  only 
be  held  as  an  isolated  fact,  and,  without  place  or  signifi- 
cancy,  had  no  root  in  the  system. 

The  Pelagian,  however,  in  superseding  the  atonement 
fundamentally,  retained  some  scattered  fragments  of  the 
doctrine.  The  relation  of  Christ,  as  Kedeemer,  to  the 
whole  race  of  man,  was  abandoned  in  that  doctrine  of  free 
will  which  represented  all  men  as  able  to  fulfil,  and  some 
as  having  fulfilled,  the  whole  law,  without  any  other  aids 
than  such  as  were  attached  to  the  system  of  nature.  This 
position  was  a  contradiction  to  a  universal  atonement.  But 
though  the  Pelagians  did  not  regard  the  assisting  grace, 
which  that  event  procured,  as  necessary  for  everybody,  or 
the  pardoning  grace  as  wanted  by  all,  they  attached  an 
advantage  and  benefit  to  the  one,  and  maintained  a  general 
need  of  the  other.  The  grace  of  which  Christ  was  the 
source  rendered  the  fulfilment  of  the  law,  though  possible 
without  it,  easier,  and  was  a  valuable,  though  not  a  neces 
sary  assistance ;  while  the  great  mass  of  mankind  stood  in 
need  of  the  atonement  for  the  pardon  of  actual,  though 
not  of  original  sin.  But  the  force  of  the  Christian  atone 
ment  lies  in  its  interest  to  mankind  as  one  corporate  whole, 
and  that  interest  being  one  of  absolute  need.  To  deny 
the  universal  necessity  of  the  atonement,  therefore,  was  to 
give  up  the  doctrine.  As  advantageous  to  any,  essential 
to  some,  the  grace  of  Christ  was  a  Pelagian  fiction,  accom 
modated  to  a  theory  opposed  to  it,  and  maintained  as  a 

turae    nostrae    communione    distin-  qui  carnem  Christi  a  naturae  nostrae 

gueret.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  33.  communione   distinguunt,    sed    qui 

Augustine,  in  reply,  distinguishes  nullam  carnem  Christum  habuisse 

between  the  Apollinarist  statement,  contendunt.  .  .  .  Dimitte  illos  .  .  . 

Christum  non habuisse corporis sensus,  quia  nobiscum  carnem  Christi  etsi 

and  his  own,  that  those  senses  non  dissimiliter  confiteris.  Nee  nos  enim 

contra  Spiritum  concupisse  (1.  4.  c.  earn    a   naturae    atque    substantiae 

47.);    and   as   against  the    Mani-  carnis  nostrae,sed  a  vitii  communione 

cheans,  he  says, '  Manichaei  non  sunt,  distinguimus.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  33. 


96  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  in. 

feeble  show  of  orthodoxy.  The  separation  of  renovating 
from  pardoning  grace,  again,  was  a  blow  at  the  integrity 
of  Grospel  grace.  Pardoning  grace  was  necessary  for  any 
one  who  had  sinned,  because  the  sin  was  a  past  fact  which 
could  not  be  undone  ;  but  the  renovating  or  assisting  grace 
of  Christ  was  not  necessary,  however  advantageous  to  him, 
because  the  future  sin  could  be  avoided  by  nature  alone. 
These  two  graces  go  together  in  the  Divine  scheme,  and 
belong  to  the  same  act  of  the  Divine  mercy. 

Out  of  one  extreme  statement  at  the  commencement, 
Pelagianism  thus  expanded  into  a  large  body  of  thought, 
incomplete  indeed,  but  having  one  general  stamp,  and 
developing  more  and  more,  as  it  came  out,  the  original 
difference  from  Catholic  truth ;  passing  from  the  human 
will  to  higher  mysteries,  and  upon  the  basis  of  exalted 
nature  threatening  the  truth  of  the  Incarnation. 

The  philosophical  fault  of  Pelagianism  was,  that  it  went 
upon  ideas  without  considering  facts — in  the  case  both  of 
freewill  and  the  Divine  justice.  The  abstract  idea  of  free 
will  is  that  of  a  power  to  do  anything  that  it  is  physically 
possible  for  us  to  do.  As  man  had  freewill,  then,  the  Pela 
gian  argued  that  he  had  this  power ;  and  that  any  man, 
therefore,  could  fulfil  the  whole  law  and  be  perfect.  But 
what  we  have  to  consider  in  this  question,  is  not  what  is 
the  abstract  idea  of  freewill,  but  what  is  the  freewill  which 
we  really  and  actually  have.  This  actual  freewill,  we  find, 
is  not  a  simple  but  a  complex  thing ;  exhibiting  opposi 
tions  and  inconsistencies  ;  appearing  on  the  one  side  to  be 
a  power  of  doing  anything  to  which  there  is  no  physical 
hindrance,  on  the  other  side  to  be  a  restricted  faculty.  It 
is  that  will  which  S.  Paul  describes,  when,  appealing  to 
the  facts  of  human  nature  (the  account  of  which,  as  referred 
to  the  sin  of  Adam,  is  a  matter  of  faith,  but  which  are 
themselves  matters  of  experience),  he  describes  a  state  of 
divided  consciousness,  and  a  sense  of  power  and  weakness. 
But  the  Pelagian  did  not  possess  himself  properly  of  the 
facts  of  human  nature,  and,  committing  the  same  fault  in 
morals  that  the  mediaeval  philosophers  did  in  science,  he 
argued  upon  an  abstract  idea,  instead  of  examining  what 


CHAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  97 

the  faculty,  as  we  experienced  it,  really  is  ;  and  an  abso 
lute  freewill,  which  was  a  simple  conception  of  the  mind, 
displaced  the  incomprehensible  actual  will,  the  enigma  of 
human  nature,  the  mystery  of  fact. 

The  Pelagian's  argument  respecting  the  Divine  justice 
proceeded  in  the  same  way  upon  an  idea  without  consider 
ing  facts.  It  was  founded  indeed  upon  the  true  natural 
idea  of  justice  in  our  minds ;  and  so  far  no  fault  is  to 
be  found  with  it.  Nor  was  this  a  mere  abstract  idea. 
But  he  did  not  take  into  consideration  with  it  the  facts  of 
the  existing  constitution  of  things.  We  find  a  severe  law 
of  suffering  in  operation  in  this  world  previous  to  the 
existence  of  the  individual;  which  law,  therefore,  can 
hardly  be  said  to  be,  in  a  comprehensible  sense,  a  just 
one.  Our  moral  nature,  then,  and  the  existing  constitu 
tion  of  things,  being  at  variance  on  the  question  of  the 
Divine  justice,  we  arrive  at  the  conclusion  that  the  Divine 
justice  is  incomprehensible.  But  the  Pelagian  attended 
simply  to  the  idea  of  justice  in  his  own  mind,  and  ignored 
the  facts  on  the  other  side.  The  doctrine  of  original  sin, 
then,  which  is  in  truth  nothing  but  an  account,  though  a 
revealed  one,  of  these  facts,  was  not  wanted  by  him.  He 
did  not  attend  to  the  difficulty,  and  therefore  wanted  no 
solution.  This  doctrine  was  therefore,  in  his  eyes,  a  mere 
gratuitous  theory,  which  needlessly  and  wantonly  contra 
dicted  the  truth  of  the  Divine  justice. 

But  the  primary  fault  of  Pelagianism  was  the  sin  against 
piety  contained  in  its  fundamental  assertion,  as  explained 
at  the  commencement  of  this  chapter,  of  an  ultimate  move 
ment  of  the  natural  will  to  good,  unassisted  by  Grod. 
However  logical  a  result  of  the  admission  of  the  freedom 
of  the  will,  the  absolute  assertion  of  this  position  was 
false,  because  its  premiss  was  an  imperfect  one ;  and  it 
was  contrary  to  piety,  the  religious  mind  feeling  an  insnr- 
mountable  check  and  prohibition  against  calling  any  good 
movement  purely  its  own,  and  appropriating  it  to  the 
exclusion  of  Grod.  But  the  Pelagian  ventured  on  this  act 
of  appropriation. 

Kaised  upon  a  basis  thus  philosophically  and  religiously 


gg  The  Pelagian  Controversy.         CHAP.  m. 

at  fault,  Pelagianism  was  first  an  artificial  system,  and  next 
of  a  low  moral  tendency. 

It  wanted  reality,  and  was  artificial  in  assigning  to  man 
what  was  opposed  to  his  consciousness  and  to  what  he  felt 
to  be  the  truth  about  himself.  The  absolute  power  of  man 
to  act  without  sin  and  be  morally  perfect  was  evidently  a 
fiction,  based  on  an  abstract  idea  and  not  on  the  expe 
rienced  faculty  of  freewill.  And  when  he  followed  with  a 
list  of  men  who  had  actually  been  perfect  moral  beings, 
Abel,  Enoch,  Melchisedek,  and  others,  he  simply  trifled ; 
and  showed  how  fantastic,  absurd,  and  unsubstantial  his 
position  was.  Human  nature  is  too  seriously  alive  to  the 
law  of  sin  under  which  it  at  present  acts,  not  to  feel  the 
mockery  of  such  assertions. 

The  system,  again,  had  a  low  moral  tendency.  First, 
it  dulled  the  sense  of  sin.  Prior  to  and  independent  of 
action  there  exists  a  state  of  desire  which  the  refined  con 
science  mourns  over ;  but  which  is  part  of  the  existing 
nature  as  distinguished  from  being  the  choice  of  the  man. 
Hence  the  true  sense  in  which  the  saints  have  ever  grieved, 
not  only  over  their  acts,  but  over  their  nature :  for,  how 
ever  incomprehensible,  they  have  felt  something  to  be 
sinful  within  them  which  was  yet  coeval  with  them.  But 
the  Pelagian,  not  admitting  any  sin  but  that  of  direct 
choice,  would  not  see  in  concupiscence  anything  but  a 
legitimate  desire,  which  might  be  abused,  but  was  in  itself 
innocent.  In  disallowing  the  mystery  of  evil  he  thus  im 
paired  his  perception  of  it ;  he  only  saw  nature  in  that  to 
which  the  acute  conscience  attached  sin1 ;  and  gave  him- 

1  '  Naturalem  esse  omnium  sen-  ing  and  conscience.  '  Quod  vero 

suum  voluptatem,  testimonio  univer-  posuisti,  legem  quidem  peccati  esse 

sitatis  docemus  .  .  .  Concupiscentia  in  membris  nostris,  sed  tune  habere 

cum  intra  limitem  concessorum  te-  peccat urn  quando  consentimus  ;  tune 

netur  affectio  naturalis  et  innocuus  vero  solum  prcelium  suscitare  quan- 

est.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  71.  do  non  consentimus,  et  indicere 

The  particular  difficulty  attach-  miseriam  pace  turbata  ;  quis  non 

ing  to  concupiscence  as  sin,  and  yet  prudens  pugnare  perspiciat  ?  Nam 

unavoidable,  Julian  exposes  with  si  lex  peccati,  id  est,  peccatum,  et 

logical  acuteness,  which  does  not,  necessitas  peccati  membris  est  in- 

however,  still  answer  the  real  argu-  serta  natural] ter,  quid  prodest  non 

ment  upon  which  this  sort  of  sin  ei  prsebere  consensum,  cum  propter 

rests,  which  is  that  of  inward  feel-  hoc  ipsum  quod  est,  necesse  sit 


CTTAP.  in.          The  Pelagian  Controversy.  99 

self  credit  for  a  sound  and  practical  standard  of  morals, 
as  opposed  to  a  morbid  and  too  sensitive  one.  The  doc 
trine  of  perfectibility  encouraged  the  same  tendency  in 
the  system,  demanding  a  lower  moral  standard  for  its 
verification. 

And  the  same  narrowness  of  moral  basis  which  dulled 
the  sense  of  sin,  depressed  the  standard  of  virtue.  The 
Pelagian  denied  virtue  as  an  inspiration  and  gift  of  God, 
confining  his  idea  of  it  entirely  to  human  effort  and  direct- 
choice.  But  the  former  conception  of  the  source  of  virtue 
was  necessary  to  a  high  standard  of  virtue  itself.  If  we 
are  to  rely  on  what  general  feeling  and  practical  experi 
ence  say  on  this  subject,  virtue  needs  for  its  own  support 
the  religious  rationale,  i.e.  the  idea  of  itself  as  something 
imparted.  There  must  be  that  image  and  representation 
of  it  in  men's  minds,  which  present  it  less  as  a  human 
work  than  as  an  impulse  from  above,  possessing  itself  of 
the  man  he  knows  not  how ;  a  holy  passion,  and  a  spark 
kindled  from  the  heavenly  fire.  It  is  this  conception  of 
it  as  an  inspiration  that  has  excited  the  sacred  ambition 
of  the  human  mind,  which  longs  for  union  with  Grod,  or  a 
participation  of  the  Divine  life,  and  sees  in  this  inspiration 
this  union.  Virtue  has  thus  risen  from  a  social  and  civil 
to  a  sublime  and  intrinsic  standard,  and  presented  itself  as 
that  which  raised  man  above  the  world,  and  not  simply 
moulded  and  trained  him  for  it.  This  conception  has 
accordingly  approved  itself  to  the  great  poets  of  the  world, 
who  have  in  their  ideal  of  man  greatly  leaned  to  the  in 
spired  kind  of  virtue.  So  congenial  to  the  better  instincts 
even  of  the  unenlightened  human  mind  is  the  Christian 
doctrine  of  grace,  while,  disconnected  with  this  ennobling 
conception,  morality  has  sunk  down  to  a  political  and 
secular  level.  Nor  is  there  any  justice  surer  than  that  by 
which  the  self-sufficient  will  is  punished  by  the  exposure 
of  its  own  feebleness,  and  rejected  grace  avenged  in  a 
barren  and  impoverished  form  of  virtue.  Those  schools 

subire  supplicium  ?     Aut  si  est  lex       (si  dici  permittat  absurditas)  cogit 
quidem  peccati,  sed  quando  ei  non       ipsum  non  peccare  peccatum.' — Op. 
consentio   non  pecco,  inestimabilis       Imp.  1.  1.  c.  71. 
potentia  voluntatis    human  se,   quse 

H  2 


ioo  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 

that  have  seen  in  the  doctrine  of  grace  only  an  unsound 
enthusiasm,  and  have  aimed  at  fortifying  the  ground  of 
morals  by  releasing  it  from  this  connection,  have  not  im 
proved  their  moral  standard,  but  greatly  lowered  and 
relaxed  it.  With  a  dulled  sense  of  sin,  a  depressed  stan 
dard  of  virtue,  Pelagianism  thus  tended  to  the  moral  tone 
of  Socinianism,  and  the  religion  which  denies  the  Incar 
nation.  The  asceticism  of  its  first  promulgators  and 
disciples  could  not  neutralize  the  tendencies  of  a  system 
opposed  to  mystery  and  to  grace,  and  therefore  hostile 
at  once  to  the  doctrinal  and  the  moral  standard  of  Chris 
tianity. 

The  triumphant  overthrow  of  such  a  school  was  the 
service  which  S.  Augustine  performed  to  the  Church,  and 
for  which,  under  God,  we  still  owe  him  gratitude.  With 
all  the  excess  to  which  he  pushed  the  truth  which  he  de 
fended,  he  defended  a  vital  truth,  without  which  Chris 
tianity  must  have  sunk  to  an  inferior  religion,  against  a 
strong  and  formidable  attack.  He  sustained  that  idea  of 
virtue  as  an  inspiration  to  which  the  lofty  thought  of  even 
heathen  times  ever  clung,  which  the  Gospel  formally 
expressed  in  the  doctrine  of  grace,  and  which  is  necessary 
to  uphold  the  attributes  of  God  and  the  moral  standard 
of  man. 


CHAPTEE    IV. 

DIFFERENT    INTERPRETATIONS    OF    ORIGINAL    SIN. 

THE  doctrine  of  the  fall  of  man  has  been  always  held  as  a 
fundamental  doctrine  in  the  Church;  and  all  Catholic 
writers  have  witnessed  to  the  truth,  that  the  first  man 
came  from  the  hands  of  God  an  upright  creature,  that  he 
fell  from  that  uprightness  by  voluntary  transgression,  and 
that  he  involved  in  his  fall  the  whole  of  his  posterity. 
But  the  different  ways  in  which  this  doctrine  has  been  held 


CHAP.  iv.  of  Original  Sin.  101 

involve  a  discussion  of  some  length  and  difficulty,  to  which 
I  shall  devote  this  chapter. 

The  language  in  which  the  primitive  Church  expresses 
this  doctrine  distinctly  asserts  two  things.  The  early 
fathers,  in  the  first  place,  clearly  held  that  the  sin  of 
Adam  did  not  stop  with  itself;  they  speak  of  the  race  and 
not  of  the  individual  only,  with  reference  to  it ;  and  the 
universal  terms  of  'man,'  'mankind,'  'the  soul,'  leave  no 
doubt  as  to  their  belief  that  human  nature  was  in  some 
way  or  other  affected  by  that  sin.1  Secondly,  when  we 
examine  what  this  universal  consequence  was,  we  find 
that  it  is  called  apostacy,  captivity,  corruption,  and  death.3 
These  are  metaphorical  expressions,  indeed,  and  convey 
no  precise  and  accurate  meaning,  but  they  plainly  signify 
something  more  than  a  privation  of  higher  good,  and 
something  more  than  a  mere  tendency  to  positive  evil. 
This  tendency  existed  before  the  fall,  and  no  mere  increase 
of  it  could  have  brought  it  up  to  the  natural  meaning  of 
these  terms  ;  which  must  therefore  be  taken  to  signify 
positive  moral  evil,  and  to  indicate,  as  the  doctrine  of  the 
early  fathers,  the  positive  sinfulness  of  the  whole  human 
race  in  consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam,  that  is  to  say,  the 
doctrine  of  original  sin. 

But  as  Scripture  reveals  this  consequence  of  the  sin  of 
Adam,  so  natural  reason  certifies,  on  the  other  hand,  that 
nobody  can  sin  but  by  his  own  personal  act,  and  that  one 

1  Justin  Martyr :    Tb  yevos  rStv  irettra  TOV  Kara  fyvaiv. — Horn.  Deus 

avOpdwdsv  6  anb  TOV  'ASayu.  virb  Odva-  non  Auctor  Mali,  s.  6. 

TOV  *tal  ir\avt}v  TT\V  TOV  o<f>ios  eireir-  Of  the  same  generic  sort  are  the 

Tiijcet. — Dial,  cum  Tryph.  c.  88.  expressions,  TJ  irpwTi)  yfvfffis  (Justin. 

Irenseus:  Hominem  (the  race)  ab-  Apol.  1.  61.),  fi  ira\aia  y4i/e<ris  (Ta- 

sorberi  magno  ceto. — Adv.  Hoer.  3.  tian,  contra  Grsec.  c.  11.). 

22.  2  Dominabatur  nobis  apostasia. — 

Tatian  :  irTfpwffis  jap  rr)s  tyvxns  Irenseus,  Adv.  Hoer.  5.  1 , 

rb  TTt/eOjua  rb  re\f lov,  Zirep  airopptyaffa  Quos  in  eadem  captivitate  (Adam) 

8«et  TTfV  apapTiav  eVrrj  &o-irep  vfoffffbs,  generavit. — 3.  34. 

Kal  xajuaiirer^s  e^eVcro. — Ad  Grsec.  Per  priorem  generationem  mortem 

c.  20.  hsereditavimus. — 5.  1. 

Athanasius :    'H   I^UY^   airoffTao-a  Vitium   originis.      Naturae    cor- 

TTJJ  irpbs  TO  Ka\k  6ewpias. — Contra  ruptio. — Tertullian,  De  Anima,  c.  41. 

Gentes,  4.  Nativitatis  sordes. — Origen,  Horn. 

Basil:  'E*caKe607j  f)  4/ux^  ira.pa.Tpa.-  14.  in  Luc. 


IO2  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 

man's  guilt  cannot  be  transferred  to  another.  This  truth 
of  natural  reason  mingled  intimately  in  the  statements  of 
the  early  fathers  with  the  truth  of  revelation ;  so  inti 
mately  indeed,  that  often  no  definite  meaning  can  be  ex 
tracted  from  them.  Two  opposite  truths  are  expressed 
together,  and  side  by  side.1  The  consequence  is,  that 
persons  accustomed  to  the  later  theological  statements  of 
this  doctrine  have  been  often  dissatisfied,  when  they  have 
gone  to  examine  the  earlier  one,  and  have  set  down  the 
writers  as  not  full  believers  in  it.  But  the  truth  is,  such 
mixed  and  double  statements  more  faithfully  express  the 
truth  than  single-sided  ones  drawn  out  in  either  direction 
would,  because  they  express  the  whole  truth,  and  not  a 
part  of  it.  What  appears  to  be  ambiguity  is  comprehen 
siveness,  and  is  a  merit  and  perfection,  and  not  a  defect. 
Nor,  on  the  same  grounds  on  which  the  early  fathers  are 
charged  with  a  disbelief  in  this  doctrine,  could  Scripture 
itself  be  acquitted. 

But  it  was  not  in  accordance  with  the  nature  of  the 
human  mind  to  allow  these  great,  truths  respecting  the 
moral  condition  of  man  to  go  on  thus  mixed  and  united. 
Theology  began  soon  to  draw  out  each  separately  ;  and  this 
mixture  parted  into  two  great  doctrinal  views  or  schemes, 
of  which  the  earlier  took  the  side  of  the  natural  truth, 
the  later  of  the  revealed,  The  earlier  fathers,  without 
negativing  their  witness  to  the  true  doctrine  of  original 
sin  as  expressed  in  Scripture,  and  handed  down  in  the 
Church,  wrote  as  theologians  with  a  strong  bias  in  favour 
of  the  natural  truth;  and  gave  it,  in  their  scheme  of 
philosophy  and  doctrine,  a  disproportionate  expansion. 
Instead  of  leaving  the  truth  of  revelation  in  its  original 
mystery  and  contradiction  to  human  reason,  as  individual 
thinkers  they  modified  and  limited  it,  so  as  to  be  consistent 
with  reason ;  while  a  later  school  went  to  the  other  ex 
treme,  and  developed  the  revealed  truth  at  the  expense  of 
the  natural. 

But  an  account  of  the  doctrine  of  the  fall  will  require 

1  NOTE  XV. 


CHAP.  iv.  of  Original  Sin.  103 

as  an  introduction  some  account  of  the  state  from  which 
this  was  a  fall,  i.e.  of  man's  original  righteousness. 

The  original  righteousness  of  man,  then,  is  universally 
described  in  ancient  writers  as  partly  natural,  partly  super 
natural.  It  was  natural  in  this  respect,  that  it  proceeded 
from  the  exercise  of  a  natural  freewill  and  power  of  choice. 
It  was  supernatural  in  this  respect,  that  certain  supernatural 
gifts,  in  addition  to  freewill,  were  required  for  it.  These 
gifts  could  not  produce  righteousness  unless  his  natural  will 
first  consented  to  use  them ;  nor  could  his  will,  however 
sound,  without  the  inspiring  assistance  of  these  gifts ;  and 
grace  was  necessary  for  the  righteousness  of  man  upright 
as  well  as  of  man  fallen. 

Such  a  doctrine,  however,  requires  some  explanation 
with  respect  to  two  points.  P"irst,  how  could  it  be  main 
tained  with  a  consistent  meaning  that  supernatural  assist 
ance  was  necessary  towards  fulfilling  the  Divine  precepts, 
if  man  had  naturally  freewill  ?  For  we  mean  by  freewill, 
it  may  be  said,  the  power,  supposing  the  opportunity,  of 
doing  or  abstaining  from  any  actions  whatever ;  and  there 
fore,  whatever  impulse  and  facility  might  be  given  to  right 
action  by  supernatural  assistance,  the  poiver  to  act  would 
not  depend  upon  it.  But  to  this  objection  it  may  be  replied 
that,  however  we  may  define  freewill  in  words  as  such  a 
power,  we  do  not  mean  that  it  is  such  a  power  abstracted 
from  all  stimulus  or  motive  supplied  to  our  nature  from 
other  quarters.  Thus,  in  the  sphere  of  common  life,  a  man 
with  freewill  has  the  power  to  do  his  duty  to  his  parents, 
relations,  and  friends  ;  but  he  has  not  this  power  indepen 
dently  of  certain  affections  implanted  in  his  nature  over 
and  above  his  will.  Such  questions  as  these  cannot  be 
treated  satisfactorily,  on  account  of  the  great  defects  and 
obscurity  both  in  our  conceptions  of  our  own  nature  and 
the  language  in  which  we  express  them.  But,  upon  the  most 
correct  idea  we  can  form  of  what  the  will  is,  and  what  the 
affections  are,  it  would  seem  that  neither  of  them  could, 
without  the  other,  enable  us  to  fulfil  our  duties  in  common 
life.  The  benevolent  affections  incline  us  indeed  to  bene 
volent  acts ;  but,  unless  supported  by  the  will,  they  yield 


]  O4  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 

to  selfish  considerations,  and  produce  no  fruits.  The  will, 
in  like  manner,  does  not  enable  us  to  perform  laborious 
services  in  our  neighbour's  behalf  without  the  stimulus  of 
the  affections.  Nor,  did  it  even  enable  us  to  perform  the 
external  acts,  could  it  therefore  enable  us  to  perform  our 
whole  duty ;  such  duty  involving  something  of  love  and 
affection  in  the  very  performance  of  it. 

There  is,  then,  something  defective  in  the  will  as  a 
source  of  action  ;  and  this  defect  existed  in  the  will  of  the 
first  man,  however  sound  and  perfect  that  will  might  be ; 
because  it  is  a  defect  inherent  in  the  will  itself,  and  not 
attaching  to  it  as  a  weak  and  corrupted  will  only.  As 
therefore,  for  fulfilling  the  relations  of  common  life  we  re 
quire  the  help  of  certain  natural  gifts,  such  as  the  natural 
affections  plainly  are,  being  received  from  Grod  at  our  crea 
tion  ;  in  the  same  way  the  first  man,  to  enable  him  to  per 
form  the  spiritual  relations  assigned  to  him,  required  the 
aid  of  certain  gifts  supernatural,  or  such  gifts  as  come 
under  the  head  of  grace. 

But,  in  the  second  place,  granting  that  these  gifts  were 
necessary  for  the  first  man,  it  may  still  be  asked,  why  call 
them  supernatural  ?  They  were  not  supernatural  as  being 
Divine  gifts  ;  for  in  that  case  our  natural  affections  would 
be  supernatural  gifts.  Nor  were  they  supernatural  as  being 
additions  to  his  created  state  ;  though,  had  they  been,  they 
would  not  have  been  supernatural,  because  they  were  thus 
additional.  Is  not  this,  then,  it  may  be  asked,  an  arbi 
trary  distinction  ?  How  can  the  nature  of  a  man  be  defined 
but  as  that  assemblage  of  faculties  and  affections,  higher  or 
lower,  with  which  God  endows  him  ?  and  how  can  we  there 
fore,  out  of  this  whole  assemblage,  single  out  some  as  natu 
ral,  others  as  supernatural  ? 

In  answer  to  this  objection,  it  may  be  enough  to  say, 
that  when  the  fathers  speak  of  these  gifts  as  supernatural, 
they  do  not  seem  to  mean  that  they  were  above  human 
nature  itself,  that  nature  being  whatever  it  might  please 
(rod  by  His  various  gifts  to  make  it,  but  above  human 
nature  as  adapted  to  that  order  of  things  in  which  it  is  at 
present  placed — this  visible  order  of  things  or  the  world. 


CHAP.  iv.  of  Original  Sin.  1 05 

A  world  is  below  or  on  a  level  with  any  pet  of  affections, 
according  as  it  manifests  or  does  not  manifest  the  final 
objects  of  them.  The  world  in  which  we  are  manifests  or 
presents  to  our  sight  the  final  object  of  the  social  affections, 
viz.  man  ;  this  world,  therefore,  is  not  below,  but  on  a  level 
with  the  social  affections.  But  the  final  object  of  the  spiri 
tual  affections  is  not  man,  but  (rod  ;  and  this  world,  though 
it  proves  to  the  understanding  the  existence  of,  does  not 
manifest  or  present  to  our  sight,  (rod.  This  world  is,  there 
fore,  below  the  spiritual  affections  ;  i.e.  the  spiritual  affec 
tions  are  above  this  world.  The  heavenly  world  cannot  be 
carried  on  without  these ;  for  in  heaven  is  what  divines  call 
the  Visio  Dei,  the  sight  of  God  ;  and  therefore  the  supreme 
visible  Inhabitant  of  that  world,  and  omnipresent  as  He  is 
supreme,  would  want  attention  and  regard  without  4hem. 
But,  though  absolutely  needing  the  social  affections  for  its 
maintenance,  this  world  can  be  carried  on  and  its  affairs 
conducted  without  the  aid  of  the  spiritual ;  which,  as  being 
more  than  necessary  for  its  maintenance,  are  therefore  above 
it ;  that  is  to  say,  are  above  nature,  or  supernatural.1 

Such  being  the  composition  of  man's  original  righteous 
ness,  the  earlier  fathers  held  that  the  fall  deprived  him  of 
these  supernatural  gifts,  but  left  him  a  fundamentally  sound 
nature,  while  Augustine  maintained,  together  with  the  loss 
of  these  supernatural  gifts,  an  entire  corruption  of  his  nature 
as  the  consequence  of  the  fall. 

To  account  for  the  rise  of  a  particular  school  of  thought 
is  a  superfluous  task,  when  all  that  we  are  concerned  with 
is  the  school  itself;  and  a  task  often  more  perplexing  than 

1  Man   may  be  considered   in  a  spiritual  and  celestial  life  ;  and  of 

double   order   or   relation.       1.    In  this  life  the  Spirit  of  God  is  the 

relation  to  the  natural,  animal,  or  principle  ;  for  man's  natural  powers 

earthly  life.     And  so  he  is  a  perfect  and   faculties,    even   as   they   were 

man   that  hath  only  a  reasonable  before  the  fall,  entire,  were  not  suf- 

soul  and  a  body  adapted  thereunto ;  ficient  of  themselves  to  reach  such  a 

for  the  powers  and  faculties  of  these  supernatural  end,  but   needed   the 

are  sufficient  to  the  exercise  of  the  power    of     the    Divine     Spirit    to 

functions  and  operations  belonging  strengthen,  elevate,  and  raise  them 

to  such  a  life.     But,  2.  Man  may  be  thereunto. — Bull,  '  On  the  State  of 

considered    in    order    to  a   super-  Man  before  the  Fall/  vol.  ii.  p.  87, 
natural  end,  and  as  designed  to  a 


io6  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 

useful.  Some  reasons,  however,  are  perhaps  discernible  in 
hhe  circumstances  of  the  early  Church  for  the  supremacy 
of  a  milder  interpretation  of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin. 
The  writers  of  that  age  were,  in  the  first  place,  more  imbued 
with  gentile  thought  than  those  of  a  later  era ;  and  the 
Church,  on  its  first  entrance  into  the  world,  was  both  more 
dependent  on  and  less  suspicious  of  the  world's  philosophers. 
It  was  more  dependent  on  them,  because  it  was  as  yet  with 
out  an  established  literature  of  its  own ;  it  was  less  suspi 
cious  of  them,  because  it  did  not  stand  in  so  strong  an 
antagonistic  relation  to  the  world  without,  as  it  subse 
quently  did  when  that  world  had  been  longer  tried,  and 
had  shown — that  portion  of  it  which  remained  without  — 
greater  obstinacy  in  rejecting  the  Gospel.  Earlier  Chris 
tianity  regarded  the  gentile  world  more  as  a  field  of  pro 
mise  ;  and  saw  in  it  the  future  harvest  rather  than  the 
present  foe.  Nor  is  it  to  be  forgotten,  that  the  principal 
writers  of  that  age  themselves,  Justin  Martyr,  Clement  of 
Alexandria,  and  others,  came  from  the  ranks  of  gentile 
philosophy,  and  retained  in  their  conversion  the  intellectual 
tastes  of  their  former  life.  The  early  Church  thus  adopted 
a  friendly  tone  toward  gentile  philosophy, and  acknowledged 
sympathies  with  it.  But  such  sympathies  could  not  but 
raise  the  estimate  of  the  natural  state  of  man;  for  they  were 
themselves  a  tribute  of  respect  to  the  fruits  of  human 
thought  and  feeling  in  that  state. 

Another  reason  for  the  milder  interpretation  of  original 
sin  in  the  early  Church  was  the  great  prominence  then 
given  to  the  doctrine  of  the  Logos,  i.e.  to  the  contempla 
tion  of  our  Lord  as  the  wisdom  or  reason  of  the  Father,  and 
as  such  the  source  of  wisdom  and  enlightenment  to  the 
human  mind ; — the  aspect  in  which  he  is  set  forth  in  the 
opening  of  St.  John's  gospel.  The  early  fathers,  partly 
from  a  peculiar  sympathy  with  it  as  philosophers, — partly 
from  an  acquaintance  with  the  Platonic  doctrine  of  a  Logos, 
which  bore  some  resemblance  to  and  appeared  to  be  a  hea 
then  anticipation  of  the  true  one, — and  partly  to  fortify  a 
controversial  position  against  the  Gnostics,  whose  boast  of 
a  peculiar  inward  illumination  imparted  by  their  philosophy 


CHAP.  iv.  of  Original  Sin.  107 

was  thus  met  on  its  own  ground,  gave  a  conspicuous  place 
to  this  character  of  our  Lord.  The  result  was,  without  any 
intention  on  their  part,  some  loss  of  pre-eminence  to  our 
Lord's  office  of  Victim  and  Expiator.  The  doctrine  of  the 
Logos  divided  a  theological  attention,  which  was  afterward 
given  more  wholly  to  the  doctrine  of  the  atonement.  And 
this  position  of  the  atonement  would  naturally  affect  the 
position  of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin. 

But,  whatever  were  the  reasons,  an  earlier  school  repre 
sented  man's  nature  as  continuing  fundamentally  sound 
after  the  fall,  and  laid  down,  as  the  consequence  of  that 
event,  a  state  of  defect  and  loss  of  perfection  as  distin 
guished  from  a  state  of  positive  corruption.  Man  was 
deprived  of  impulses  which  elevated  his  moral  nature;  but 
still  that  moral  nature  remained  entire  and  able  to  produce 
fruits  pleasing  in  their  measure  to  God.  And  though  it 
was  admitted  that  all  mankind  were,  as  a  matter  of  fact, 
positive  sinners,  such  positive  sin  was  not  regarded  as  the 
necessary  consequence  of  original,  but  referred  to  the  free 
will  of  each  individual,  who  could  have  avoided  it,  had  he 
chosen  -,1  all  that  original  sin  had  entailed  as  of  necessity 
and  beyond  the  power  of  man  to  avoid,  being  a  state  of 
defect.2 

Such  an  estimate  of  the  effects  of  the  fall,  as  it  was 
partly  produced  by,  in  its  turn  produced,  a  more  favourable 
view  of  the  moral  condition  of  that  large  proportion  of 

1  Tb  avdaiperov  rf/s  avQpcaTrivrjs  arbitrio  factus  et  suse  potestatis, 
tyvxris— rb  avre£ov<ri6v — rb  avdai-  ipse  sibi  causa  est,  ut  aliquando 
perov  aSouXwroj/  irpbs  ^^oyyv  fiiov  quidem  frumentum,  aliquando  autem 
—  a'lpfffis  MCTajBoA.?}?  curia  — irpoat-  palea  fiat. — Irenseus,  1.  4.  c.  9.  Id 
peats  tXevOepa — rb  c<p'  vjfuv — a</>'  quod  erat  semper  liberum  in  homine 
tavrov  e\6/*fvos  rb  ayaOov  —  euro-  et  suse  potestatis. — C.  29.  I  give 
Kparr)s. — These  expressions  occur-  below  Tertullian's  elaborate  state- 
ring  in  the  early  fathers  (Justin  ment  of  man's  freewill.  No  dis- 
Martyr,  Irenaeus, 'Clement  of  Alex-  tinction,  as  regards  the  will,  appears 
andria,  Athenagoras,  Tatian,  Cyril)  to  have  been  made  between  man 
are  applied  to  man  fallen  as  well  as  fallen  and  unfallen,  but  man  as  such 
unfallen.  '  All  the  Greek  fathers,'  is  spoken  of  as  having  it. 
says  Hagenbach,  '  maintain  the  2  Bull,  '  On  the  State  of  Man 
avretyvffiov  of  the  human  soul.'  before  the  Fall,'  describes  the  loss 
The  early  westerns  are  no  less  ex-  of  the  supernatural  gifts  as  the 
plicit :  Homo  vero  rationabilis  et  consequence  which  the  early  fathers 
secundum  hoc  similis  Deo,  liber  in  annexed  to  the  fall. 


io8  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 

mankind  which  had  been  in  no  way  relieved  from  them,— 
the  heathen  world.  It  may  be  considered  doubtful  to  what 
precise  extent  S.  Clement  of  Alexandria,  the  earlier  schools' 
great  exponent  on  this  question,  represents  the  sentiments 
of  the  actual  early  Church  at  large  upon  it.  He  acknow 
ledges  in  his  writings  the  existence,  and  answers  the  objec 
tions,  of  a  part  of  the  Church  that  did  not  agree  with  him.1 
But  it  is  difficult  to  j  tidge  of  the  size  or  importance  of  this 
part ;  and  a  great  writer  is  in  later  ages  legitimately  sup 
posed,  in  the  absence  of  express  evidence  to  the  contrary, 
and  if  tradition  has  attached  authority  to  his  name,  to 
represent  the  mind  of  his  age. 

Clement  of  Alexandria,  then,  on  this  subject,  takes  what 
may  be  called  the  natural  view  of  the  facts  which  meet  his 
eye.  He  acknowledges  the  noble  affections,  the  moral 
virtues,  even  the  religious  acts,  of  the  heathen  as  real  and 
genuine,  only  as  not  reaching  so  high  a  standard  as  those 
of  the  Christian.  The  authority  of  Scripture  is  claimed, 
and  the  Apostle  is  cited  as  saying  that  '  the  uncircurncision 
kept  the  righteousness  of  the  law.' 2  There  was  a  first  puri 
fication  of  the  soul,  which  resulted  in  abstaining  from  evil ; 
a  second,  which  advanced  to  positive  goodness.3  Attention 
is  drawn  to  the  moral  lessons  of  heathen  poets,  to  the 
labours  of  lawgivers,4  to  the  ascetic  fruits  of  the  Buddhist 
and  Brahman  religions,5  to  the  worship  which  Athens  igno- 
rantly  paid  to  the  true  God. 

But  the  philosophy  of  the  heathen,  as  the  highest  effort 
of  their  moral  as  well  as  intellectual  faculties,  their  dis 
cipline  of  life  and  school  of  perfection  as  well  as  guide  to 

^   Oi  TroAAoi   Se,  Ka.Qa.Trep  ol  TratSes  TOVTOW    TO     yevos,    ol    fjikv    ~2,apfj.dvai. 

ra    noppoXfaia    OVTWS    oeoiaffi    T^V  avTwi/,  ol  8e   Bpax/J-dvai   KaKov^voi  • 

'EAArj/cV  ^i\o(TO(piav,  (f>o§ov/j.evoi  ^  teal  T&V  'Zap/j.avwv  ol  'A\\6§ioi  irpoffa- 

airaydyr)  aurovs. — Potter's  ed.  v.  ii.  •yopeuo'/iej/oi,     oure    ir6\eis     OIKOVCTIV, 

p.  780.    No!  fafflv  yeypd^eai,  irdvres  otfre     (Treyas    ^Xovff^,     HevSpuv     5e 

oi    Trpb    TTJS     Trapovffias    TOV    Kvpiov,  a.^i4vvvvra.i    <p\oiois,   KCU    a.Kp68pva 

KAeTrrai  etVt  Kal  \7jo-Tat. — Vol.  i.  p.  crtTovvrai,  Kal  vSoopTOis  -^^VKivov- 

oiv,  ov   yd/j.ov,  ov   irai8otro(a.v  tcraffiv, 

Strom.  1.  1.  c.  19.  &o"irfp  ol  vvi/'EyKparyTdi  Ka\ov/Afvoi. 

Ibid.  1.  6.  c.  7.  Elffl   Se   T£>V   'IvSuv    ol  rots  E6vrra 

Ibid.  1.  1.  c.  14,  15.  Trei06fj.ei/oi  irapayyc\iji.ao-ivbv  St'  virep- 

'Ivouv  re  of  IVroo-ocJuo-Tai,  ^A\oi  6o\^v   o-e^TTjros   els   ®eov 

re  <S>i\o<r6$oi   Qdpfapoi.      Airrbv  8e  Kacrt.— Strom.  1.  1.  c.  15. 


CHAP.   IV. 


of  Original  Sin. 


109 


truth,  was  the  great  fact  which  influenced  Clement  on  this 
question,  and  whicli  elicited  his  greatest  admissions,  both 
as  to  the  reality  and  the  source  of  heathen  goodness. 
Heathen  philosophy,  then,  was,  in  his  view,  a  reaching 
forward  to  Divine  truth  and  a  reflection  of  it.  It  only 
taught,  indeed,  comprehensible  and  not  mysterious  truth  ; 
but  the  one  prepared  the  way  for  the  other.  Heathen 
philosophy  was  the  forerunner  of  the  Grospel,1  and,  as  being 
so  excellent  a  thing,  it  could  have  no  other  source  than  a 
Divine  one.  Philosophy  was  the  great  gift  of  God  to  the 
gentile  world  ;  and  the  less  perfect  law  and  the  more  perfect 
law  came  both  from  the  same  Fountain  Head.2  And  though 
some  called  its  truths  stolen  ones,  or  attributed  them  to 
the  devil,  or  to  nature  as  their  teacher ;  still  philosophy,  if 
it  had  stolen  its  truths,  had  them  ;  the  devil,  if  he  taught 


1  'Ope'-yerai    T 

ouSeVco  8e  rvyxdvfi.  —  Strom.  1.  6.  C. 
7.     The  true  Gnostic  or  Christian 
alone  attained  this   knowledge:  'O 
Se    (Kftvos,    TCI    So/coGt/ra 
eli/ai  TO?S   $AArus,  avrbs 
KaTaAa/j.€dv(i  '    Tncrreuo'as   STI    ouSer/ 
aKaTaATjTTTpr/  T<£  vtV  ToG  0eoG.  —  L.  6. 
c.  8.     But  the  heathen  philosophy 
supplied  the  elements  of  the  Divine  : 
Aib   Kal    (rroix€tc«>TaT'*/    T^s    effriv   T\ 
i\o<ro<>ia    TT)S    reAe/as 


TTfpl      TO     VOTJTO,      KO.I      6Ti     TOUTO)!/     TO 

Trvtvp.ariK(aTfpa  avaff'rpftyofj.tvTis.  —  c. 
8.  npo/caTarTKeua£et  rV  68bv  rfj 
PaffiXiKurdrr)  8i$a<TKa\ta.  —  L.  1.  c. 
16*  'AA\a  ffv\Xa/j,€dverai  ye  T(JU 
\oyiit£>s  eTrixetpeTv  ffftrovSaK^r.  avQa- 
iTT6ff0ot  yvdffews.  —  c.  20.  Kairoi  eV 
iro\Ao?s  TO  ^oi/cdra  eTrt^f  ^pet  Kal  iriQa- 
i/ctJerai  QiXoffotyla  '  aAXd  ray  atpe- 
<rejs  ^Trt^air^et.  —  c.  19.  Kal  /car' 
$lJL<l>a<Tiv  Se  Kal  Sidtyaffiv  ol  aKpi€cas 
irapa  "E\Arj<rt  <f>jAo(ro<p7j(ra>'Tes  Sto- 
pSxri  rbv.  ®e6v.  —  c.  19.  IlaGAos  eV 
TOIS  e7rt(TToAo??  ov  <pL\o(ro<t>iav  Sta- 
ov  It6ff/j.ov 


Ttva    ofiffav,     Kal    irpoffiraififiav   rr/s 
oATjflefas.  —  Strom.  1.  6.  c.  8, 


—Strom.  1.  1.  c.  2.  'Aywybv  Se  rb 
epaarbi'  irpbs  T^V  eauroG  Sewpiav,  irav- 
Tbs  rov  o\ov  eavrdv  ry  TT)?  yv<i><r«as 
aydirri  eVtfie&ATjKoros  rrj  dfcapia.  Aib 
Kal  TOS  fVToXas  as  eSco/fev,  ray  TC 
irpoTfpas  rds  re  Seure'pas  e'/c  fj.ias 
apvT'r6^vos  irriyiris  6  Kvpios,  K.  T.  A. 
— L.  7.  c.  2. 

"EffTi  yap  rcf  ovri  ^)iAo<ro</)ia  /j.eyi- 
ffrov  Krri/j.a,  Kal  rip-Ltararov  ©ecU. — 
Justin  Martyr,  Dial.  c.  2.  Though 
in  the  Cohortatio  ad  Gr&cos,  he  dis 
parages  Pagan  philosophy,  while  he 
acknowledges  its  possession  of  some 
truths,  such  as  the  unity  of  the 
Deity  as  taught  by  Plato  ;  which,  as 
well  as  his  doctrine  of  ideas,  how 
ever,  he  considers  him  to  have  got 
from  the  Scriptures  which  he  saw  in 
Egypt  ;  the  latter  from  the  mention 
of  the  pattern  shown  to  Moses  on  the 
mount. — Ad  Grsec.  c.  21.  et  seq. 

Ea  quidem  quse  ad  sapientes  se- 
culi  deveritatis  scientia  pervenerunt, 
Deorevelantepervenerunt;  seddum 
aut  vanse  gloriae  student,  aut  adu- 
lantur  erroribus  vetustis,  aut  metu 
principum  refrenantur,  damnationis 
suse  ipsi  judices  fiunt. — Origen,  in 
Kom.  i.  18.,  vol.  4.  p.  471. 


1  10  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 

them,  had  taught  the  truth  ;  and  there  was  but  one  Author 
of  nature,  i.e.  God.1 

But  gentile  philosophy  is  not  only  referred  to  Divine 
inspiration  generally  as  its  source,  but  especially  to  our 
Lord  as  the  Logos  ;  being  a  fragment  of  that  truth  which 
afterwards  issued  from  the  Incarnate  Word  as  an  harmo 
nious  whole.2  The  estimate  of  the  heathen  world  thus 
gained  another  important  step  ;  and  natural  goodness,  once 
admitted  to  belong  to  it,  did  not  rest  simply  such,  but  rose 
above  nature  and  claimed  affinity  with  grace.  The  dispen 
sation  of  Paganism,  so  far  as  it  contained  truth,  was  but  a 
lower  part  of  one  large  dispensation,  which  our  Lord,  as 
the  Divine  Reason,  had  instituted  and  carried  on  for  the 
enlightenment  of  the  human  race,  and  of  which  the  Gros- 
pel  was  the  consummation  ;  heathens  and  Christians  were, 
though  in  a  different  measure,  still  alike  partakers  of  that 
one  '  Light  that  lighteth  every  man  that  cometh  into  the 
world  ;  '  and  all  mankind,  as  brought  into  union  and  fellow 
ship  by  that  common  participation,  formed  one  religious 
society  and  communion  —  one  Church.3 


1  Ou    roivvv   ^euSrys  r]   (/>iAorro</Ha,  KOI   ol  fj.fv  o>?  (pi\oi,  ol  Se  &s   o'lKerai 
aav  6   KAeVrrjs,  Kal    6  tyevffrT)*  Kara  Tricrroi  •   ol    Se    o>s    a7rA.a)s   oiKtrai  '    6 
jueTaa'XTjjUaTia'iU&j'   eVepyeuis  TO  d\7j-  SiSaa/caAos   ovros  6  TraiSetWi'  /j.varT]- 
07?  Ae'yr?.  —  Strom.  1.  6.  C.  8.    'O  KAfTr-  plots    /J.fV  rbv  yviaffriKOV,    f  \irio~t    Se 
TTjy  o?rep  vq>£X6fj.tvo<i  exei  a\7)6cas  exet>  ayada'is    rbv  iricrrbv,    Kal  TratSem   rfj 
KO.V  -%9vff'iov  ri,Kai>  apyvpos,  K$,V  \6yos,  eiravopQwTiKfj     Si'     at(T07jTi/C7js     eVc/j- 
K&V  S6jfji.a.  —  Strom.  1.  I.e.  20.       fit  yeias  rbi/  aK\i\poKap§iov.   .   .   .   ovr6s 
Se  (6  SidSo^os),   ws    ^^eAns  (^COT^S  eVrtj/    6   SiSous  Kal  TO?S  "EAArjtn  rfyv 
Trpo<pr]revet,    aA7]0r)     apa  'pe?.  —  L.   6.  tyiXoaofyiav,    Sia    rtav    virfp8ee(TT€pcav 
c.  8.     E?T'  av  fyvviK^v  tvvoiav  eVx^J-  ayyeXav.   .   .   .  "Uroiyap  ov  (ppovTifa 
Kfvai   TOUS  "EAArj//as   Ae*yot,   rbi/   rr/s  -rravrcov  av9pa>Tr<av  6  Kvptos  '  Kal  TOVTO, 
(pvffecas    S-n/u-Lovpybv  ej/a  yivuffKopev.  fy  rep  p.}]  SvvaaQai  iraQoi  av  •   ttirep  ov 

—  L.  1.  c.  19.  6efj.ir6v  •    avOeveias  yap   <r7j/ueTo»'  •    ^ 

2  OuTw?   ovv  7}  re  j8ap§apos,  ^   re  rf  ^  /3ouAea-0at  twdfievos,  OVK  aya- 
'EAATji/i/c^j  ^tAoo-ocpia  rrjv  a'iSiav  aArj-  6bv  Se  rb  TrdOos.             TI  K^Serat  TU>V 
Qfiav  ffirapaypov  rtva,  ov  rrjs  Aiovu-  (Jv/j.Trdvr<av  •     '6irep    Kal     KaO^Kfi    r<$ 
ffov    fj.v6o\oyias,    TT)$    5e    rov   Adyov  Kvpicp  Travrav  y  evolve?  •   ffwrrip  ydp 
rov  ovros  ael  ©eoAoyias  TreTroirjrai'  6  Se  eV-ni/  •   ov^l   TWV  /j.cv,    riav  5'    o(/.  — 
Ta§ir)priij.€vao-vv6fls  av6i.s,Kal€voTroL-f)-  Strom.  1,  7.  c.  2. 

jas,  Te'Aejoi/  rbv  i\6yov  aKivSvvws   ev  'Hs  ovv  (rvyKivftrai  Kal  jLUKpOT^TTf 

to-0'   '6n   Karotyerai,  ryv  aX^fiav.  —  ffiSijpow  juolpa  r$  TTJS  'UpaK\etas  \i0ov 

Strom.  1,  1.  c.  13.  Tn/eu^ari,    810    TTO\\UV  ra>v   ffiSr}pwv 

^  3  noi/res  auroO  of  aj/0pa>7rot  •  aA\'  e/cretj/o^eVT?  SaKrvXiwv,  ovrca  Kal  rep 

01  /lev  war'  MyvoHnv,  ol  Se  ouSeVw  •  ayiv  Ttvevpari  Ix^evoi,  ol  per  tvd- 


CHAP.  iv.  of  Original  Sin.  1 1 1 

The  interpretation  of  original  sin,  again,  as  a  privation 
of  higher  good  rather  than  a  positive  state  of  sin,  affected 
the  punishment  which  was  assigned  to  it.  The  penalty  of 
the  fall  was  exclusion  from  Paradise,  and  with  it  exclusion 
from  that  state  of  blessedness  for  which  the  life  in  Paradise 
was  a  preparation.1  Had  man  kept  the  commandment 
given  to  him,  he  would  have  been  allowed  to  continue  in 
a  state  of  earthly  felicity  till  his  obedience  had  been  tried  ; 
he  would  then  have  migrated  by  no  process  repugnant  to 
nature,  but  by  an  easy  and  painless  one,  provided  by  God 
for  this  purpose,  from  an  earthly  to  a  heavenly  Paradise. 
His  disobedience  excluded  him  from  both  these  states.  But 
both  the  earthly  Paradise  and  the  heavenly  one  were  states 
of  higher  good ;  one  of  lower  good  was  still  left  open  to 
him,  as  the  reward  of  such  virtue  as  he  was  still  capable 
of  reaching. 

The  distinction  between  the  natural  and  supernatural 
life,  it  is  to  be  remembered,  is  a  distinction  between  the 
two  states  themselves,  and  not  between  the  dates  of  them, 
whether  now  or  in  futurity.  It  is  one  drawn  from  their 
respective  inherent  characteristics,  which  are  not  affected 
by  the  order  of  time.  Christian  association  indeed  iden 
tifies  the  supernatural  with  future  life,  the  natural  with 
present ;  because  the  future  life  at  which,  as  Christians, 
we  aim  is  a  supernatural  one ;  but  the  two  ideas  are 
not  identical.  The  future  eternal  world  of  the  Pagan,  the 
Mahometan,  and  the  savage  is  a  natural  order  of  things, 
and  even  an  inferior  one  of  that  rank.  A  much  higher  and 
more  moral  eternity  may  be  conceived,  which  would  still 
be,  according  to  the  distinction  which  has  been  laid  down 
on  this  subject2,  a  natural  one.  Such  an  eternity  was, 
according  to  early  theology,  open  to  man  in  a  state  of  ori- 

pfToi,    o'lKfiovvrai    -rrj    irpdrri   ^6vri,  sent   by  God  to   the  Jews   having 

tyftfs  8'  &\\oi  fJ.fXPl  TV*  T€\€vraias.  been  sent  for  their  sake  as  well. 

— L.  7.  c.  2.  '  Tatian,  Ad  Graec.  c.  20.     i&pi- 

Athanasius  (De  Incarn.  c.  12)  ap-  (r64)(ra.v  ol  irpcaToir^affral  airb  TT)S  7775 

pears  to  speak  of  the  heathen  as  in  p*v,  aAA.'  ot/«  e«  TOVTTJS,  KpEtrroi/os  Se 

a  certain  sense  under  the  same  dis-  TTJS  evravQa  SiaKcff^irecas.    See  Bull, 

pensation  as  the  Jews  ;  as  having  On  the  State  of  Man  before  the  Fall, 

the  power  irarpbs  \6yov  yv&vai  from  p.  67. 

the  works  of  nature ;  the  prophets  2  P.  105. 


112 


Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 


ginal  sin,  though  shut  out  from  a  supernatural  or  heavenly 

one ; the  penalty  of  which  sin  was  therefore,  as  regards  a 

future  life,  made  a  privation  only,  and  not  a  positive  pun 
ishment.  As  regards  the  present  life,  the  exchange  of 
pain,  labour,  and  sorrow  for  the  happiness  of  Paradise  was 
indeed  in  itself  positive  punishment.  But  if  transient 
pain  leads  to  an  eternity  of  happiness,  even  of  the  natural 
kind,  the  existence  of  the  creature  is  on  the  whole  a  good 
to  him,  not  an  evil.  And  therefore,  however  it  may  have 
pleased  God  to  lighten  the  state  of  trial  in  the  first 
instance,  and  even  to  make  it  painless  and  happy,  a  pain 
ful  trial  is,  as  the  means  to  so  valuable  an  end,  not  other 
wise  than  a  good. 

The  assignment  of  such  a  punishment  to  original  sin 
was  in  substance  the  doctrine  of  a  middle  state ;  and  early 
theology  may  be  considered  as  having  pointed  to  such  a 
state  as  the  final  condition  of  the  heathen  and  unbaptized. 
In  saying  this,  however,  I  give  what  theology  before  the 
time  of  S.  Augustine  upon  this  subject  as  a  whole  comes 
to,  rather  than  any  definite  doctrine  that  was  held.  If  we 
examine  the  particulars  of  the  early  Church's  view,  or  what 
was  said  at  different  successive  times  on  this  subject,  these 
will  appear  mainly  under  the  three  following  heads  : — 

I.  The  statements  of  the  three  first  centuries  bearing 
on  the  question  are  principally  confined  to  a  general  ac 
knowledgment  of  real  goodness  existing  among  the  heathen; 
such  an  acknowledgment  as  immediately  suggests  future 
reward  as  the  necessary  result,  under  (rod's  moral  govern 
ment,  of  such  goodness  ;  but  without  any  reference,  express 
or  implicit,  to  such  a  result.  These  statements,  however, 
assume  occasionally  a  greater  significance  in  this  direction, 
and  appear  to  include  without  expressly  mentioning,  a 
future  state  of  reward.  The  Logos  or  Son  of  God  is, 
according  to  Clement,  not  only  the  Teacher  and  Light  of 
all  mankind  in  different  degrees,  but  the  Saviour  of  all ; 
dispensing  His  bounty,  in  proportion  to  their  fitness  for  it ; 
to  the  Greeks  and  barbarians  a  lesser,  to  the  faithful  and 
elect  a  greater  share  ;  to  all,  according  to  the  measure 
in  which  He  has  dispensed  His  gifts,  and  the  use  made 


CHA.P.  rv.  of  Original  Sin.  113 

of  them,  awarding  a  higher  or  a  lower  rank  in  the  uni 
verse.1  And  an  express  allusion  to  a  future  life  is  made 
in  the  application  to  the  heathen  of  the  passage  in  Hermas 
relating  to  the  salvation  of  just  men  before  the  law,  be 
stowed  by  means  of  a  baptism  after  death.2  But  while  a 
proportionate  eternal  reward,  in  the  case  of  the  heathen, 
is  pointed  to,  no  positive  line  is  as  yet  drawn  between  the 
heathen  and  the  Christian  states  in  eternity.  One  state 
with  different  ranks  in  it  is  rather  suggested,  and  all  good 
men  considered  Christians  in  their  degree  are  admitted 
to  one  common,  though  variously  arranged,  kingdom  of 
heaven.3 

II.  But,  secondly,  the  concession  to  the  heathen  of 
some  state  of  happiness  after  death  not  being  abandoned, 
we  find,  in  course  of  time,  the  opinion  established  in  the 
Church,  that  original  sin  did  exclude  from  that  place  of 
supernatural  happiness  which  was  called  the  kingdom  of 
God,  or  the  kingdom  of  heaven.  Origen,  while  he  pointedly 
claims  for  heathen  goodness  some  eternal  reward,  and  so 
applies  the  text  '  Glory,  honour,  and  peace  to  every  man 
that  worketh  good,  to  the  Jew  first,  and  also  to  the  Gen 
tile,'  at  the  same  time  excludes  the  heathen,  as  being  still 
under  original  sin,  from  the  kingdom  of  heaven.4  The 
Pelagians,  with  a  doctrine  which  did  not  support,  or  rather 
opposed  such  a  conclusion,  deferred  to  an  established  dis 
tinction,  and  excluded  the  unbaptized,  whom  the  Church 
at  large  regarded  as  under  the  guilt  of  original  sin,  though 
they  themselves  acknowledged  no  such  sin  in  the  first 


1  BeA/riora    aTroAOjU.jSaj'etj/     eV    ry  4  '  Quod  (Rom.  ii.  10)  de  Judaeis 
irai/rl  T^I/  Ta|«/.—  Strom.  1.  7.  c.  2.  et  Gentibus  dicit,  utrisque  nondum 

2  'fls    "AjSeA.,  a>s    Nwe,   a>s  el   TLS  credentibus.     Potest  enim  fieri  .   . 
erepos  8i'/coios.  —  Strom.  1.  2.  c.  9.  ut  Grsecus,    i.e.    Gentilis  justitiam 

8  Tbv  Xptffrbv.  .  .  .  \6yov  ovra,  ov  teneat.  .  .  .  Iste  licet  alienus  a  vita 

irav  yevos  avdpwirwv  /tereVxe  •  Kal  ot  videatur  aeterna,  quia  non  credit  in 

fiera  \6yov  pidxravTfs  xpumavol  elcri,  Christo,    et   intrare    non   possit   in 

Kav  adeoi  evo(j.i(T6i)(rav  •  ailov  iv  "E\-  regnum  ccelorum,  quia  renatus  non 

\i}<Tt  n.ev  SttKpcd-rjs  KOI  *  Hpa/cAeiTos,  est  ex  aqua  et  Spiritu,videtur  tamen 

Kal  ol  8fj.oioi  avTois  •  cV  |8aj8j8apots  Se  quod   per    haec   quae    dicuntur    ab 

'Appaan   Kal  'Avai/ios,   Kal   'A^apias,  Apostolo,  bonorum  operum  gloriam, 

Kal  Murafa,   Kal  'ITAfov,   KO!  &\\oi  et  honorem,  et  pacem  perdere  pe- 

iro\\oi.  —  Justin,  Apol.  1.  46.,  Ben.  nitus  non  possit.'  —  In  Eom.  ii.  10., 

ed.  vol.  iv.  p.  484. 


CHA.P.  IV. 


1 1 4  Different  Interpretations 

instance  from  which  such  guilt  could  arise,  from  this  state 
of  happiness.  The  text,  '  Except  a  man  be  born  of  water 
and  of  the  Spirit,  he  cannot  enter  into  the  Kingdom  of 
God,'  was,  indeed,  considered  to  settle  this  question,  and 
that  in  two  ways  :  first,  as  deciding  that  no  one  in  a  state 
of  nature  could  enter  into  the  Kingdom  of  God  ;  secondly, 
as  deciding  that  the  only  means  by  which  the  penalty  of 
nature  was  removed  was  the  rite  of  baptism.  An  exception 
was  made  in  favour  of  those  who  died  accidentally,  before 
partaking  of  this  sacrament,  having  shown  faith  and  re 
pentance  ;  and  especially  in  favour  of  martyrs.  But  no 
supposition  of  a  subsequent  extraordinary  Divine  mercy, 
and  extraordinary  means,  was  allowed  in  favour  of  the 
rest,  who  were  all,  heathen  and  unbaptized  infants  alike, 
considered  as  cut  off  for  ever  from  the  remission  of  original 
sin,  and  so  as  excluded  eternally  from  the  kingdom  of 
heaven.1 

III.  A  state  of  happiness  after  death,  which  is  not  the 
highest  state,  is  by  implication  a  middle  state.  But, 
thirdly,  a  definite  idea  of  a  middle  state  subsequently  grew 
up.  Two  distinguished  fathers  of  the  Eastern  Church, 
Gregory  Nazianzen,  and  Gregory  of  Nyssa,  leaned  to  it ; 2 
and  the  Pelagians  seem  to  have  held  it  unchallenged  till 
Augustine — who  himself,  in  his  earlier  theological  life, 
inclined  to  it — rebuked  them.  But  this  state  was  intro 
duced  only  to  meet  the  case  of  infants,  not  of  heathens ; 
though  on  the  same  principle  in  which  the  former  were 
admissible  into  it,  the  latter  were  also ;  for  those  who  have 
made  the  most  of  inferior  opportunities  are  in  no  worse 
case  than  those  who  have  had  none.  But  the  early  Church 
stopped  short  of  any  large  application  of  the  doctrine  of  a 
middle  state ;  checked  by  the  absence  of  any  allusion  to  it 

1  Augustine  appeals  to  this  estab-  licus.    (De  Anima,  1.  3.  c.  ix.)    This 

lished  opinion  in  the  case  of  infants  is  opposed  to  the  most  fundamental 

in  his  controversy  with  Vincentius  Catholic   faith — contra    Catholicam 

Victor :— '  Never  believe,  or  say,  or  fundatissimam  fidem.'— De  Anima, 

teach  that  infants  dying  before  they  1.   2.  c.   xii.     See  Wall  on  '  Infant 

are  baptized  can  attain  to  the  re-  Baptism,'  part  1.  c.  15  ;  part  2.  c.  6. 
mission  of  original  sin,  if  you  wish          2  NOTE  XVI. 
to  be  a  Catholic— si  vis  esse  Catho- 


CHAP.  iv.  of  Original  Sin.  1 1 5 

in  Scripture,  and  reluctant  to  give  substance,  shape,  and 
expansion  to  an  idea  in  which  Christians  had  no  practical 
concern,  for  the  aim  assigned  to  them  was  no  middle  one, 
but  the  highest. 

But  while  we  have  before  us  as  the  view  on  the  whole 
of  the  early  Church  before  Augustine's  time,  with  respect 
to  the  virtuous  heathen  and  unbaptized  infants,  partly 
implied  and  partly  expressed,  a  middle  state,  it  is  in 
different  to  the  question  before  us  whether  this  state  was 
a  distinct  one  or  only  a  lower  rank  of  one  and  the  same 
heavenly  state ;  the  only  point  important  to  observe  being, 
that  the  penalty  of  original  sin  was  a  privation,  not  a 
positive  evil. 

The  doctrine  of  original  sin,  thus  explained  and  modi 
fied,  was  not  inconsistent  with  natural  reason  and  justice. 
It  did  not  contradict  the  truth  of  common  sense,  that  one 
man  is  not  responsible  for  another  man's  acts,  because  it 
did  not  attach  any  such  judicial  consequences  to  the  sin 
of  Adam,  as  required  such  a  responsibility  to  justify  them. 
The  penalty  of  original  sin  was  a  particular  state  and  con 
dition  of  the  human  race,  which  would  not  have  been 
unjustly  ordained,  had  there  been  no  original  sin  at  all. 
The  infliction  of  positive  evil  and  pain  as  a  punishment  is 
wholly  contrary,  indeed,  to  natural  justice,  except  on  the 
ground  of  personal  guilt ;  but  every  one  must  admit,  that 
the  Author  of  nature  has  a  perfect  right  to  allot  different 
degrees  of  good  to  His  creatures,  according  to  His  sovereign 
will  and  pleasure ;  and  that  He  is  not  bound  in  justice  to 
give  either  the  highest  moral  capacities,  or  their  accom 
paniment,   the   highest   capacities   for  happiness   to  all, 
because  He  is  able  to  bestow  these  when  it  pleases  Him. 
We  see,  in  the  order  of  nature,  and  in  the  constitution  of 
the  world  around  us,  the  greatest  variety  en  this  head ; 
and  on  the  same  principle  on  which  God  has  created  dif 
ferent  kinds  of  beings  He  may  also  create  the  same  kind 
with  higher  or  lower  faculties.     A  lower  capacity,  then, 
for  virtue  and  happiness  in  the  human  race,  was  no  injus 
tice  as  a  consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam ;  because  it  was 
no  injustice  had  it  been  no  consequence  of  anything,  but 

i  2 


1 1 6  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 

been  assigned  to  man  originally  at  his  creation,  as  that 
measure  of  good  which  it  pleased  God  to  appoint  for  him. 
For,  though  the  fall  was  the  occasion  and  cause  of  this 
measure  being  assigned,  it  is  not  unjust  to  do  that  for  a 
particular  reason  which  you  have  a  right  to  do  without  a 
reason  ;  the  agreement  of  the  act  itself  with  justice  being 
supposed,  no  great  importance,  at  any  rate,  will  attach  to 
such  a  further  question.  Nor  is  temporary  pain,  again,  an 
injustice,  if  it  is  designed  to  lead  to  ultimate  happiness ; 
but  might  have  been  justly  imposed  by  Grod  on  mankind 
at  the  creation,  and  independently  of  the  sin  of  Adam, 
for  that  end. 

From  such  a  limited  and  modified  doctrine  of  original 
sin  let  us  turn  to  the  doctrine  of  a  later  school. 

The  Western  Church  has,  as  a  whole,  entered  more 
deeply  into  the  mysteries  of  the  inner  man  than  the  Eastern 
has,  into  that  mixed  sense  of  spiritual  weakness  and  desire, 
of  a  void  which  no  efforts  can  fill,  and  of  a  struggle  end 
less  upon  all  natural  principles.  This  disposition  has 
characterised  her  great  schools ;  has  largely  hinged  her 
great  conflicts  and  divisions ;  the  portions  which  the  Re 
formation  separated  from  the  main  body  have  retained  it : 
the  Roman  and  Protestant  churches  meet  in  it ;  and  the 
West  has  been  the  providential  exponent  of  the  doctrine 
of  S.  Paul.  Tertullian  first  set  the  example  of  strength 
and  copiousness  in  laying  down  the  nature  and  effects  of 
original  sin;  he  was  followed  by  Cyprian  and  Ambrose. 
But  language  did  not  as  yet  advance  out  of  the  meta 
phorical  stage ;  and  apostacy,  captivity,  death,  in  a  word, 
the  corruption  of  human  nature,  was  all  that  was  yet 
asserted.  But  language  could  not  ultimately  rest  in  a 
stage  in  which,  however  strong  and  significant,  it  did  not 
state  what  definite  thing  had  happened  to  human  nature 
in  consequence  of  the  fall,  and  just  stopped  short  of  ex 
pressing  what, 'upon  a  real  examination,  it  meant.  If  a 
man  is  able  to  do  a  right  action,  and  does  a  wrong  one,  he 
is  personally  guilty  indeed,  but  it  cannot  be  said  that  his 
nature  is  corrupt.  The  passions  and  affections  may  be 
inconveniently  strong,  and  so  the  nature  be  at  a  disad- 


CHAP.  iv.  of  (Original  Sin.  1 1 7 

vantage ;  but  no  mere  strength  of  the  passions  and  affec 
tions  shows  the  nature  corrupt  so  long  as  the  will  retains 
its  power.  On  the  contrary,  the  nature  is  proved  to  be 
fundamentally  sound,  by  the  very  fact  of  its  being  equal 
to  the  performance  of  the  right  act.  The  test  of  a  sound 
or  corrupt  nature,  then,  is  an  able  or  an  impotent  will ;  and 
if  a  corruption  of  nature  means  anything  at  all,  it  means 
the  loss  of  freewill.  This  was  the  legitimate  advance  which 
was  wanted  to  complete  the  expression  of  the  doctrine  ;  and 
this  complement  it  was  left  to  S.  Augustine  to  give. 

S.  Augustine's  position  respecting  freewill  had  its  com 
mencement  at  a  date  in  the  history  of  man  earlier  than  the 
corruption  of  his  nature,  viz.  at  his  creation.  Philosophy 
raises  an  insuperable  difficulty  to  the  freedom  of  any  created 
will ;  for  freedom  of  the  will  implies  an  original  source  of 
action  in  the  being  who  has  it,  original  not  relatively  only, 
in  the  way  in  which  any  cause,  however  secondary,  is 
original  as  compared  with  its  effect,  but  absolutely ;  and 
to  be  an  original  cause  of  anything  is  contrary  to  the  very 
essence  of  a  being  who  is  not  original.  Tertullian  had  a 
distinct  philosophical  conception  of  this  difficulty,  and 
met  it  by  the  only  answer  open  to  a  believer  in  freewill ; 
an  assertion  of  the  truth  together  with  an  acknowledgment 
of  the  difficulty.  Originality  is  the  highest  form  of  being ; 
and  everything  which  does  not  move  itself,  whatever  be  its 
grandeur  or  sublimity  as  a  spectacle,  is  intrinsically  despic 
able,  in  comparison  with  that  which  does.  The  Divine 
Power,  then,  resolving  upon  its  own  highest  exertion,  chose 
originality  itself  as  a  subject  of  creation,  and  made  a  being 
which,  when  made,  was  in  its  turn  truly  creative,  the 
author  and  cause  of  its  own  motions  and  acts.  And 
whereas  the  creature  would,  as  such,  have  possessed  nothing 
of  his  own,  God  by  an  incomprehensible  act  of  liberality, 
alienated  good  from  Himself  in  order  that  the  creature 
might  be  the  true  proprietor  of  it,  and  exhibit  a  goodness 
of  which  His  own  will  was  the  sole  cause.1  And  this  re- 

1  '  Sola  nune  bonitas  deputetur,       bonus  natura  Deus  solus.    .    .    . 
quae  tantum  homini  largita  sit,  id       Homo  autem  qui  totus  ex  institu- 
est  arbitrii  libertatem.  .  .  .   Nam      tione  est,  habens  initium,  cum  in- 


1 1 8  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 

dounded  ultimately  to  God's  glory,  for  the  worthiest  and 
noblest  creature  must  know  Him  best.  Tertullian,  then, 
distinctly  and  philosophically  recognised  a  created  will 
which  was  yet  an  original  cause  in  nature.  But  8.  Augus 
tine,  while  on  the  ground  of  Scripture  he  assigned  freewill 
to  man  before  the  fall,  never  recognised  philosophically  an 
original  source  of  good  in  the  creature.  As  a  philosopher 
he  argued  wholly  upon  the  Divine  attribute  of  power,  or 
the  operation  of  a  First  Cause,  to  which  he  simply  referred 
and  subordinated  all  motion  in  the  universe  ;  and  laid 
down  in  his  dicta  on  this  subject  the  foundation  of  scho 
lastic  necessitarianism.1 

Thus  philosophically  predisposed,  the  mind  of  S.  Au 
gustine  took  up  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  as  handed 
down  by  the  voice  of  the  Church  and  by  a  succession  of 
writers,  and  brought  the  whole  mass  of  language  which 
three  centuries  had  produced,  and  which  up  to  his  time 
had  advanced  in  copiousness  and  illustration,  rather  than 
in  strength  of  meaning,  to  a  point.  He  explained  the 
corruption  of  human  nature  to  mean  the  loss  of  freewill ; 
and  this  statement  was  the  fundamental  barrier  which 
.divided  the  later  from  the  earlier  scheme  and  rationale 
of  original  sin.  The  will,  according  to  the  earlier  school, 
was  not  substantially  affected  by  the  fall.  Its  circum 
stances,  its  means  and  appliances,  were  altered,  not  itself; 
and  endowed  with  spiritual  aids  in  Paradise  ;  deprived  of 
them  at  the  fall ;  re-endowed  with  them  under  the  Gospel, 
it  retained  throughout  these  alterations  one  and  the  same 
unchanged  essential  power,  in  that  power  of  choice  whereby 
it  was,  in  every  successive  state  of  higher  or  lower  means, 
able  to  use  and  avail  itself  of  whatever. means  it  had.  But 
in  Augustine's  scheme  the  will  itself  was  disabled  at  the 
fall,  and  not  only  certain  impulses  to  it  withdrawn,  its 

itio  sortitus  est  formam  qua  esset,  boni    in    homine    et  quodammodo 

atque  ita  non  natura  in  bonum  dis-  natura,  de  institutions  ascripta--est 

positus  est,  sed  institutione ;    non  illi    quasi   libripens    emancipati   a 

suum  habens  bonus  esse  sed  insti-  Deo  boni,  libertas  et  potestas  arbi 

tutione.  .  .  .  Ut  ergo  bonum  jam  trii,  quse   efficeret  bonum  ut   pro 

suum  haberet  homo,  emancipatum  prium.' — Adv.  Marc.  1.  2.  c.  6. 
*ibi  a  Deo,  et  fieret  proprietas  jam  J  See  p.  4. 


CHAP.  rr.  of  Original  Sin.  1 1 9 

power  of  choice  was  gone,  and  man  was  unable  not  only 
to  rise  above  a  defective  goodness,  but  to  avoid  positive 
sin.  He  was  thenceforth,  prior  to  the  operation  of  grace, 
in  a  state  of  necessity  on  the  side  of  evil,  a  slave  to  the 
devil  and  to  his  own  inordinate  lusts. 

Such  a  difference  in  the  explanation  of  original  sin 
necessarily  produced  a  corresponding  difference  in.  the 
estimation  of  heathen  morals.  Augustine  and  Clement 
both  regard  the  heathen  character  as  faulty  ;  but  there  are 
two  distinct  types  of  a  faulty  character.  It  is  a  rule  in 
morals,  that  the  morality  of  the  man  must  precede  the 
morality  of  the  action,  that  some  general  condition  must 
be  fulfilled  in  the  agent's  character  before  any  particular 
act  can  be  pronounced  good  in  him  ;  this  morality  of  the 
man,  the  fulfilment  of  this  general  condition,  is  the  founda 
tion.  One  type,  then,  of  a  faulty  character  is  that  of  a 
character  good  at  the  foundation,  and  only  failing  in  de 
gree  ;  another  is  that  of  a  character  bad  at  the  foundation. 
The  fruits  of  the  former  are  solid,  as  far  as  they  go ;  but 
the  apparently  good  fruits  of  a  fundamentally  corrupt 
character  are  hollow,  and  are  not  real  virtues.  Such  a 
character  may  display,  for  example,  affection  to  individuals, 
generosity  upon  occasions,  or  courage,  or  industry ;  but 
upon  such  a  foundation  these  are  not  virtues.  This  is  the 
distinction  between  the  faultiness  which  Clement  and  the 
faultiness  which  Augustine  attributes  to  heathen  morality. 
Clement  allows  the  foundation  to  exist — this  general  con 
dition  to  be  fulfilled  in  a  degree — in  the  heathen,  because 
he  considers  nature  able  in  a  degree  to  supply  it;  he 
therefore  regards  heathen  morality  as  real  and  solid,  as 
far  as  it  goes,  though  imperfect.  But  Augustine  does  not 
admit  the  power  of  nature  to  supply  such  a  foundation  in 
any  degree  whatever ;  for  constituting  which  he  requires 
a  certain  state  of  mind,  which  he  considers  to  be  only  pos 
sible  under  grace,  viz.  faith,  so  interpreting  the  texts, 
4  Without  faith  it  is  impossible  to  please  Grod,'  and  '  what 
soever  is  not  of  faith  is  sin.' J  He  therefore  regards  heathen 

1  '  Sed  absit  ut  sit  in  aliquo  vera      autem  ut  sit  Justus  vere,  nisi  yivat 
rirtus,   nisi  fuerit  Justus.      Absit      ex  fide:  "  Justus  enim  ex  fide  vivit." 


I2O 


Different  Interpretations 


CHAP.    IV. 


morality  as  bad  at  the  foundation,  and  therefore  as  a  hollow, 
false,  and  only  seeming  morality  itself.  Nor  does  he  admit 
the  existence  of  a  good  heathen,  though  he  admits  that 
the  heathen  did  actions  which  in  Christians  would  be  good 
ones.1  And  though  he  allows  that  the  Divine  image  in 
which  man  was  created  did  not  wholly  disappear  at  the  fall, 
a  remainder  (to  preserve  man's  identity  in  the  two  states) 
of  a  rational  nature  is  alone  admitted.  He  extends  this  view 
to  heathen  philosophy.  Acknowledging  in  some  systems  a 
greater  likeness  to  Christian  truth  than  in  others,  he  speaks 
of  heathen  philosophy  as  a  whole  with  coldness,  distrust,  and 
hostility,  warning  the  Christian  against  it.  He  looks  on 
the  truth  it  promulgates  as  external  to  Christian  truth  and 
not  mingling  with  it,  and  sees  a  barrier  between  the  two 
where  the  earlier  fathers  only  saw  a  gradual  ascent.2 

But,  though  no  goodness  in  the  heathen  is  admitted, 
he  allows  different  degrees  in  evil,  and  that  some  men  in 
a  state  of  nature  have  been  less  sinful  than  others,  such  as 


Quis  porro  eorum  qui  se  Christianos 
haberi  volant,  nisi  soli  Pelagiani, 
aut  in  ipsis  etiam  forte  tu  solus, 
justum  dixerit  infidelem,  justum 
dixerit  impium,  justum  dixerit  dia- 
bolo  mancipatum  ?  Sit  licet  ille 
Fabricius,  sit  licet  Fabius,  sit  licet 
Scipio,  sit  licet  Kegulus,  quorum 
me  nominibus,  tanquam  in  antiqua 
Curia  Romana  loqueremur,  putasti 
esse  terrendum.'— Contra  Julianum, 
Pelag.  1.  4.  n.  17. ;  see,  too,  Contra 
Duas,  Ep.  1.  3.  n.  14.  23. 

'  Hi  qui  naturaliter  quse  legis 
sunt  faciunt,  nondum  sunt  habendi 
in  numero  eorum  quos  Christi  jxisti- 
ficat  gratia ;  sed  in  eorum  potius 
quorum  etiam  impiorum  nee  Deum 
verum  veraciter  justeque  colentium, 
qufedam  tamen  facta  vel  legimus 
vel  novimus  vel  audimus,  quae  se- 
cundum  justitise  regulam  non  solum 
vituperare  non  possumus,  verum 
etiam  merito  recteque  laudamus  ; 
quanquam  si  discutiantur  quo  fine 
fiant,  vix  inveniuntur  quse  justitiae 
aebitam  laudem  defensionemve  me- 


reantur.' — De  Spirit,  et Lit.  1. 1.  n.48. 

2  Eosque  (Platonists,  Pythago 
reans,  &c.)  nobis  propinquiores 
fatemxir.— De  Civit.  Dei,  1.  8.  c.  9. 

'  Gavet  (Christianus)  eos  qui  se- 
cundum  elementa  hujus  mundi  phi- 
losophantur,  non  secundum  Deum, 
a  quo  ipse  factus  est  mundus.  Ad- 
monetur  enim  prsecepto  Apostolico  : 
"  Cavete  ne  quis  vos  decipiat," '  &c. 
(Col.  ii.  8.)— De  Civit.  Dei,  1.  8.  c.  10. 

It  is  worthy  of  remark,  that 
while  Clement  sees  in  the  'rudi 
ments  of  the  world '  which  S.  Paul 
speaks  of,  the  objects  of  intellectual 
apprehension,  as  distinct  from,  but 
subsidiary  to,  those  of  faith  (Strom. 
1.  6.  c.  8.),  Augustine  sees  in  them 
carnal  and  corrupt  ideas  only.  The 
latter  interpretation  agrees  more 
with  the  text,  in  which,  however, 
S.  Paul  is  speaking  only  of  a  certain 
portion  of  heathen  philosophy,  not 
the  whole  of  it :  but  the  difference 
in  the  interpretation  of  the  Apostle 
shows  the  different  feeling  of  the 
two  writers  on  this  subject. 


CHAP.  iv.  of  Original  Sin.  1 2 1 

Socrates  and  Fabricius ;  but  it  is  difficult  to  say  whether 
he  allows,  in  this  admission,  any  relaxation  in  the  servitude 
of  the  natural  will,  any  kind  or  degree  of  liberty  of  choice 
as  still  left  in  it,  or  whether  he  only  means  that  the  evil 
passions  are  less  strong  in  some  natural  constitutions  than 
in  others.  Indeed,  if  it  be  asked  to  what  extent  Augus 
tine's  law  of  peccatum  poena  peccati  operated, — whether 
that  relation  of  necessary  effect  in  which  actual  sin  stood 
to  original  applied  to  all  the  actual  sin  of  man  in  a  state 
of  nature, — whether  the  want  of  power  to  avoid  sin  involved 
in  original  sin  was  a  want  of  power  to  avoid  every  ex 
cess  of  sin  which,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  had  been  committed 
in  the  world, — and  so  whether  the  whole  of  that  mass  of 
depravity  and  crime  which  the  history  of  mankind  pre 
sented  went  back,  according  to  his  doctrine,  to  original 
sin,  as  the  necessary  development  of  that  one  seed, — it 
must  be  replied,  that  his  language  varies  on  this  subject. 
He  sometimes  represents  the  whole  of  this  ma?s  of  actual 
sin  as  the  necessary  effect  of  original,  and  accounts  for  the 
different  degrees  in  it  by  supposing  different  degrees  of 
original  sin ;  that  is  to  say,  by  supposing,  the  impotence  of 
the  will  remaining  the  same  in  all,  different  degrees  of 
strength  in  the  evil  passions  and  inclinations.  Sometimes 
he  only  represents  a  part  of  it  as  such,  and  the  rest  as 
added  by  the  man  himself.1  But  the  language  in  which 
this  modification  of  the  effect  of  original  sin  is  expressed  is 
obscure  and  uncertain ;  nor  is  it  easy  to  see  whether  those 
additions  are  only  additions,  as  effects  or  additions  to  a 
cause,  or  whether  they  are  additions  man  himself  has  made 
in  the  use  of  a  lower  kind  of  freewill  still  left  in  his  nature. 
Thus  much  is  certain,  however,  that  such  a  liberty  of  choice, 
if  it  is  allowed  by  Augustine,  is  not  the  liberty  to  choose 
good,  but  only  lesser  evil,  and  therefore  is  not  properly 
freewill ;  though  whether  a  will  which  can  do  the  one  and 
not  the  other  is  a  tenable  conception,  is  a  question  into 
which  we  need  not  enter. 

Original  sin  was  thus  represented,  in  its  nature  and 
effects,  by  Augustine,  as  positive  sin,  and  not  as,  according 
1  NOTE  XVII. 


122  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  iv. 

to  the  earlier  interpretation,  a  loss  of  higher  goodness  only; 
and  this  difference  was  followed  by  a  corresponding  differ 
ence  in  the  punishment  attached  to  it.  S.  Augustine  held 
a  state  of  positive  evil  and  pain,  and  not  a  privation  of 
higher  happiness  only,  as  the  punishment  of  original  sin. 
Inclined,  at  an  earlier  stage  of  his  theological  life,  to  the 
position  of  a  middle  state  for  unbaptized  infants,  as  a  con 
venient  solution  of  a  difficulty,  a  stronger  subsequent  view 
of  the  guilt  of  original  sin  rejected  it ;  and  in  the  contro 
versy  with  the  Pelagians  he  not  only  attacked  that  position, 
but  made  an  argumentative  use  of  the  contrary  one  as 
proved  from  Scripture.  The  Pelagians  adopted  the  posi 
tion  of  a  middle  state  as  fitting  in  with  their  own  scheme, 
which  they  had  constructed  upon  a  mixed  ground  of  their 
own  peculiar  doctrine,  and  of  deference  to  the  general 
belief  of  the  Church.  Denying  original  sin  altogether,  they 
could  not  admit  any  positive  punishment  as  due  to  unbap 
tized  infants,  much  less  a  punishment  in  hell ;  while  defer 
ence  to  general  belief  prevented  the  assignment  of  heaven. 
A  middle  place,  therefore,  between  heaven  and  hell,  exactly 
served  their  purpose  ;  neither  punishing  the  innocent  being 
nor  exalting  the  unbaptized  one.  But  Augustine  attacked 
this  position  energetically  as  one  which  in  effect  abolished 
original  sin  itself;  arguing  forcibly,  that  only  two  places 
were  mentioned  in  Scripture,  heaven  and  hell,  and  that, 
therefore,  a  third  place,  which  was  neither  the  one  nor  the 
other,  was  an  unauthorised  invention  of  man.  He  then 
used  the  scriptural  position  of  only  two  places  as  a  positive 
argument  in  support  of  his  doctrine  of  original  sin.  For 
if  there  were  only  two  places,  and  those  guilty  of  original 
sin  were  excluded  by  the  general  belief  of  the  Church  from 
heaven,  hell  only  remained  for  them ;  and  a  punishment  in 
hell  necessarily  implied  a  positive  original  guilt  to  deserve  it.1 
The  position  of  a  middle  state  then  rejected,  Augustine 

1  Istara  nescio  quam  medietatem  renatos  ?     Dicite  ergo  hujus  infeli- 

quam    conantur    quidam     parvulis  citatis  meritum,  verbosi  et  conten- 

non  baptizatis  tribuere.'— De  Pecc.  tiosi,   qui    negatis    originale    pec- 

-M-erit.  et  Rem.  1.  28.     '  An  tandem  catum.'— Op.    Imp.   2.   113.      'Qui 

aliquando  extra  regnum   Dei  infe-  velut  defensione  justitise  Dei  niteris, 

lices  futures  fatemini  parvulos  non  ut  evertas  quod  de  parvulorum  non 


CHAP.  iv.  of  Original  Sin.  123 

assigned  a  punishment  in  hell  to  original  sin,  and,  allowing 
differences  in  degree,  still  left  some  degree  or  other  of  that 
punishment  necessary  for  that  sin.  The  heathen  who  had 
not  sinned  against  the  light  had  a  milder  punishment  in 
hell  than  those  who  had ;  but  ignorance  was  only  allowed 
to  procure  a  mitigation  of  it,  not  a  release  from  it.  Those 
who  knew  our  Lord's  will  and  did  it  not,  were  beaten  with 
many  stripes ;  those  who  knew  it  not  and  did  it  not,  with 
few  stripes.1  With  respect  to  unbaptized  infants,  his  lan 
guage  varies  in  strength.  The  severest  consigns  them  to 
the  flames  of  hell ;  the  most  lenient  to  such  a  punishment 
as  left  existence  under  it  better  than  deprivation  of  being ; 
— a  limitation  which  might  appear  to  leave  no  room  for 
positive  punishment  at  all,  as  it  might  be  said  that  it 
would  be  better  not  to  exist  than  to  exist  eternally  in  any 
degree  of  pain  ;  but  such  refinements  are  hardly  worth 
pursuing.  A  middle  language  consigns  them  to  the  mildest 
punishment  which  there  is  in  hell.  On  the  whole,  some 
true  punishment  in  hell  is  assigned  to  unbaptized  infants.2 
This  whole  doctrine  of  original  sin,  its  effects  and  its 
punishment,  we  must  observe,  is  but  the  legitimate  draw 
ing  out,  in  statement  and  consequence,  of  the  true  and 
scriptural  doctrine  of  original  sin.  The  corruption  of 
human  nature  followed  deservedly,  according  to  that 

regeneratorum  damnatione  tota  sen-  Deum." ' — De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.  c.  iii. 

tit   ecclesia,  nunquam   dicturus   es  '  Sicut  enim  non  impediunt  a  vita 

grave  jugum   super  parvulos  unde  eterna  justum  qusedam  peccata  veni- 

sit  justum,  si  non  trahant  originale  alia  sinequibus  hsec  vita  non  duci- 

peccatum.'  —  2.     117-      See    NOTE  tur:  sic  ad  salutem  aeternam  nihil 

XVIII.  prosunt   impio  aliqua   bona  opera, 

1   '  Sed    et    ilia    ignorantia    quae  sine  quibus  difficillime  vita  cujus- 

non    est    eorum    qui    scire    nolunt,  libet    pessimi    hominis     invenitur. 

sed  eorum  qui  tanquam  simpliciter  Veruntamen  sicut  in  regno  Dei  velut 

nesciunt,   neminem   sic  excusat   ut  stella  ab  stella  in  gloria  different 

sempiterno    igne     non    ardeat,    si  sancti ;  sic  et  in  damnatione  poense 

propterea    non   credidit,   quia   non  sempiternse  tolerabilius  erit  Sodomae 

audivit  omnino  quod  crederet ;  sed  quam  alteri  civitati :  et  erunt  qui- 

fortasse    ut   mitius    ardeat.      Non  dam  duplo  amplius  quibusdam  ge- 

enim  sine  causa  dictum  est "  Effunde  hennae  filii :  ita  nee  illud  in  judicio 

iram  tuam  in  gentes   quse  te  non  Dei  vacabit,  quod  in  ipsa  impietate 

noverunt ;  "  et  illud  quod  ait  Apos-  damnabili  magis  alius  alio  minusve 

tolus,  "  Cum  venerit  in  flamma  ignis  peccaverit.' — De  Sp.  et  Lit.  1.  I.e.  28. 

dare  vindictam  in  eos  qui  ignorant  2  NOTE  XVIII. 


T  24  Different  Interpretations  CHAP.  IT. 

doctrine,  upon  the  sin  of  Adam.  But  the  corruption  of 
human  nature  can  only  be  adequately  defined  as  the  loss 
of  freewill  or  necessary  sinfulness ;  and  sin  deserves  eternal 
punishment,  and  deserving  it  will,  according  to  the  Divine 
justice,  infallibly  obtain  it,  unless  it  is  forgiven.  The  con 
signment,  therefore,  of  heathens  and  unbaptized  infants  to 
the  punishment  of  hell,  extreme  result  as  it  was,  was  but 
the  result  of  the  true  doctrine ;  because,  in  the  absence  of 
the  only  authorised  sign  of  Divine  forgiveness,  these  lay 
under  the  full  guilt  of  a  sin  which  deserved  such  punish 
ment.  There  was  no  authority,  indeed,  for  the  positive 
assertion  of  the  fact  of  such  punishment ;  for  the  fact  im 
plies  that  no  forgiveness  by  any  other  means  has  been 
obtained,  and  nobody  can  know  whether  Grod  may  not 
choose  to  employ  other  means  to  this  end  besides  those  of 
which  He  has  informed  us ;  and  if  an  exception  to  the 
necessity  of  baptism  is  allowed  in  certain  cases,  it  can  not 
be  arbitrarily  limited  ;  nor  does  the  doctrine  of  original  sin 
itself  at  all  restrict  the  means  by  which  its  guilt  may  be 
removed.  In  asserting  the  fact,  then,  Augustine  plainly 
exceeded  the  premiss  which  the  true  doctrine  supplied;  but, 
so  far  as  he  left  all,  who  lay  under  the  guilt  of  original  sin, 
under  desert  of  eternal  punishment,  he  no  more  than  drew 
out  the  true  scriptural  and  Catholic  doctrine.  But,  while 
he  interpreted  the  revealed  doctrine  on  the  whole  legiti 
mately  and  faithfully,  he  failed  in  not  seeing  or  not  allow 
ing  a  place  to  the  counter-truth  of  natural  reason.  As 
Scripture  declares  the  nature  of  every  man  to  be  corrupt 
in  consequence  of  Adam's  sin,  and  from  that  corruption 
sinfulness  necessarily  follows,  and  from  that  sinfulness 
desert  of  eternal  punishment, — so  Scripture  and  reason 
alike  declare,  that  one  man  is  not  responsible  for  another 
man's  sins ;  and  from  that  position  it  follows  that  the  pos 
terity  of  Adam  are  not  as  such  sinful ;  and  from  that,  that 
they  do  not  as  such  deserve  eternal  punishment.  It  was 
wrong,  then,  to  draw  out  a  string  of  consequences  from  the 
doctrine  of  original  sin,  and  state  them  as  absolute  truths, 
when  they  were  contradicted  at  every  step  by  a  set  of 
parallel  consequences  from  another  truth,  which  was  equally 


CHAP.  iv.  of  Original  Sin.  125 

certain,  and  to  which  Scripture  itself  bore  equal  testimony. 
It  was  quite  true  that  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  did  it 
stand  alone,  withdrew  from  the  heathen  the  whole  founda 
tion  of  virtue,  and  so  represented  a  good  heathen  as  im 
possible.  But  this  was  only  one  aspect  of  his  state ;  there 
was  also  another,  in  which  he  came  before  us  as  capable  of 
virtue ;  and,  under  the  check  of  a  mystery,  the  plain  and 
natural  facts  of  the  case  might  be  acknowledged.  And  the 
same  may  be  said,  with  respect  to  the  heathen,  on  the 
question  of  future  punishment.  These  were  truths,  then, 
to  be  held  with  a  special  understanding  in  accordance  with 
the  partial  premiss  from  which  they  were  derived ;  they 
were  not  to  be  stated  as  absolute  truths,  such  as  are  drawn 
from  ascertained  data,  like  the  truths  of  natural  philosophy. 
It  was  incorrect  to  deduce  conclusions  of  the  same  certainty 
from  an  incomprehensible  relationship,  which  would  be 
drawn  from  ordinary  and  known  ones,  and  to  argue  in  the 
same  way  from  a  mysterious  Divine  wrath,  as  if  it  were 
the  same  affection  with  which  we  are  cognisant  in  ourselves 
and  in  common  life.  The  doctrine  of  original  sin  ought 
not  to  be  understated  or  curtailed  because  it  leads  to  ex 
treme  conclusions  on  one  side  of  truth  ;  and  Augustine, 
who  is  not  deterred  by  such  results  from  the  full  statement 
of  it,  is,  so  far,  a  more  faithful  interpreter  of  it  than  an 
earlier  school.  But  those  who  draw  out  this  doctrine  to 
the  full,  and  do  not  balance  it  by  other  truths,  give  it  force 
at  the  expense  of  tenableness  and  justice. 

From  the  Augustinian  statements  relating  to  original 
sin  two  inferences  remain  to  be  drawn.  First,  the  doctrine 
of  original  sin  itself  was  a  sufficient  premiss  for  a  doctrine 
of  predestination.  The  latter  consigns  a  certain  portion  of 
mankind,  antecedently  to  actual  sin,  to  eternal  punishment; 
but  if  antecedently  they  deserve  such  punishment,  the  con 
signment  to  it  is  a  natural  consequence  of  such  desert,  and 
is  no  injustice.  But,  secondly,  Augustine  says  more  than 
that  persons  under  the  guilt  of  original  sin  deserve  eternal 
punishment;  for  he  asserts  that  they  are  punished  eter 
nally.  But  such  actual  punishment  is  more  than  a  premiss 
for,  for  it  is  itself  an  instance  of,  predestination.  It  evi- 


126  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  v. 

dently  does  not  depend  on  a  man's  conduct  in  what  part  of 
the  world  he  is  born,  whether  in  a  Christian  part  or  a 
heathen  ;  or  in  what  state  as  an  infant  he  dies,  whether 
with  baptism  or  without  it,  These  are  arrangements  of 
God's  providence  entirely.  If  such  arrangements,  then, 
involve  eternal  punishment,  the  Divine  will  consigns  to 
such  punishment  antecedently  to  all  action—  which  is  the 
doctrine  of  predestination.  A  true  predestination,  then, 
is  seen  in  full  operation  in  his  theology,  before  we  come  to 
the  specific  doctrine  ;  arid  we  have  substantially  at  an  earlier 
stage  all  that  can  be  maintained  at  a  later. 


CHAPTER  V. 

AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE    OF    PREDESTINATION. 

FROM  S.  Augustine's  doctrine  of  original  sin,  I  proceed 
to  his  statements  on  the  subject  of  predestination.  S. 
Augustine,  then,  held  the  existence  of  an  eternal  Divine 
decree,  separating,  antecedently  to  any  difference  of  desert, 
one  portion  of  the  human  race  from  another  ;  and  ordaining 
one  to  everlasting  life  and  the  other  to  everlasting  misery. 
This  doctrine  occurs  frequently  in  many  of  his  treatises  ; 
wholly  pervades  some,  and  forms  the  basis  of  his  whole 
teaching  in  the  latter  portion  of  his  theological  life.  It 
will  be  impossible,  therefore,  by  one  or  two  extracts  to 
represent  duly  the  position  which  this  doctrine  has  in  his 
writings  ;  but  the  following  may  be  taken  as  samples  of  a 
general  language  on  this  subject.1 

1  The  dates  of  the  four  following  about  so  and  alternates  and  oecil- 
ertracts  are,— of  the  first  A.D.  426,  lates  so  long  between  one  conclusion 
of  the  second,  A.D.  428,  of  the  third,  and  another,  that  it  is  with  some 
A.D.  421,  of  the  fourth,  A.D.  417.  difficulty  that  we  ascertain  what  his 
But  the  Liber  ad  Simplicianum,  real  conclusion  is.  He  ends,  how- 
written  A.D.  394,  contains  substan-  ever,  in  adopting  the  strong  inter- 
tially  the  same  doctrine,  though  pretation  of  S.  Paul :  and  his  argu- 
being  written  just  as  he  was  cross-  ment,  which  is  to  reconcile  the  text, 
ing  the  boundary  line,  and  passing  '  Many  are  called  but  few  chosen,' 
from  one  system  to  another,  it  winds  with  an  effectual  call — effectrix  vo- 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  127 

'Whoever,  therefore,  are  separated  by  Divine  grace 
from  that  original  damnation,  we  doubt  not  but  that  there 
is  procured  for  them  the  hearing  of  the  Gospel,  that  when 
they  hear  they  believe,  and  that  in  that  faith  which  worketh 
by  love  they  continue  unto  the  end ;  that  even  if  they  go 
astray  they  are  corrected,  and,  being  corrected,  grow  better  ; 
or  that  if  they  are  not  corrected  by  man,  they  still  return 
into  the  path  they  left,  some  being  taken  away  from  the 
dangers  of  this  life  by  a  speedy  death.  All  these  things 
in  them  He  worketh  whose  handiwork  they  are,  and  who 
made  them  vessels  of  mercy ;  He  who  chose  them  in  His 
Son  before  the  foundation  of  the  world  according  to  the 
election  of  grace  ;  "  and  if  of  grace,  then  no  more  of  works, 
otherwise  grace  is  no  more  grace."  Of  such  the  Apostle 
saith,  "  We  know  that  all  things  work  together  for  good  to 
them  that  love  God,  who  are  called  according  to  His  pur 
pose."  Of  them  none  perish  because  all  are  elect;  and  they 
are  elect  because  they  are  called  according  to  the  purpose; 
and  that  purpose  not  their  own,  but  God's ;  of  which  He 
elsewhere  saith,  "  That  the  purpose  of  God  according  to 
election  might  stand,  not  of  works  but  of  Him  that  calleth. 

If  any  of  these  perish,  God  is  deceived,  but  none 

doth  perish,  for  God  is  not  deceived.  If  any  of  these 
perish,  God  is  overcome  by  man's  corruption ;  but  none 
doth  perish,  for  God  is  conquered  by  nothing.  They  are 
chosen  to  reign  with  Christ,  not  as  Judas  was  chosen,  of 
whom  our  Lord  said,  "  Have  I  not  chosen  you  twelve,  and 
one  of  you  is  a  devil,"  but  chosen  in  mercy  as  He  was  in 
judgment,  chosen  to  obtain  the  kingdom  as  He  was  to  spill 

catio — runs  thus :  Is  it  that  they  are  modo  vocati  accommodare  fidei  volun- 

called  and  that  the  call  is  not  effec-  tat  em  1     He  decides  in  favour  of  this 

tual,  because   they  do  not  will   to  interpretation,  on  the  ground  that  it 

obey  it  ?     This  does  not  agree  with  agrees  with  the  text,  '  Not  of  him 

the  text,  'Not  of  him  that  willeth,'  that  willeth,' &c. ;  while  the  contrary 

&c. ;  for  the   contrary,  not  of  God  cannot  be  said  of  it,   because  the 

that  giveth  mercy,  but  of  him  that  effectual  call  thus  defined  depends 

willeth,  would  then  be  true  as  well.  not  on  man's   will  but   on    God's, 

Is  it,  then,  because  God  calls  some  who  would  have  given  it  to  others 

in  a  way  which  He  knows  will  be  besides  those  to  whom  He  has  given 

effectual,  and  gives  this  call  to  some  it.  if  He  had  pleased.    Quia  si  veUet 

and  not  to  others.     So  that  of  the  etiam  ipsorum  misereri,  posset   ita 

latter  it  might  be  said,  possent  alio  vocare,  quomodo  eis  aptum,  esset. 


I28  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP,  v. 

his  own  blood These  it  is  who  are  signified  to 

Timothy,  where,  after  saying  that  Hymenseus  and  Philetus 
were  subverting  the  faith  of  some,  the  Apostle  adds, 
"  Nevertheless,  the  foundation  of  God  standeth  sure,  having 

this  seal,  the  Lord  knoweth  them  that  are  His." 

Their  faith,  which  worketh  by  love,  either  never  faileth, 
or,  if  it  does,  is  repaired  before  life  is  ended  ;  and,  all  inter 
vening  iniquity  blotted  out,  perseverance  unto  the  end  is 
imputed  to  them.  But  those  who  are  not  about  to  perse 
vere  are  not,  even  at  the  time  when  they  live  piously,  to 
l)e  reckoned  among  that  number;  because  they  are  not 
separated  from  that  mass  of  perdition  by  the  Divine  fore 
knowledge  and  predestination  ;  and  therefore  are  not  called 
according  to  His  purpose,  and  therefore  not  chosen.' — De 
Correptione  et  Gratia,  c.  vii. 

Again :  '  Such  is  the  predestination  of  the  saints,  the 
foreknowledge  that  is,  and  preparation  of  the  Divine  acts 
of  grace,  by  which  every  one  is  infallibly  saved  who  is  saved. 
But  for  the  rest,  where  are  they  but  in  that  mass  of  perdi 
tion  where  the  Divine  justice  most  justly  leaves  them? 
Where  the  Tyrians  are,  and  the  Sidonians  are,  who  would 
have  been  able  to  believe  if  they  had  seen  the  miracles  of 
Christ ;  but  who,  inasmuch  as  faith  was  not  destined  for 
them,  were  denied  the  means  of  faith  as  well.  Whence  it 
is  evident  that  some  have  a  Divine  gift  of  intelligence  im 
planted  in  their  natures,  designed  for  exciting  them  to 
faith,  provided  they  see  or  hear  preaching  or  miracles 
which  appeal  to  that  gift ;  and  yet  being,  according  to  some 
deeper  judgment  of  Grod,  not  included  within  the  predesti 
nation  of  grace,  and  separated  from  the  mass  of  perdition 
by  it,  have  not  those  Divine  words  and  those  Divine  acts 
brought  before  them,  and  so  are  not  enabled  to  believe.1 

\  Ex  quo  apparet  habere  quosdam  ipsa  eis  adhibentur  vel  dicta  divina 

in  ipso  ingenio  divinum  naturaliter  vel  facta,  per  quse  possent  credere, 

munus  intelligentise,  quo  moveantur  si  audirent  utique  talia  vel  viderent. 

ad  fidem,  si  congrua  suis  mentibus  In  eadem  perditionis  massa  relicti 

vel  audiant  verba,  vel  signa  conspi-  sunt  etiam  Judsei  qui  non  potuerunt 

ciant :  et  tamen  si  Dei  altiore  ju-  credere  factis  in  conspectu  suo  tarn 

dicio,  a  perditionis  massa  non  sunt  magnis  clarisque  virtutibus. 
gratise  prsedestinatione  discreti,  nee 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  129 

The  Jews  who  would  not  believe  our  Lord's  miracles  were 
left  in  the  mass  of  perdition,  and  why  ?  The  Evangelist 
tells  us,  "  That  the  saying  of  Esaias  the  prophet  might  be 
fulfilled  which  he  spake,  Lord,  who  hath  believed  our  report, 
and  to  whom  hath  the  arm  of  the  Lord  been  revealed? 
Therefore  they  could  not  believe,  because  that  Esaias  said 
again,  He  hath  blinded  their  eyes  and  hardened  their 
hearts,  that  they  should  not  see  with  their  eyes  and  under 
stand  with  their  hearts,  and  be  converted,  and  I  should 
heal  them."  But  the  hearts  of  the  Tyrians  and  Sidonians 
were  not  thus  hardened,  for  they  would  have  believed  if 
they  had  seen  such  miracles.  That  they  were  able  to 
believe,  however,  was  of  no  service  to  them,  when  they 
were  not  predestinated  by  Him  whose  judgments  are  un 
searchable  and  His  ways  past  finding  out ;  any  more  than 
their  not  being  able  to  believe  would  have  been  of  disser 
vice  to  them  if  they  had  been  thus  predestinated  by  God 
to  the  illumination  of  their  blindness  and  the  taking  away 
of  their  heart  of  stone.1  With  respect  to  the  Tyrians  and 
Sidonians,  indeed,  there  may  be  possibly  some  other  inter 
pretation  of  the  passage ;  but  that  no  one  comes  to  Christ 
except  it  be  given  him,  and  that  this  is  given  only  to  those 
who  are  elected  in  Him  before  the  foundation  of  the  world, 
this  must  beyond  all  question  be  admitted  by  every  one 
whose  heart  is  not  deaf  to,  while  his  ear  hears,  the  Divine 
oracles.' — De  Dono  Per  sever  antice,  c.  xiv. 

Again  :  '  The  Lord  knows  those  that  are  His.  All 
things  work  together  for  good  for  those  alone  who  are 
called  according  to  His  purpose ;  the  called  according  to 
His  purpose,  not  the  called  simply,  not  the  many  called, 
but  the  few  chosen.  For  whom  He  did  foreknow  He  also 
did  predestinate  to  be  conformed  to  the  image  of  His  Son, 
that  he  might  be  the  firstborn  among  many  brethren  ;  and 
whom  He  did  predestinate  them  also  He  called  ;  and  whom 
He  called  them  also  He  justified  ;  and  whom  He  justified 

1  Sed  nee  illis  profuit  quod  pote-  istis  obfuisset  quod    non   poterant 

rant  credere,  quia  prsedestinati  non  credere,    si  ita  prjedestinati  essent, 

sunt  ab  eo  cujus  inscrutabilia  sunt  ut  cos  csecos  Deus  illuminaret,  et  in- 

judicia,  et  investigabiles  vise  ;    nee  duratis  cor  lapideum  vellet  anferre. 


Augustinian  Doctrine 


CHAP.  v. 


them  He  also  glorified.  All  things  work  together  for 
good  to  those  who  were  chosen  before  the  foundation  of 
the  world  by  Him  who  calleth  those  things  which  be  not 
as  though  they  were  ;  to  the  elect  according  to  the  elec 
tion  of  grace,  who  were  chosen  before  the  foundation  of 
the  world  freely  and  not  on  account  of  any  good  works 
foreseen.  Within  that  number  of  the  elect  and  the  pre 
destinated,  even  those  who  have  led  the  worst  lives  are  by 
the  goodness  of  (rod  led  to  repentance  ....  Of  these 
our  Lord  spoke  when  He  said,  "  This  is  the  Father's  will 
which  hath  sent  me,  that  of  all  He  hath  given  I  should 
lose  nothing."  But  the  rest  of  mankind  who  are  not  of 
this  number,  but  who,  out  of  the  same  lump  of  which 
they  are,  are  made  vessels  of  wrath,  are  brought  into  the 
world  for  the  advantage  of  the  elect.  Grod  does  not  create 
any  of  them  indeed  without  a  purpose.  He  knows  what 
good  to  work  out  of  them  :  He  works  good  in  the  very 
fact  of  creating  them  human  beings,  and  carrying  on  by 
means  of  them  this  visible  system  of  things.1  But  none 
of  them  does  He  lead  to  a  wholesome  and  spiritual  re 
pentance.  All  indeed  do,  as  far  as  themselves  are  con 
cerned,  out  of  the  same  original  mass  of  perdition  treasure 
up  unto  themselves  after  their  hardness  and  impenitent 
heart,  wrath  against  the  day  of  wrath  ;  but  out  of  that 
mass  Grod  leads  some  in  mercy  to  repentance,  and  others 
in  judgment  does  not  lead.'  —  Contra  Julianum  Pelay, 
1.  v.  n.  14. 

Again  :  '  There  is  a  certain  defined  number  of  saints 
in  Grod's  foreknowledge  (Dei  prccscientia  definitus  nume- 
rus  sanctorum)  who  love  Grod  because  God  hath  given 
them  His  Holy  Spirit  shed  abroad  in  their  hearts,  and  to 
whom  all  things  work  together  for  good  ;  who  are  called 
according  to  His  purpose  .....  There  are  others,  too, 

1  Cseteri  autem  mortales  qui  ex  cum  et  hoc   ipso  bonum  operetur, 

isto  numero  non  sunt,  et  ex  eadem  quod  in  eis  humanam  creat  naturam. 

quidem  ex  qua  et  isti,  sed  vasa  irse  et  ex  eis  ordinem  praesentis  sseculi 

facta  sunt,  ad  utilitatem  nascuntur  exornat.     Istorum  neminem  adducit 

istorum.  Non  enim  quenquam  eorum  ad  pcenitentiam  salubrem  et  spiri- 

Deus  temere  ac  fortuito  creat,  aut  tualem. 
quid  de  illis  boni  operetur  ignorat; 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  137 

called,  but  not  chosen  ;  and,  therefore,  not  called  accord 
ing  to  His  purpose.  The  former  are  the  children  of 
promise,  the  elect,  who  are  saved  according  to  the  election 
of  grace,  as  it  is  written,  "  But  if  of  grace,  then  no  more 
of  works,  otherwise  grace  is  no  more  grace."  These  are 
the  vessels  of  mercy,  in  whom  Grod  even  by  means  of 
the  vessels  of  wrath  makes  known  the  riches  of  His 

glory But  the    rest   of  mankind — who  do   not 

pertain  to  this  society,  but  whose  soul  and  body,  never 
theless,  Grod  hath  made,  together  with  whatever  also 
belongs  to  their  nature  apart  from  its  corruption — are 
created  by  a  foreknowing  (rod  on  this  account,  that  by 
them  He  may  show  how  little  the  freewill  of  fallen  man 
can  do  without  His  grace ;  and  that  by  their  just  and  due 
punishment  the  vessels  of  mercy,  who  are  separated  from 
the  original  mass  not  by  their  own  works,  but  by  the  free 
grace  of  Grod,  may  know  how  great  a  gift  has  been  be 
stowed  upon  them,  that  every  mouth  may  be  stopped,  and 
that  he  that  glorieth  may  glory  in  the  Lord.'1 — Epist. 
186,  c.  vii. 

The  general  conclusion  to  which  these  passages  point, 
is  that  S.  Augustine  held  the  predestinarian  doctrine ; 
viz.  that  God  by  an  eternal  decree  prior  to  any  difference 
of  desert,  separated  one  portion  of  mankind  from  another, 
ordaining  one  to  eternal  life  and  the  other  to  eternal 
punishment.2  But  it  will  be  proper  to  enter  into  some 
distinctions  which  are  drawn  on  this  subject  in  order  to 
separate  S.  Augustine's  doctrine  from  another  and  a  dif 
ferent  doctrine  of  predestination. 

A  certain  limited  and  qualified  doctrine  of  predesti 
nation  is  held  by  some  schools  of  divines  opposed  to  the 
predestinarians,  who  maintain  the  doctrine  to  be  a  sound 
and  scriptural  one,  but  maintain  the  predestination  to  be 
first  to  privileges  and  means  of  grace^not  to  final  happi 
ness  ;  or,  secondly,  if  to  final  happiness,  to  be  a  predesti- 

1  Ut  in  his  ostenderet  liberum  gratia  sunt  ab  ilia  concretione  dis- 
arbitrium  sine  sua  gratia  quid  va-  creta,  quid  sibi  collatum  esset  addis- 
leret ;  ut  in  eorum  justis  et  debitis  cerent. 

poenis  vasa  misericordiae,  quse  non  2  See  Hooker's  Statements  of  S, 
suorum  meritis,  sed  gratuita  Dei  Augustine's  Doctrine.  NOTE  XIX. 

K  2 


Augustinian  Doctrine 


CHAP.  T. 


nation  in  consequence  of  foreseen  virtue  and  holiness  in 
the  individuals  predestinated.  A  third  modification,  which 
rests  upon  a  distinction  between  individuals  and  the  body, 
and  allowing  predestination  to  be  to  final  glory,  applies  it 
to  the  Church  as  a  whole,  and  not  to  individuals,  is  evi 
dently  only  the  second  in  another  form.  For,  as  no  one 
can  mean  to  say  that  the  whole  of  the  visible  Church  is 
predestinated  to  eternal  glory,  by  the  Church  as  a  body 
must  be  meant  the  truly  virtuous  and  pious  members  of 
the  Church  whom  God  predestinates  to  glory  in  conse 
quence  of  foreseeing  this  piety  and  virtue  in  them.  Now, 
had  S.  Augustine  only  held  predestination  in  this  sense, 
that  God  determined  from  all  eternity  to  admit  a  certain 
portion  of  mankind  to  certain  religious  privileges  and  to 
reward  the  pious  and  virtuous  with  eternal  glory,  he  would 
only  have  held  what  no  Christian,  or  even  believer  in 
natural  religion,  can  deny.  It  is  evident  that  Grod  has 
admitted  a  certain  portion  of  mankind  to  certain  religious 
privileges  to  which  He  has  not  admitted  others  ;  and,  as 
He  has  done  this,  it  is  certain  that  He  has  eternally  de 
creed  to  do  it.  And  it  is  certain  that  God  will  finally 
reward  men  according  to  their  works  ;  and,  as  this  will  be 
His  act,  and  this  the  reason  of  it,  it  is  certain  He  has 
eternally  decreed  the  one  and  foreseen  the  other.  Such 
a  doctrine  of  predestination  as  this,  then,  is  no  more  than 
what  everybody  must  hold.  But  the  passages  which  have 
been  quoted  contain  very  clearly  a  different  doctrine  of 
predestination  from  this.  And  this  difference  will  appear 
the  more  decisively,  the  more  we  enter  into  the  particulars 
of  S.  Augustine's  view. 

In  the  first  place,  we  find  S.  Augustine  always  speak 
ing  of  predestination  as  a  mystery,  a  dark  and  perplexing 
doctrine,  contradictory  to  our  natural  ideas  of  the  Divine 
justice,  and  requiring  the  profoundest  submission  of  human 
reason  in  order  to  its  acceptance.  For  example,  he  says, 
in  the  text  (John  vi.  45)  :  '  Every  one  that  hath  heard  and 
hath  learned  of  the  Father  cometh  unto  me.' 

'  Very  far  removed  from  our  fleshly  senses  is  that 
school  in  which  God  is  heard  and  teaches  —  valde  remota 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  133 

est  a  sensibus  carnis  hcec  schola  in  qua  Pater  auditur 
et  docet.  We  see  many  come  to  the  Son,  because  we  see 
many  believe  in  Christ :  but  where  and  how  they  heard 
and  learned  this  of  the  Father  we  see  not.  Too  secret  is 
that  grace ;  but  that  it  is  grace  who  can  doubt  ?  This 
grace  thus  secretly  imparted  is  rejected  by  no  heart,  how 
ever  hard.1  Indeed,  it  is  given  for  that  purpose,  viz.  that 
this  hardness  of  heart  may  be  removed.  When  the  Father 
is  heard,  and  teaches  the  man  within  to  come  to  the  Son, 
He  takes  away  the  stony  heart  and  gives  the  heart  of  flesh, 
thus  making  sons  of  promise  and  vessels  of  mercy  prepared 
for  glory.  But  why  does  He  not  teach  all  to  come  to 
Christ  ?  Because  those  whom  He  teaches  He  teaches  in 
mercy,  and  those  whom  He  teaches  not  He  teaches  not  in 
judgment.  "  For  He  hath  mercy  on  whom  He  will  have 

mercy,  and  whom  He  will  He  hardeneth." And 

to  him  who  objects  why  doth  He  yet  complain,  for  who 
hath  resisted  His  will  ?  the  Apostle  answers,  not  by  deny 
ing  the  objection,  but  urging  submission  under  it :  0  man, 
who  art  thou  that  repliest  against  God  ?  "  2 

Again :  (  Why,  when  both  alike  hear,  and,  supposing 
a  miracle,  both  alike  see,  one  believes  and  another  does 
not  believe,  lies  in  the  abyss  of  the  riches  of  the  wisdom 
and  knowledge  of  Grod,  whose  judgments  are  unsearchable, 
and  who,  without  iniquity,  has  mercy  upon  whom  He 
will  have  mercy,  and  whom  He  will,  hardeneth.  For 
His  decrees  are  not  unjust,  because  they  are  incompre 
hensible.'  3 

Again  :  '  It  displeases  him  (the  objector  in  Rom.  c.  ix.) 
that  Grod  complains  of  sinners  whom,  as  it  appears  to  him, 
He  hardens.  But  Grod  does  not  harden  sinners  by  obliging 
them  to  sin,  but  by  withholding  grace,  such  grace  being 
withheld  from  those  from  whom  it  is  withheld,  according 
to  an  occult  justice,  infinitely  removed  from  human  per 
ceptions.'  4 

1  Nimium  gratia  ista  secreta  est,  2  De  Prsed.  Sanct.  c.  viii. 

gratiam  vero   esse    quis   ambigat  ?  s  Epist.  194.  c.  iii. 

Haec  itaque  gratia,  quse  occulte  hu-  4  De  Div.  Quaest.  ad  Simplic.  1.  i. 

manis  cordibus  divina  largitate  tri-  Q.  2.  n.  16. 
buitur,  a  nullo  duro  corde  respuitur. 


134  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  v. 

Again :  '  Why  He  wills  to  convert  some,  and  to  punish 
others  for  being  unconverted  (quare  illos  velit  converters, 
illos  ve.ro  pro  aversione  punire),  let  none  presume  to  ask 

as  if  to  blame  God for  the  law  of  His  ^  secret 

justice  rests  with  Him  alone  (consilium  occultioris  jus- 
titice  penes  ipsum  est).' l 

S.  Augustine,  then,  regarded  predestination  as  a  per 
plexing  mystery, — a  doctrine  which  disagreed  with  our 
natural  ideas  of  God's  justice,  and  which  could  only  be  de 
fended  by  a  reference  to  His  inscrutable  and  sovereign  will. 

I  will  single  out  the  term  c  hidden  justice — occulta 
justitiaj  as  expressing  in  a  summary  and  convenient 
form  this  characteristic  of  the  doctrine  held  by  him.  S. 
Augustine  asserts,  as  every  one  who  believes  in  the 
existence  of  a  God  must  do,  that  God  is  just,  and  there 
fore  that  the  decree  of  predestination  and  reprobation 
which  He  has  from  all  eternity  made  is  just ;  but  he  adds, 
that  this  justice  is  of  a  nature  not  addressed  to  our  natural 
faculties  and  perceptions,  or  discernible  by  them.  Natural 
justice — the  rule  of  rewarding  and  punishing  according  to 
desert — is  justice,  and  is  also  a  justice  cognisable  by  our 
natural  faculties ;  predestinating  justice  is  as  real  justice 
as  natural,  but  is  not  thus  cognisable.  The  one  is  justice 
and  also  apparent  justice ;  the  other  is  justice,  but  not 
apparent  justice — i.e.  apparent  mjustice. 

But  such  language  as  this  is  very  inapplicable  to  a 
doctrine  of  predestination,  which  is  no  more  than  the  as- 
i  sertion  that  God  has  determined  from  all  eternity  to  admit 
some  portions  of  mankind  and  not  others  to  certain  privi 
leges  and  means  of  grace ;  or,  that  God  has  determined  to 
reward  or  punish  those  respectively  who  He  sees  will  be 
virtuous  or  vicious.  There  is  nothing  mysterious  in  the 
doctrine  of  predestination  as  thus  explained,  nothing 
from  which  natural  feeling  or  reason  shrinks,  nothing 
which  requires  any  deep  submission  of  the  intellect  to 
accept.  That  God  should  reward  the  virtuous  and  punish 
the  wicked  is  the  simple  rule  of  justice,  and  that  He  should 

1  De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Kern.  1.  2.  c.  xviii. 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  135 

give  privileges  to  some  which  He  does  not  give  to  others, 
is  no  injustice. 

It  may  be  said,  indeed,  that  the  admission  of  one 
portion  of  mankind  to  peculiar  religious  privileges  and 
advantages  not  enjoyed  by  the  rest  is  a  mystery;  that 
there  is  something  inexplicable  in  that  great  inequality 
of  God's  administration  in  this  respect  which  we  see  in 
the  world,  especially  the  remarkable  one  of  one  part  of 
the  world  only  having  been  admitted  into  the  Christian 
Church,  while  far  the  larger  part  has  been  left  in  pagan 
darkness  and  ignorance :  but  it  cannot  be  said,  that  this 
is  a  mystery  in  the  sense  of  being  a  scandal  or  offence  to 
our  reason.  It  is  a  mystery,  in  the  first  place,  as  being  a 
fact  which  we  are  obliged  to  refer  simply  to  the  Divine 
will  and  pleasure ;  but  in  this  sense  many  of  the  commonest 
events  which  take  place  in  the  world  are  mysteries.  It  is 
one  thing  to  be  uninformed,  and  another  to  be  scandalised  ; 
one  thing  not  to  have  curiosity  satisfied,  and  another  to 
have  reason  perplexed.  It  is  a  mystery  also  in  a  sense 
somewhat  stronger  than  this ;  for  without  imposing  as 
obligatory,  our  moral  nature  yet  favours  the  rule  of  equal 
dealing,  and  its  bias  is  in  that  direction ;  so  that  excep 
tions  to  it  are  not  in  themselves  acceptable  to  us.  But 
neither  in  this  sense  is  it  a  difficulty  or  scandal ;  being  only 
the  violation  of  a  rule  which  is  not  obligatory.  Indeed, 
this  bias  of  our  minds  is  one  which  easily  submits,  on  the 
first  due  consideration,  that  there  may  be  good  reasons  for 
the  inequality  we  see  in  the  Divine  dispensing  of  religious 
privileges.  And,  on  the  whole,  provided  the  great  rule  of 
justice  be  kept  to,  that  men  are  rewarded  and  punished 
according  to  their  use  of  the  means  given  them,  the  gene 
ral  sense  of  mankind  allows  the  Almighty  the  right  to 
apportion  the  means  themselves  as  He  thinks  fit,  and  give 
some  higher,  and  some  lower,  without  making  any  diffi 
culty  of  the  matter.  Particular  persons,  indeed,  have 
embraced  so  rigid  and  importunate  an  idea  of  justice,  that 
they  have  not  been  able  so  to  satisfy  themselves,  but  have 
insisted  on  an  absolute  equality  of  spiritual  condition  for 
all.  And  truly  the  idea  of  justice,  like  other  ideas,  may 


Augustinian  Doctrine 


CHAP.  T. 


be  unduly  nourished  ;  and  persons,  by  brooding  narrowly 
upon  it,  may  get  themselves  to  regard  many  things  as 
grievances,  both  in  human  society  and  the  system  of  Pro 
vidence,  which  they  would  not  otherwise  have  done.  But 
such  an  idea  of  justice  is  not  supported  by  the  general 
feeling  of  mankind,  which  has  adopted  a  larger  and  more 
liberal  one. 

Inequality,  then,  in  the  dispensing  of  religious  privi 
leges,  is  not  a  difficulty  to  reason  or  contrary  to  justice  ; 
but  S.  Augustine  speaks  of  predestination  as  a  difficulty, 
and  contrary  to  our  instinctive  ideas  of  justice  ;  and  there 
fore  must  have  included  something  more  than  this  kind  of 
inequality  in  his  idea  of  what  predestination  was. 

Indeed,  the  very  circumstances  of  the  argument  which 
S.  Augustine  is  carrying  on,  if  any  one  will  consider  them, 
will  be  found  to  involve  something  more  than  this  as  his 
meaning  of  predestination  ;  for,  had  he  meant  no  more 
than  this,  there  would  have  been  no  occasion  for  this  de 
fence  of  the  doctrine  at  all.  In  arguing  with  an  infidel  he 
might  have  had  to  answer  the  objection  of  these  inequali 
ties  in  the  Divine  dispensation  ;  but  he  is  defending  the 
doctrine  of  predestination  not  against  an  infidel,  but  against 
a  Christian  objector  —  i.e.  an  objector  who  at  the  very 
outset  admits  such  inequalities,  and  therefore  would  not 
object  to,  or  call  out  a  defence  of  that  doctrine  on  that 
ground.  Indeed,  S.  Augustine's  opponent  is  not  only  a 
Christian,  but  sometimes  even  a  Catholic  Christian,  he 
having  to  defend  this  doctrine  not  only  against  Pelagians 
but  against  opponents  within  the  Church.1  But  it  is 
absurd  to  suppose  such  an  opponent  taking,  against  a 
particular  doctrine,  a  ground  only  suitable  to  an  infidel 
arguing  against  revelation  altogether,  just  as  it  would  be 
absurd,  on  the  other  hand,  to  suppose  S.  Augustine  not 
giving  the  ready  and  obvious  answer  to  such  an  objection 
if  brought.  He  answers  his  opponent  by  referring  him  to 
God's  secret  and  inscrutable  will  ;  but  had  mere  inequality 

1  The  Church  of  Marseilles,  which,  book  De  Co-rreptione  et  Gratia,  and 
through  Prosper  and  Hilary,  pro-  were  answered  by  the  book  De 
tested  against  the  doctrine  of  the  Prcedestinatione  Sanctorum. 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  137 

been  his  opponent's  ground  of  objection,  he  would  have 
answered  him  much  more  decisively  by  referring  him  to 
the  broad  and  evident  fact  of  the  inequality  in  the  Divine 
dispensing  of  means  of  grace  involved  in  the  very  existence 
of  Christianity,  not  to  say  in  the  very  order  of  God's  natural 
providence. 

But  the  general  admission  of  mystery,  darkness,  and 
apparent  contrariety  to  justice  which  S.  Augustine  makes 
with  respect  to  predestination,  is  only  a  preliminary,  how 
ever  decisive  an  answer,  to  such  an  interpretation  of  his 
doctrine  as  would  reduce  it  to  the  qualified  doctrine  of 
predestination  above  referred  to.  The  qualified  doctrine 
drew  distinctions,  according  as  it  wanted  them,  between 
individuals  and  the  body  as  the  subjects  of  predestination, 
between  the  means  of  grace  and  final  happiness  as  the  gift 
in  it,  and  between  foreseen  merits  and  arbitrary  choice  as 
the  reason  and  ground  of  it.  But  none  of  these  distinc 
tions  appear  in  the  Augustinian  statements  of  the  doctrine, 
which  quite  plainly  and  simultaneously  assign  to  predes 
tination  individuals  as  its  subjects,  final  glory  as  its  gift, 
and  a  sovereign  and  inscrutable  choice  on  the  part  of  God, 
as  distinguished  from  foreseen  merits  in  the  predestinated 
person,  as  its  reason  and  ground. 

He  applies,  in  the  first  place,  predestination  to  indi 
viduals,  speaking  of  the  subjects  of  it  as  'these'  and 
'those'  (illi,  isti),  and  'many'  (multi,  plurimi}.  The 
question  put  by  the  objector  to  the  doctrine,  and  met  by 
him  with  the  answer  of  God's  inscrutable  will,  is,  '  Why 
God  liberates  this  man  rather  than  that — cur  istum  potius 
quam  ilium  liberet.'' !  And  the  predestinated  are  considered 
as  amounting  to  a  certain  definite  number  of  persons.  '  I 
speak,'  he  says,  eof  those  who  are  predestinated  to  the 
kingdom  of  God,  of  whom  the  number  is  so  certain  that 
no  one  can  be  added  to  them  or  taken  from  them.' 2 

It  is  evident,  in  the  next  place,  that  S.  Augustine  is 

speaking  of  the  predestination  of  these  individuals  to  final 

glory,  and  not  to  means  of  grace  only  ;  asserting,  as  he 

does,  that  by  predestination  '  every  one  is  infallibly  saved 

1  Prsed.  Sanct.  c.  viii.  2  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xiii. 


Augustinian  Doctrine 


CHAP.  v. 


who  is  saved  —  eertissime  liberantur  qiiicumque  liberan- 
turj  and  that  '  of  the  elect  none  perish,'  l  and  everywhere 
speaking  of  predestination  as  predestination  to  eternal  life. 
It  is  equally  evident  that  he  does  not  mean  that  these 
individuals  are  predestinated  to  eternal  life  on  account  of 
foreseen  goodness  in  them.  This  was  the  ground  on  which 
predestination  was  placed  by  some  maintainers  of  a  quali 
fied  doctrine  on  this  subject  in  S.  Augustine's  time  ;  but 
it  met  not  with  his  agreement  but  strong  condemnation  ; 
and  those  who  held  it  are  argued  with  as  opponents  not 
so  far  gone  as  the  Pelagians,  but  still  labouring  under 
formidable  error.  The  distinction  of  foreseen  merits  was 
a  regular  and  known  distinction  in  the  controversy  on  this 
question  at  that  day,  and  was  thus  disposed  of.  Thus, 
commenting  on  the  text,  '  Ye  have  not  chosen  Me,  but  I 
have  chosen  you'  (John  xv.  16),  he  says,  'This,  then,  is 
the  immoveable  truth  of  predestination.  The  Apostle 
says,  "  He  hath  elected  us  in  Him  before  the  foundation 
of  the  world."  If  this  is  interpreted,  then,  to  mean  that 
Grod  elects  men  because  He  foresees  they  will  believe,  and 
not  because  He  is  about  to  make  them  believing,  against 
such  a  foreknowledge  as  this  the  Son  speaks,  saying,  "  Ye 
have  not  chosen  Me,  but  I  have  chosen  you,"  for  upon  this 
interpretation  Grod  would  rather  have  foreseen  that  they 
would  choose  Him,  and  so  deserve  to  be  chosen  by  Him. 
They  are  chosen  therefore  before  the  foundation  of  the 
world  by  that  predestination  by  which  God  foresees  his 
own  future  work  ;  and  they  are  chosen  out  of  the  world 
by  that  calling  by  which  Grod  fulfils  what  He  predestines.'  2 
Again,  on  the  text  (Eph.  i.  4)  '  According  as  He  hath 
chosen  us  in  Him  before  the  foundation  of  the  world,  that 
we  should  be  holy  and  without  blame  before  Him  in  love.' 
"  He  foreknew,"  says  the  Pelagian,  «  who  were  about  to 
be  holy  and  without  blame  by  the  exercise  of  their  free 
will,  and  therefore  chose  them  before  the  foundation  of 
the  world  in  His  foreknowledge,  because  He  foreknew  that 

2  S!  S°n°  Pers*  c>  xiv>  stitutionem  ea  praedestinatione  in 

Lte  Freed.  Sanct.  c.  xvii.—  Quod  qua  Deus  sua  futura  facta  praescivit  : 

•recto  si  i  propterea  dictum  est  quia  electi  sunt  autem  de  mundo  ea  voca- 

prascmt  Deus  credituros  esse  ----  tione,  qua  Deus  id,  quod  prsedes- 

Mecti  sunt  autem  ante  mundi  con-  tinavit  impleyit 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  139 

they  would  be  such."  But  the  Apostle  says,  "  Chose  not 
because  we  were,  but  that  we  might  be  holy  and  with 
out  blame."  They  were  to  be  such,  then,  because  He 
elected  them  and  predestinated  them  to  be  such  by  His 
grace.' l 

The  text,  again  (Rom.  ix.  11),  respecting  Jacob  and 
Esau,  c  For  the  children  being  not  yet  born,  neither  having 
done  any  good  or  evil,  that  the  purpose  of  God  according 
to  election  might  stand,  not  of  works,  but  of  Him  that 
calleth,'  is  strongly  insisted  upon  as  obviously,  and  at  first 
sight  disproving  the  conditional  ground  attributed  by  some 
to  predestination ;  and  the  explanation  by  which  this 
natural  inference  from  the  passage  is  met,  viz. — that  the 
election  of  Jacob  in  preference  to  Esau,  though  not  caused 
by  any  difference  of  conduct  between  them  at  the  time, 
inasmuch  as  they  were  not  yet  born,  was  yet  caused  by 
the  difference  which  was  to  be  and  which  God  foresaw,  is 
rejected,  as  depending  on  a  distinction  wholly  irrelevant ; 
it  making  no  difference  to  works  as  a  cause  of  election, 
whether  they  operate  thus  as  present  or  as  foreseen  works. 
'  Jacob  was  not  loved  because  he  was  of  such  a  character, 
or  because  he  was  to  be ;  but  he  was  made  of  such  a 
character  because  he  was  loved — non  ideo  quia  tails  erat, 
vel  talis  futurus  erat  dilectum,  sed  talem,  quia  dilectus 
est,  factum.  The  Apostle  does  not  lie.  Jacob  was  not 
loved  on  account  of  works,  for  if  of  works,  then  no  more 
of  grace ;  but  he  was  loved  on  account  of  grace,  which 
grace  made  him  to  abound  in  works.' 2 — '  "  It  is  not  of 
him  that  willeth,  or  of  him  that  runneth,  but  of  God  that 
showeth  mercy  ?  "  God  had  not  mercy  on  Jacob,  there 
fore,  because  Jacob  willed  and  ran  ;  but  Jacob  willed  and 
ran  because  God  had  mercy.  For  the  will  is  prepared  by 
the  Lord.' 3— <  "  Jacob  have  I  loved,  but  Esau  have  I  hated." 
The  Apostle  speaks  of  an  election,  where  God  does  not  find 
something  done  by  another  for  Him  to  choose,  but  some 
thing  to  choose  which  He  Himself  does — "  ubi  Deus  non 
ab  olio  factum  quod  eligat  invenit,  sed  quod  inveniat 
ipse  facit"  As  he  says  of  the  remnant  of  Israel,  "  There 

1  De  Prsed.  Sanct.  c.  xviii.  *  Ibid.  c.  141. 

2  Op.  Imp.,  Contra  Jul.  1. 1.  c.  133. 


140  Augustinian  Doctrine  ^CHAP.  v. 

is  a  remnant  according  to  the  election  of  grace  ;  and  if  by 
grace,  then  is  it  no  more  of  works,  otherwise  grace  is  no 
more  grace."  T  Wherefore  ye  are  foolish  who,  when  the 
truth  says,  "  Not  of  works,  but  of  Him  that  calleth,"  say, 
on  account  of  future  works  which  God  foresaw  that  Jacob 
would  do,  and  therefore  loved  him;  contradicting  the 
Apostle's  own  words.  As  if  the  Apostle  would  not  have 
said,  not  on  account  of  present,  but  of  future  works,  if  he 
had  meant  this — "  quasi  non  posset  dicere,  non  ex  prcesen- 
tibus  sed  ex  futuris  operibus" ' 2 

The  ground  of  foreseen  merits  is  thus  expressly  rejected 
by  S.  Augustine  as  the  ground  of  predestination,  which  is 
referred,  instead,  to  an  absolute  and  inscrutable  Divine 
choice.  Though  one  distinction  must  be  here  made.  The 
most  rigid  predestinarian  must  in  one  sense  allow  that 
God  predestinates  the  elect  to  eternal  life  in  consequence 
of  goodness  foreseen  in  them.  For,  however  absolutely 
(rod  may  predestinate  particular  persons  to  eternal  life  in 
the  sense  of  certainty,  He  plainly  does  not  do  it  absolutely 
in  the  sense  of  requiring  no  qualifications.  His  predeter 
mination,  then,  to  give  them  eternal  life  must  suppose 
the  foresight  of  these  qualifications  for  it  in  them,  though 
it  is  the  foresight  of  qualifications  which  He  Himself  has 
determined  to  give  them  by  the  operation  of  efficacious 
grace.  '  (rod  foresees  His  own  future  work.'  He  has 
decreed  from  all  eternity  to  make,  and  therefore  foresees 
that  He  will  make,  Jacob  of  such  a  character.  But  this 
is  predestination  in  consequence  of  foreseen  goodness,  in 
quite  a  different  sense  from  that  which  is  intended  in  the 
modification  of  the  doctrine  above  referred  to.  The  effect 
of  that  modification  is  to  make  the  whole  of  predestination 
conditional, — God  predestinating  persons  to  eternal  life  in 
consequence  of  something  which  by  virtue  of  the  Divine 
attribute  of  foreknowledge  He  certainly  foresees,  but  which 
is  in  itself  contingent,  depending  on  the  will  and  efforts 
of  the  persons  themselves.  But  of  the  distinction  now 
spoken  of  this  is  not  the  effect.  For  though,  according 
to  it,  God  predestinates  the  elect  to  their  final  reward 

1  Horn.  xi.  5,  6.  2  Contra  Dua8j  Ep.  Pel.  1.  2.  n.  15. 


CJTAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  141 

relatively  to  their  qualifications  for  it,  He  predestinates 
them  absolutely  to  those  qualifications  ;  so  that,  though 
one  part  of  predestination  is  dependent  upon  another,  the 
whole  is  unconditional.1 

It  is  indeed  observable  that,  when  S.  Augustine  is 
charged  by  the  Pelagians  with  fatalism,  he  does  not  dis 
own  the  certainty  and  necessity,  but  only  the  popular 
superstitions  and  impieties  of  that  system.  He  rejects  the 
appeal  to  the  stars  as  absurd,  and  distinguishes  between 
the  operation  of  fate  which  is  for  good  and  evil  alike,  and 
that  of  Divine  grace  which  is  for  good  only  ;  sin  and  its 
punishment  being  referable  wholly  to  man.  But  he  does 
not  disown  a  Divine  predestination,  upon  which  the  future 
happiness  and  misery  of  mankind  depend.2 

Such  being  S.  Augustine's  doctrine  of  predestination, 
the  ground  on  which  the  justice  of  such  a  doctrine  is 
defended  has  already  appeared  in  so  many  of  the  extracts 
given,  that  it  is  hardly  necessary  to  recur  to  it.  Had 
mankind  continued  in  the  state  in  which  they  were  ori 
ginally  created,  the  consignment  of  any  portion  of  them 
antecedently  to  all  action  to  eternal  punishment,  would 
have  been  unjust.  But  all  mankind  having  fallen  from 
that  state  by  their  sin  in  Adam,  and  become  one  guilty 
mass,  eternal  punishment  is  antecedently  due  to  all ;  and 
therefore  none  have  any  right  to  complain  if  they  are 
consigned  antecedently  to  it ;  while  those  who  are  spared 
should  thank  God's  gratuitous  mercy. 

To  this  mass  of  perdition,  this  apostate  root,  we  are 
referred  for  the  defence  of  the  justice  of  predestination. 
4  Those  who  are  not  freed  by  grace,  whether  they  have  not 
had  the  opportunity  of  hearing,  or  whether  they  have 
heard  and  refused  to  obey,  or  whether  they  have  not  lived 

1  '  Effectum  prsedestinationis  con-  Theol.  P.  1.  Quaest.  23.  Art.  5. 

siderare  possuraus  dupliciter  :    uno  2  '  Fatumquiaffirmantdesiderum 

modo  in  particular!,  et  sic  nihil  pro-  positions,  ad  tempus  quo  concipitur 

hibet  aliquem  effectum  prsedestina-  quisque  vel  nascitur,  actus  et  eventa 

tionis   esse   causam  alterius  ....  pendere  contendunt :  Dei  vero  gratia 

Alio  modo  in  communi ;  et  sic  impos-  omnia   sidera    progreditur  .    .    .    . 

sibile  est  quod  totus  prsedestinationis  Deinde   fati  assertores  et  bona   et 

effectus  in  communi  habeat  aliquam  mala    hominum    fato     tribuunt.' — 

causam    ex    parte     nostra.' — Sum.  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  2,  n.  12. 


Augustinian  Doctrine 


CHAP.  v. 


to  be  old  enough  to  hear,  but  died  before  receiving  the 
washing  of  regeneration  to  save  them,  are  all  justly  con 
demned  ;  inasmuch  as  they  are  none  of  them  without  sin, 
original  or  actual.  For  all  have  sinned,  either  in  Adam 
or  in  themselves,  and  come  short  of  the  glory  of  God. 
The  whole  mass,  therefore,  deserves  punishment  ;  and  were 
this  punishment  inflicted  upon  all,  it  would  be  inflicted 
beyond  all  doubt  justly.'  *—  <  It  is  unjust,  say  they,  that 
when  both  are  in  one  and  the  same  evil  case,  this  man 
should  be  liberated  and  that  man  punished.  But  it  were 
just  that  both  should  be  punished.  Who  can  deny  this  ? 
Let  us  give  thanks,  then,  to  the  Saviour,  for  that  He  does 
not  repay  to  us  what,  by  the  damnation  of  others  like  us, 
we  know  to  be  our  clue.  Were  every  man  liberated,  it 
would  not  be  seen  what  sin  deserved  ;  were  no  man,  what 
grace  could  bestow  ....  But  the  whole  lump  deserving 
condemnation,  justice  repays  the  due  shame,  grace  bestows 
the  unmerited  honour.'2  —  'Forasmuch  as  that  one  man 
in  whom  all  have  sinned  is  also  in  each  individual  pun 
ished.'  3  —  '  Grace  alone  separates  the  redeemed  from  the 
lost,  alone  divides  those  whom  a  common  original  sin 
formed  into  one  mass  of  perdition  .....  The  whole 
human  mass  was  so  justly  condemned  in  the  apostate  root, 
that,  were  none  rescued  from  that  damnation,  none  could 
blame  Grod's  justice.  Those  who  are  rescued  are  rescued 
gratuitously  ;  those  who  are  not,  only  show  what  the  whole 
lump  deserved,  even  the  rescued  themselves,  had  not  un 
deserved  mercy  succoured  them.'  4  —  '  Divine  Scripture 
calleth  those  inexcusable  whom  it  convicts  of  sinning 
knowingly.  But  neither  does  the  just  judgment  of  Grod 
spare  them  who  have  not  heard  :  "  for  as  many  as  have 
sinned  without  law  shall  also  perish  without  law."  And 
however  they  may  appear  to  excuse  themselves,  He  admits 
not  this  excuse  who  knows  that  He  at  first  made  man 
upright,  and  gave  him  the  commandment  to  obey  ;  and 
that  sin  has  not  passed  to  his  posterity  but  by  his  misuse 
of  freewill.  Men  are  not  condemned  without  having 

1  De  Nat.  et  Grat.  c.  iv.  8  Ep.  186.  c.  4. 

2  Ep.  194.  c.  2.  *  Enchiridion,  c.  99. 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  143 

sinned,  inasmuch  as  sin  hath  passed  to  all  from  one,  in 
whom,  previous  to  their  separate  individual  sins,  all  have 
sinned  in  common.  And  on  this  account  every  sinner  is 
inexcusable,  either  by  the  guilt  of  his  origin  or  the  addi 
tion  of  his  own  will,  whether  he  knows  or  whether  he  is 
ignorant;  for  ignorance  itself  is  sin  beyond  question  in 
those  who  are  unwilling  to  learn,  and  in  those  who  are  not 
able  is  the  punishment  of  sin.  So  that  of  both  the  excuse 

is  unjust,  the  damnation  just What  did  He  love 

in  Jacob  but  the  free  gift  of  His  own  mercy,  what  did  He 
hate  in  Esau  but  original  sin  ? ' l 

One  peculiar  argument  for  predestination  drawn  from 
the  Incarnation  should  be  added  to  the  general  body  of 
statement  which  we  meet  with  in  S.  Augustine  on  this 
subject — an  argument  which  is  remarkable  as  showing  how 
intimately  the  doctrine  of  predestination  is  connected  with 
the  fundamental  truths  of  Christianity.  Original  sin  is 
its  main  basis ;  but  an  oblique  proof  of  it  is  here  drawn 
from  the  assumption  of  the  Man  Jesus  into  unity  of  person 
with  God.2 

'  The  most  eminent  instance  of  predestination  and  grace 
is  the  Saviour  Himself,  the  Mediator  of  God  and  man,  the 
Man  Christ  Jesus ;  for  by  what  preceding  merits  of  its 
own,  either  of  works  .or  faith,  did  that  human  nature  which 
was  in  Him  earn  this  ?  Answer  :  How  did  the  Man  Jesus 
merit  to  be,  as  assumed  into  unity  of  person  with  the  co- 
eternal  Word,  the  only  begotten  Son  of  God  ?  What 
good  in  him  preceded?  What  did  he  do,  believe,  ask, 
antecedently,  that  he  should  attain  to  this  ineffable  dignity? 
Was  not  this  Man,  by  virtue  of  his  assumption  by  the 
Word,  from  the  first  moment  that  He  was  Man,  the  Son 
of  God  ?  Was  it  not  as  the  only  Son  of  God  that,  that 
woman  full  of  grace  conceived  him  ?  Was  he  not  born 
the  only  Son  of  God  of  the  Holy  Ghost  and  the  Virgin 
Mary  by  a  singular  dispensation  ?  Was  there  any  fear 

1  Ep.  194.  c.  6.  8.  acts  of  the  will  of  the  human  soul 

2  Edwards,  in  his  book  '  On  the  of  Jesus  Christ,    necessarily  holy, 
Freedom  of  the  Will,'  uses  the  same  yet    truly  virtuous,    praiseworthy, 
argument  in   the   chapter  on   '  the  rewardable,'  &c. 


J44  Augustiriian  Doctrine  CHAP.  v. 

then,  that,  on  coming  to  mature  age,  that  man  should  sin 
in  the  exercise  of  freewill  ?  Or,  had  he  not  freewill  on 
that  account ;  nay,  a  will  on  that  very  account,  and  because 
He  could  not  serve  sin,  all  the  more  free?  All  these 
singular  and  wonderful  privileges  human  nature  in  him 
received,  without  any  preceding  merits  of  its  own.  And 
will  any  man  dare  to  say  to  God,  "  Why  was  not  I  so 

privileged? Why,  when   nature    is    common,  is 

grace  so  different  ?  Why  is  there  respecting  of  persons 
with  God  ? "  What,  I  will  not  say,  Christian,  but  sane 
man  would  say  this.'  From  the  case  of  Him,  then,  who 
is  our  Head,  we  may  understand  the  operation  of  grace ; 
how  from  the  Head  it  diffuses  itself,  according  to  the 
measure  of  each,  through  all  the  members.  By  what 
grace  that  Man  was  made  from  the  beginning  Christ,  by 
that  grace  is  every  man  who  is  such  made  from  the  be 
ginning  of  his  faith  a  Christian :  reborn  of  the  spirit  of 
which  he  was  born ;  forgiven  his  sins  by  the  same  Spirit 
by  whom  he  was  made  to  have  none.  This  is  the  predes 
tination  of  saints,  which  shone  chiefly  in  him  who  is  the 
Saint  of  saints.  In  so  far  as  he  was  Man,  the  Lord  of 
glory  was  Himself  predestinated — predestinated  to  be  the 

Son  of  God Jesus  was  predestinated  to  be  of  the 

seed  of  David  according  to  the  flesh,  and  according  to  the 

Spirit  of  holiness  the  Son  of  God  with  power As, 

then,  that  one  Man  was  predestinated  to  be  our  Head,  so 
are  we  many  predestinated  to  be  his  members.  Let  human 
merits,  which  perished  in  Adam,  be  silent,  and  let  grace 
reign.  Whoever  finds  in  our  Head  preceding  merits  to 
cause  his  singular  generation,  may  find  in  his  members 
the  same  to  cause  their  regeneration.  But  as  that  gene 
ration  was  not  a  reward,  but  a  free  gift  to  Christ,  so  is  our 

regeneration  no  reward,  but  a  free  gift  to  us He 

makes  us  believe  in  Christ,  who  made  him  that  Christ  in 
whom  we  believe.1 

Again :  '  God  therefore  took  the  nature  of  man,  i.e. 
the  rational  soul  and  flesh  of  the  Man  Christ,  by  a  singu- 

1  De  Prsed.  Sanct,  c.  xv.     See  De  Dono  Perseverantise,  c.  xxiv.,    Op. 
Imp.  1.  1.  c.  138. 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  145 

larly  wonderful  and  wonderfully  singular  adoption  ;  so  that, 
without  any  preceding  merits,  that  Man  was  from  the 
beginning  of  his  human  life  the  Son  of  God,  even  as  he 
was  one  Person  with  the  Word,  which  is  without  beginning. 
For  no  one  is  so  blindly  ignorant  as  to  dare  to  say  that, 
born  of  the  Holy  Spirit  and  the  Virgin  Mary,  the  Son  of 
Man,  he  obtained,  by  the  merit  of  a  sinless  life  and  the 
good  use  of  freewill,  the  Divine  Sonship  ;— to  say  this  in 
the  face  of  the  text :  "  The  Word  was  made  flesh.''  For 
where  did  this  take  place  but  in  the  Virgin's  womb,  where 
the  Man  Christ  began  to  be That  gratuitous  nati 
vity  joined  in  unity  of  person  man  with  God,  the  flesh  with 
the  Word.  Good  works  then  followed  that  nativity,  and 
did  not  merit  it.  There  was  no  risk,  when  human  nature 
was  thus  ineffably  taken  into  unity  of  Person  by  the  Word 
of  God,  that  it  should  sin  in  the  exercise  of  freewill: — that 
nature  being  so  assumed  by  God  that  it  admitted  of  no 
evil  motion  of  the  will.  As,  therefore,  this  Mediator  was, 
by  reason  of  his  assumption,  never  evil  but  always  good  ; 
so  those  whom  God  redeems  by  his  blood  are  made  by  him 
eternally  good  out  of  evil.'  l 

This  is  an  argument,  however,  for  predestination  which 
admits  of  much  the  same  answer  which  was  given  to  the 
argument  drawn  from  original  sin.  The  sinless  life  of  the 
Man  Jesus  was  undoubtedly  an  infallible  consequence  of 
the  Incarnation ;  for  He  could  not  be  one  with  God  and 
be  capable  of  sinning.  His  goodness  was  therefore  a  ne 
cessary  goodness  ;  and  one  Man,  in  being  predestinated 
from  all  eternity  to  a  union  with  God,  was  predestinated 
to  a  perfect  holiness.  The  Incarnation  is  thus  a  premiss 
for  a  doctrine  of  predestination.  But  it  should  be  remem 
bered  what  kind  of  premiss  this  is,  that  it  is  not  a  truth  of 
nature  or  reason  which  we  comprehend,  but  a  mysterious 
and  incomprehensible  truth  ;  and  therefore  that  the  infer 
ence  drawn  from  it  is  alike  a  mystery  and  not  an  ascer 
tained  and  complete  truth,  like  a  logical  consequence  from 
a  known  premiss. 

The  conclusion,  then,  to  which  S.  Augustine's  general 
1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xi. 
L 


Augustinian  Doctrine 


CHAP.   V. 


statements,  given  at  the  commencement  of  this  chapter, 
of  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  naturally  led,  has  only 
obtained  confirmation  and  accuracy  from  further  examina 
tion  and  the  subsequent  particulars  into  which  we  have 
entered.  The  characteristic  of  S.  Augustine's  doctrine, 
compared  with  the  scriptural  one  is,  that  it  is  a  definite 
and  absolute  doctrine.  Scripture,  as  a  whole,  as  has  been 
said,1  only  informs  us  of  a  mystery  on  the  subject ;  that 
is  to  say,  while  it  informs  us  that  there  is  a  truth  on  the 
subject,  it  makes  no  consistent  statement  of  it,  but  asserts 
contrary  truths,  counterbalancing  those  passages  which 
convey  the  predestinarian  doctrine  by  passages  as  plain  the 
other  way  ;  but  S.  Augustine  makes  predestinarian  state 
ments  and  does  not  balance  them  by  contrary  ones.  Kather 
he  endeavours  to  explain  away  those  contrary  statements 
in  Scripture.  Thus  he  evades  the  natural  force  of  the 
text  that  '  G-od  would  have  all  men  to  be  saved,'  by  sup 
posing  that  it  only  means  that  no  man  is  saved  except 
through  the  will  of  Grod  ; 2  or  that  '  all '  means  not  all  men, 
but  some  out  of  all  classes  and  ranks  of  men  :  on  the  same 
rule  on  which  we  understand  the  phrase  '  ye  tithe  all  herb,'3 
as  meaning  not  that  the  Pharisees  gave  literally  a  tenth 
of  all  the  herbs  in  the  world,  but  only  of  all  kinds  of 
herbs.4 

1  Chapter  II.  is   no  difference,  all  deserving  eon- 

2  Enchiridion,    c.    ciii. ;     Contra  demnation.     Upon  this   ground    S. 
Jwl.  Pelag.  1.  4.  c.  viii. ;  Ep.  217.  Augustine     rejects    his    opponent's 
c.  vi.  application  of  this  text  altogether 

3  Luke  ii.  42.  as  incorrect :  '  Nee  ulla  est  acceptio 

4  '  Neque   enim    Phariscei  omnia  personarum,   in  duobus  debitoribus 
olera  decimabant.    .  .  .  Ita  et  illic  sequaliter  reis,    si  alteri   dimittitur 
omnes    homines,    omne     hominum  alteri     exigitur,    quod    pariter   ab 
genus    intelligere    possumus.' — En-  utroque  debetur.' — Contra  Duas,  Ep. 
chiridion,  c.  ciii.  1.   2.    c.   7.     '  Cur  ergo   in  regnum 

The  text  that  God  is  no  respecter  coelorum,  non  accepto  regenerationis 

of  persons  is,  in  its  general  spirit,  a  lavacro,   parvulus  nullus   intrabit? 

counter  text  to  the  predestinarian  Nunquidnam  ipse  sibi  parentes  infi- 

ones.     But  its    opposition    is    not  deles  Arel  negligentes,  de  quibus  nas- 

exact,  because  it  supposes  a  differ-  ceretur  elegit  ?     Quid  dicam  de  ino- 

ence  of  rank,    or  other  advantages,  pinatiset  repentinis  innumerabilibus 

in  the  individuals,  which  is  not  re-  mortibus,  quibus  ssepe  etiam  religio- 

spected  ;  whereas  predestination  ap-  sorum  Christianorum  prsesumuntiir, 

plies  to  those  between  whom  there  et  baptismo  praeripiuntur  infantes; 


CHAP.  v.  of  Predestination.  147 

S.  Augustine  then  takes  that  further  step  which  Scrip 
ture  avoids  taking,  and  asserts  a  determinate  doctrine  of 
predestination.  He  erects  those  passages  of  Scripture 
which  are  suggestive  of  predestination  into  a  system,  ex 
plaining  away  the  opposite  ones  ;  and  converts  the  obscurity 
and  inconsistency  of  Scripture  language  into  that  clearness 
and  consistency  by  which  a  definite  truth  is  stated.  His 
was  the  error  of  those  who  follow  without  due  consideration 
that  strong  first  impression  which  the  human  mind  enter 
tains,  that  there  must  be  some  definite  truth  to  be  arrived 
at  on  the  question  under  consideration,  whatever  it  may 
be :  and  who  therefore  imagine  that  they  cannot  but  be 
doing  service,  if  they  only  add  to  what  is  defective  enough 
to  make  it  complete,  or  take  away  from  what  is  ambiguous 
enough  to  make  it  decisive.  Assuming  arrival  at  some 
determinate  truth  necessary,  he  gave  an  exclusive  develop 
ment  to  those  parts  of  Scripture  which  he  had  previously 
fixed  on  as  containing,  in  distinction  to  any  apparently 
opposite  ones,  its  real  meaning.  But  the  assumption  itself 
was  gratuitous.  There  is  no  reason  why  Scripture  should 
not  designedly  limit  itself,  and  stop  short  of  expressing 
definite  truth ;  though  whether  it  does  so  or  not  is  a  ques 
tion  of  fact.  If  Revelation  as  a  whole  does  not  state  a 
truth  of  predestination,  that  stopping  short  is  as  much  a 
designed  stopping  short,  as  a  statement  would  have  been 
a  designed  statement.  Nor  are  we  to  be  discontented 
with  the  former  issue,  when  the  comparison  of  one  part  of 
(rod's  word  with  another  fairly  leads  to  it ;  to  suppose  that 
an  indeterminate  conclusion  must  be  a  wrong  one,  and  to 
proceed  to  obtain  by  forced  interpretation  what  we  had 
failed  to  do  by  natural.  If  Revelation  as  a  whole  does  not 
speak  explicitly,  Revelation  did  not  intend  to  do  so  :  and  to 
impose  a  definite  truth  upon  it,  when  it  designedly  stops 
short  of  one,  is  as  real  an  error  of  interpretation  as  to  deny 
a  truth  which  it  expresses. 

cum  e  contrario  sacrilegorum  et  tent,  ista  considerent,  hie  audeant 
inimicorum.  Christi  aliquo  modo  in  dicere  Deum  vel  acceptorem  in  sua 
Christianorum  manus  venientes,  ex  gratia  personarum,  vel  remunera- 
hac  vita  non  sine  sacramento  rege-  torem  meritorum.' — Ep.  194.  n.  32. 
nerationis  emigrent.  .  .  .  Ista  cogi- 

r.  2 


148  Angus finian  CHAP.  vr. 

CHAPTER  VI. 

AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE    OF    GRACE. 

THE  doctrine  of  absolute  predestination  implies  the  doctrine 
of  efficacious  or  irresistible  grace,  for  the  end  implies  the 
means ;  and  therefore,  if  eternal  life  is  ensured,  the  ne 
cessary  qualifications  for  that  life,  which  are  holiness  and 
virtue,  must  be  earned  also.  But  these  can  only  be  en 
sured  by  such  a  Divine  influence  as  does  not  depend  for 
its  effect  on  the  contingency  of  man's  will;  i.e.  by  what 
divines  call  irresistible  or  efficacious  grace — a  grace  which 
S.  Augustine  accordingly  maintains. 

The  language  which  the  Church  has  always  used  for 
expressing  the  relation  in  which  grace  stands  to  the  human 
will  has  been  that  grace  assists  the  will ;  and  such  a  term 
implies  in  its  natural  meaning  an  original  power  in  our 
selves,  to  which  this  assistance  was  given,  and  by  which  it 
must  be  used — an  assistance,  in  short,  which  is  no  more 
than  assistance.  S.  Augustine,  however,  in  adopting  the 
authorised  expression,  and  speaking  of  grace  as  assistance, 
is  obliged  by  his  system  to  use  the  term  in  a  meaning 
exceeding  this  natural  and  obvious  one,  viz.  not  as  assist 
ance,  but  as  control ;  though  he  arrives  at  his  definition 
of  such  a  controlling  grace  only  gradually,  after  long 
familiarity  with  the  subject,  and  when  controversy  has 
strengthened  and  sharpened  his  ideas. 

S.  Augustine  early  in  his  theological  life  commits  him 
self  to  an  idea  of  the  Divine  Power  as  being  a  power  of 
creating  perfect  goodness  in  the  creature,  and  defends  in 
his  book  De  Lihero  Arbitrio,  written  against  the  Mani- 
cheans,  the  act  of  God  in  not  creating  man  thus  perfect 
at  once,  but  only  with  the  power  of  becoming  so  ;  arguing 
that  Grocl  dispensed  different  kinds  of  advantages  1  accord- 

1  'Bona  quibus  male  uti   mains  other  goodness  itself.— De  Lib.  Arb. 

potest,   et  quorum   esse   usus   non  1.  2.  c.  17.,  et  seq.  ;  De  Pecc.  Merit. 

potest  malus;'  the  one  being  free-  et  Remiss.  1.  2.  c.  18. 
will  or  the  power  of  being  good,  the 


CHAP.  vi.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  \  49 

ing  to  His  own  sovereign  will,  and  that  a  lesser  good  is 
not  to  be  undervalued  because  it  is  not  a  higher  one.  The 
passage,  however,  expressing  as  it  does  the  fitness  of  both 
kinds  of  goods  to  be  Divine  gifts,  he  appeals  to  in  his 
'  Retractions '  to  prove  how,  even  in  an  early  work,  and 
before  his  mind  had  expanded  on  the  subject  of  grace,  he 
had  laid  down  the  principles  of  his  subsequent  teaching.1 

The  first  regular  attempt,  however,  at  a  definition  of 
the  characteristic  power  of  Grospel  grace,  occurs  in  the 
treatise  '  De  Gratia  Christi,  in  which  he  calls  it  '  the 
assistance  of  will  and  action — adjutorium  voluntatis  et 
actionis.' 2  It  will  of  course  be  evident  at  first  sight  that 
this  definition  does  not  of  itself  describe  an  irresistible 
grace,  but  would  apply  to  a  simply  assisting  one  as  well. 
But,  considered  in  connection  with  the  context,  and  taken 
in  the  meaning  which  its  opposition  to  another  definition 
of  grace  fastens  upon  it,  it  will  be  found  to  imply  the 
former.  It  was  asserted  by  the  Pelagians  that,  inasmuch 
as  the  power  of  willing  and  acting  in  one  way  or  another 
(possibilitas  utriusque  partis)  was  inseparable  from 
human  nature,  human  nature  had  of  itself  the  power  to 
will  and  act  aright ;  but  that  this  power  needed  to  be 
assisted  by  grace  (ut  possibilitas  semper  gratia  adjuvetur 
auxilio).3  To  this  Augustine  replied,  that  not  only  the 
power  to  will  and  act  was  assisted  by  grace,  but  that  will 
and  action  itself  were  ;  and  therefore  to  the  Pelagian  defi 
nition  of  grace,  as  the  '  assistance  of  power '  (adjutorium 
possibilitatis),  he  opposed  his  own,  '  the  assistance  of  will 
and  action'  (adjutorium  voluntatis  et  actionis).  Now, 
by  assisting  will  and  action  we  should  naturally  and  ordi 
narily  understand  assisting  the  power  to  will  and  act, 
taking  the  words  will  and  action  loosely  to  signify  the 
faculties  ;  for  acts  themselves  are  not  susceptible  of  assist 
ance,  being  already  done.  Nor,  therefore,  should  we  na 
turally  see  any  difference  at  all  of  meaning  in  these  two 
expressions,  assistance  of  power  and  assistance  of  action. 

1  Retraot.  1.  I.e.  9.  tatem  et  actioncm. 

2  I  give  the  Jansenist  turn  to  the  3  De  Grrat.  Christi,  c.  iii. 
phrase  gratia  qua  adjuvat  volun- 


Augitstinian 


CHAP.  YI. 


Bat  if  this  ordinary  meaning  is  disclaimed  for  the  expres 
sion  assistance  of  action,  and,  instead  of  being  identified 
with,  the  latter  is  contrasted  to,  the  assistance  of  the 
power  to  will  and  act,  it  must  follow  that  by  assistance 
of  action  a  grace  of  a  stronger  kind  is  meant  than  that 
which  assists  the  power  to  act  ;  and  what  can  that  grace 
be  but  one  which  causes  action  itself  —  i.e.  irresistible 
grace  ? 

Indeed,  this  absolute  sense  is  fastened  on  the  word 
adjutorium  in  this,  Augustine's,  definition  of  grace,  by 
the  mode  in  which  the  same  word  is  used  in  the  rival  and 
opposing  definition.  For  the  word  carries  to  the  phrase 
adjutorium  voluntatis  et  actionis  the  same  meaning  that 
it  bore  in  the  phrase  adjutorium  possibilitatis  (for  the 
two  sides  differ  not  about  the  meaning  of  assistance,  but 
about  what  is  assisted).  But  in  the  latter  phrase  it  bears 
the  sense  of  causing  as  well  as  of  assisting  ;  for  the  Pe 
lagians  said  this  power  (possibilitas)  was  given  by  Grod 
in  the  first  instance  as  well  as  assisted  when  had.  The 
word  therefore  bears  the  same  sense  in  the  phrase  '  adju 
torium  voluntatis  et  act  ion  is  J  and  implies  the  gift  or 
ca.usation  of  will  and  action,  and  not  only  the  assistance 
of  it. 

But  the  meaning  of  this  definition  of  grace,  which  is 
evident  hitherto  with  some  difficulty,  and  only  by  a  close 
and  exact  process  of  comparison,  is  abundantly  clear  and 
manifest  when  we  come  to  S.  Augustine's  own  explanation 
and  exposition  of  it.  He  says  :  '  Pelagius  in  his  first  book 
on  Freewill  thus  speaks  :  "  We  have,"  he  says,  "  a  power 
of  taking  either  side  —  possibilitatem  utriusque  partis  — 
implanted  in  us  by  God,  as  a  fruitful  and  productive  root, 
to  produce  and  bring  forth  according  to  men's  different 
wills  ;  and  either  shine  with  the  flower  of  virtue,  or  bristle 
with  the  thorns  of  vice,  according  to  the  choice  of  the 
cultivator."  In  which  passage,  not  perceiving  what  he 
says,  he  establishes  one  and  the  same  root  of  good  and  evil 
men,  against  evangelical  truth  and  apostolical  teaching. 
For  our  Lord  says,  that  a  good  tree  cannot  bring  forth 
evil  fruit,  nor  an  evil  tree  good  fruit.  And  the  Apostle 


CHAP.  vr.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  151 

Paul,  when  he  says  that  cupidity  is  the  root  of  all  evil, 
intimates  also  that  love  is  the  root  of  all  good.  If,  there 
fore,  the  two  trees  good  and  evil  are  two  men  good  and 
evil,  what  is  the  good  man  but  the  man  of  a  good  will ; 
that  is,  the  tree  of  a  good  root  ?  And  what  is  the  evil 
man,  bat  the  man  of  an  evil  will ;  that  is,  the  tree  of  an 
evil  root?  And  the  fruits  of  these  two  trees  are  acts, 
words,  thoughts;  which  if  good  proceed  from  a  good  will, 

and  if  evil  from  an  evil  will It  is  not  true,  then, 

as  Pelagius  says,  that  there  is  one  and  the  same  root  of 
good  and  evil  men :  for  there  is  one  root  of  good  men, 
viz.  love ;  and  another  root  of  evil  men,  viz.  cupidity : 
although  it  is  true  that  that  power  is  capable  of  both  roots 
— ilia  possibilitas  utriusque  radicis  est  capax — because 
a  man  is  able  not  only  to  have  love  but  also  to  have 
cupidity.' * 

He  proceeds  to  say  that  love,  which  is  the  root  of  good 
actions,  is  a  free  gift  of  (rod,  and  not  given  according  to 
our  merits. 

Now  this  passage  evidently  contains  a  different  doctrine, 
as  to  the  source  of  our  actions,  from  the  doctrine  of  free 
will.  The  doctrine  of  freewill  is  that  we  do  possess  a 
power  of  taking  both  sides,  and  act  well  or  ill  according 
as  we  use  it ;  that  therefore  good  and  evil  acts  may  both 
arise  out  of  one  root  or  one  and  the  same  moral  condition 
of  the  agent.  But  Augustine  denies  the  residence  in  man 
of  a  power  to  act  either  way,  on  the  logical  or  speculative 
ground  of  the  absurdity  of  supposing,  that  both  virtue  and 
vice  can  come  out  of  the  same  moral  condition  of  the 
agent,  as  this  neutral  state  of  power  would  be  ;  and  main 
tains  that  human  actions  proceed  either  out  of  a  moral 
condition  which  necessarily  produces  right  action,  or  out 
of  a  moral  condition  which  necessarily  produces  wrong. 
He  denies  therefore  the  doctrine  of  freewill.  He  admits, 
indeed,  that  man  is  capable  of  either  moral  condition — 
or,  to  use  his  own  language,  capable  of  either  root ;  but 
this  is  not  the  doctrine  of  freewill,  which  is,  that  the  same 
moral  condition,  or  the  same  root,  is  capable  of  either 
1  De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  xviii. 


Augustinian  CHAP. 


fruit.  The  former  is  only  the  admission  of  the  obvious 
fact,  that  man  has  a  capacity,  in  the  first  instance,  both 
for  good  and  evil ;  an  admission  which  is  quite  consistent 
with  the  subsequent  necessity  of  either  in  him  ;  just  as  a 
material  is  capable,  in  the  first  instance,  of  any  one  out  of 
many  different  forms;  but  when  it  lias  once  received  a 
particular  form,  is  necessarily  of  that  form  which  it  has 
received. 

The  whole  of  the  book,  however,  De  Gratia  Ckristi,  is 
one  comment  on  the  adjutorium  voluntcitis  ei  actionis,  a,s 
involving  the  sense  of  irresistible  grace,  as  the  following 
passage  on  illuminating  grace  will  exemplify:  '  Our  Lord 
saith,  "  Every  man  that  bath  heard  and  hath  learned  of 
the  Father,  cometh  unto  Me.''  Whosoever  therefore  doth 
not  come,  of  him  it  is  not  right  to  say,  "  He  hath  heard 
arid  learned,  indeed,  that  he  should  come,  but  he  does  not 
will  to  do  what  he  has  learned."  That  is  not  rightly  said, 
it'  we  speak  of  that  mode  of  teaching  which  (rod  employs 
through  grace.  For  if,  as  the  truth  saith.  "  Every  man 
that  hath  learned,  cometh,''  if  any  man  hath  not  come, 
neither  hath  he  learned.  It  is  true,  indeed,  a  man  comes 
or  does  not  come,  according  to  the  choice  of  his  will.  But 
this  choice  is  alone  if  he  does  not  come  ;  it  cannot  but  be 
assisted  if  he  does  come  ;  and  so  assisted  as  that  he  not 
only  knows  what  he  should  do,  but  also  does  what  he 
knows.  Wherefore,  when  God  teaches  not  by  the  letter 
of  the  law,  but  by  the  grace  of  the  spirit,  He  so  teaches  as 
that  what  a  man  learns  he  not  only  perceives  by  knowing 
it,  but  also  pursues  by  willing  it,  and  accomplishes  by 
doing  it.  By  that  Divine  mode  of  teaching  will  itself  and 
action  itself,  not  only  the  natural  power  of  willing  and 
acting,  are  assisted.  For,  were  our  poiver  alone  assisted 
by  this  grace,  our  Lord  would  have  said,  "  Every  man 
that  hath  heard  or  hath  learned  of  the  Father  is  able,  to 
come  to  Me."  But  He  has  not  said  this,  but  "  Every  man 
that  hath  heard  and  hath  learned  of  the  Father  cometh 

unto  Me." Every  man  that  hath  learned  of  the 

Father  is  not  only  able  to  come,  but  comes ;  wherein  not 


CHAP.  vr.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  153 

only  the  proficiency  of  the  power,  but  the  affection  of  the 
will,  and  the  effect  of  action  is  included.' l 

The  grace,  then,  to  which  Augustine  gives  the  name 
or  description  of  '  adjutorium  voluntatis  et  actionisj  wo 
find,  on  examining  his  own  account  and  explanation  of  it, 
to  be  endowed  with  the  effect  of  action  ;  to  be  a  grace, 
not  only  given  in  order  that  such  and  such  actions  may  be 
done,  but  also  causing  those  actions  to  be  done  in  fact. 

But  such  a  phrase  as  '  adjutorium  voluntatis  et 
actionis '  is  obviously  a  very  imperfect  and  awkward 
description  of  irresistible  grace ;  being,  in  fact,  not  of 
itself  any  description  of  it  at  all,  but  depending  entirely 
on  the  definition  to  which  it  is  opposed  and  on  the  context 
generally,  for  its  meaning.  Indeed,  hitherto,  Augustine 
appears  rather  feeling  his  way  toward  some  clear  and  exact 
definition  of  the  grace  for  which  he  is  arguing,  than  really 
defining  if.  His  language  as  a  whole  has  one  evident 
meaning ;  but  it  is  only  as  a  whole  that  it  has  :  it  efiects 
its  object  by  large,  varied,  and  diffuse  statement  and  ex 
planation  ;  but  in  aiming  at  point  it  altogether  fails,  and 
cannot  concentrate  itself  in  definition.  As  his  doctrine  of 
grace,  however,  obtains  a  more  familiar  hold  of  his- mind, 
and  perpetual  controversy  multiplies  thought  and  language 
about  it,  and  the  subject  by  being  turned  over  repeatedly 
is  seen  in  every  aspect,  his  ideas  become  more  exact  and 
his  choice  of  terms  greater ;  and  out  of  the  accumulation 
of  statements  he  is  at  last  able  to  fix  on  one  to  serve  as  a, 
complete  definition  of  this  grace. 

In  the  book  ' De  Correptione  et  Gratia' he  draws  a 
clear  distinction  between  two  different  kinds  of  grace, 
which  he  calls  respectively  '  an  assistance  without  which  a 
thing  cannot  be  done,'  and  '  an  assistance  by  which  a  thing 
is  done'  (adjutorium sine  quo  aliquid  nonfit,  and  adju 
torium  quo  aliquid  fit).  He  first  draws  a  strong  dis 
tinction  between  the  wants  of  man  before  and  man  after 
the  fall,  and  then  gives  this  as  the  corresponding  distinction 
in  the  nature  of  the  grace  by  which  these  respective  wants 
are  supplied.  Man  even  beifore  the  fall,  upright  and  per- 
1  De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  xiv. 


T54  Augitstinian  CHAP.  vi. 

feet  being  as  he  was,  and  possessed  of  freewill,  stood  in 
need  of  grace  to  enable  him  to  act  aright ;  nor  could  he 
do  anything  acceptable  to  Grod  by  his  own  natural  strength. 
But  as  an  upright  being  and  possessed  of  freewill  he  only 
stood  in  need  of  assisting  grace,  he  was  strong  enough  to 
have  the  ultimate  choice  of  good  and  evil  thrown  upon 
him,  and  only  wanted  grace  to  advance  and  aid  the  choice 
when  made.  So  great  a  burden  might  be  placed  upon  him, 
because  he  was  able  to  bear  it,  and  was  no  penalty,  but  the 
sign  of  strength  and  perfection.  To  man,  then,  before 
the  fall  'an  assistance  without  which  a  thing  is  not  done' 
was  given  ;  that  is  to  say,  an  assistance  which  he  could  not 
do  without,  but  which  did  not  effect  anything  unless  he 
added  the  exercise  of  his  own  original  choice  to  it, — that 
which  is  commonly  called  assisting  grace.  But  at  the  fall 
this  whole  state  of  things  ceased.  The  fall  deprived  man 
of  freewill,  and  inclined  his  nature  irresistibly  to  evil.  In 
this  state  he  was  too  weak  to  bear  the  ultimate  choice  of 
good  and  evil  being  thrown  upon  him,  and  must  perish  if 
it  was.  The  grace,  therefore,  which  is  given  to  man  after 
the  fall  is  not  the  assistance  '  without  which  a  thing  is  not 
done,'  but  that  '  with  which  a  thing  is  done ; '  that  is  to 
say,  an  assistance,  upon  which  being  given,  the  effect  of  a 
renewed  heart  and  renewed  will  follows  certainly.  A  grace 
is  now  given  him  suited  to  an  entirely  impotent  nature, 
wholly  controlling  choice  and  action,  and  leading  irre 
sistibly  to  good. 

Augustine  explains  at  length  the  difference  between 
these  two  kinds  of  grace,  and"  the  reason  for  it:  'Adam 
was  in  the  midst  of  good  which  be  had  received  from  the 
goodness  of  his  Creator  ;  but  the  saints  in  this  life  are  in 
the  midst  of  evil,  out  of  which  they  cry  aloud  to  Grod, 
"  Deliver  us  from  evil."  He  amidst  that  good  needed  not 
the  death  of  Christ ;  them  from  guilt,  hereditary  and  per 
sonal,  the  blood  of  that  Lamb  absolveth.  He  had  not  need 
of  that  assistance  which  they  implore,  saying,  "  I  see  an 
other  law  in  my  members  warring  against  the  law  of  my 
mind,  and  bringing  me  into  captivity  to  the  law  of  sin 
which  is  in  my  members."  In  them  the  flesh  lusteth  against 


CHAP.  YI.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  155 

the  spirit,  and  the  spirit  against  the  flesh ;  and  in  this 
struggle,  labouring  and  endangered,  they  ask  for  strength 
through  Christ's  grace  to  fight  and  conquer.  He,  tried 
and  harassed  by  no  such  conflict,  enjoyed  in  that  place  of 
bliss  internal  peace.' l 

c  The  first  man,  therefore,  had  an  assistance,  which  he 
could  desert  if  he  willed,  and  in  which  he  would  abide  if 
he  willed ;  not  one  by  which  he  was  made  to  will.  This  is 
the  first  grace  which  was  given  to  the  first  Adam :  but  a 
stronger  than  this  is  given  in  the  second  Adam.  For  the 
first  is  a  grace  of  which  the  effect  is,  that  a  man  may  have 
righteousness  if  he  ivills :  the  second  is  a  more  powerful 
one,  of  which  the  effect  is,  that  he  wills,  and  wills  so 
strongly  and  loves  so  ardently,  that  the  will  of  the  flesh  is 
conquered  by  the  contrary  will  of  the  spirit.  Nor  was  that 
a  small  assistance  by  which  the  power  of  a  concurrent  free 
will  was  acknowledged ;  being  so  great,  as  that  he  could 
not  remain  in  good  without  it,  though  if  he  willed  he  could 
desert  it.  But  this  is  so  much  the  greater,  as  that  it  is 
not  enough  to  say  that  lost  freewill  is  repaired  by  it,  not 
enough  to  say  that  a  man  cannot  attain  to  or  abide  in  good 
without  it,  but  with  it  can  if  he  will :  except  we  add  also, 
that  it  makes  him  to  wills'* 

'  For  we  must  distinguish  between  one  kind  of  assist 
ance  and  another.  There  is  one  assistance,  without  which 
something  is  not  done,  and  another  by  which  something 
is  done.  For  example,  food  is  a  thing  without  which  we 
cannot  live  ;  but  we  have  it  and  die.  And  therefore  food 
is  an  assistance  without  which  it  is  not  effected,  not  an 
assistance  by  which  it  is  effected,  that  we  live.  On  the 
other  hand,  if  happiness  be  given  to  a  man  he  is  forthwith 
happy.  Happiness,  therefore,  is  an  assistance  by  which 
something  is,  not  an  assistance  without  which  something 
is  not,  effected.  The  first  man  received  the  gift  of  being 
able  not  to  sin,  able  not  to  die,  able  not  to  desert  good  : 
that  assistance  of  perseverance  was  given  him  without 
which  he  could  not  be,  not  an  assistance  by  which  he  was 
persevering.  On  the  other  hand,  to  the  saints,  who  by 
1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  n.  29.  2  Ibid.  n.  31. 


156  Augustinian  CHAP. 


grace  are  predestinated  to  the  kingdom  of  God,  not  such 
an  assistance  of  perseverance  as  this  is  given,  but  such  an 
assistance  as  that  perseverance  itself  is  given  —  tale  ut  eis 
perseverantia  ipsa  donetur  •  not  only  a  gift  of  perseve 
rance,  without  which  they  cannot  be,  but  a  gift  by  which 
they  cannot  but  be  persevering  —  non  solum  ut  sine  isto 
dono  perseverantes  esse  non  possint?  verum  etiam  ut  per 
hoc  donurti  non  nisi  perseverantes  sint.1  . 

'  In  truth,  a  greater  freedom,  and  one  fortified  and  con 
firmed  by  the  gift  of  perseverance,  is  necessary  against  so 
many  and  so  great  temptations,  such  as  there  were  not  in 
Paradise  ;  that,  with  all  its  affections,  terrors,  errors,  the 
world  be  conquered.  This  the  martyrdom  of  the  saints 
has  shown.  For  Adam,  yielding  to  no  terror,  but  rather 
using  his  freewill  against  the  command  of  a  terrible  God, 
stood  not  firm  in  so  great  felicity,  and  so  great  facility  of 
avoiding  sin  :  but  they,  against  a  world  not  terrible  only 
but  raging,  stood  firm  in  the  faith  :  though  he  saw  those 
present  advantages  which  he  was  about  to  leave,  and  they 
saw  not  the  future  ones  which  they  were  about  to  gain. 
Whence  this,  but  by  His  gift  from'  whom  they  obtained 
mercy,  that  they  might  be  faithful.2  .... 

'  Perseverance,  then,  was  not  given  to  Adam  as  a  Divine 
gift,  but  the  choice  of  persevering  or  not  was  left  to  him 
self,  because  his  will,  created  as  it  was  without  sin  and 
without  concupiscence,  was  furnished  with  such  strength, 
that  it  was  worthy  of  such  a  choice  being  committed  to 
it;  so  great  goodness  and  facility  of  living  well  was  his. 
But  now,  after  that  great  freedom  has  been  lost  by  sin,  it 
remains  that  human  infirmity  be  assisted  with  greater 
gifts.3  ....  God  not  wishing  His  saints  to  glory  in 
their  own  strength,  but  in  Him,  gives  them  more  than 
that  assistance  which  He  gave  to  the  first  man  ;  for  inas 
much  as  they  will  not  persevere  except  they  both  can  and 
will,  He  gives  them  by  an  act  of  free  grace  the  power  and 
the  will  both.  For  if  their  own  will  were  left  in  such  a 
way  as  that  if  they  willed  they  would  persevere,  without  it 

1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  n.  34.  2  Ibid.  n.  35.  3  Ibid.  n.  36, 


CHAP.  vr.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  157 

being  provided  that  they  should  will,  their  will  must  suc 
cumb  amid  so  many  infirmities,  and  persevere  they  coidd 
not.  Therefore  such  a  succour  is  afforded  to  the  infirmity 
of  their  will  as  that  by  Divine  grace  action  takes  place, 
without  it  being  possible  to  fall  away  or  be  overcome.1 
Thus,  weak  though  it  is,  this  will  fails  not  and  is  not 
conquered.  The  feeble  will  of  man,  through  the  Divine 
strength,  perseveres  in  a  yet  imperfect  goodness,  when  the 
strong  and  sound  will  of  the  first  man  did  not  in  its  more 
perfect.  The  strength  of  freewill  failed,  because,  through 
that  assistance  of  God  without  which  a  man  cannot,  if  he 
wills,  persevere,  was  not  wanting,  such  assistance  as  that 
by  which  God  works  in  a  man  to  will,  was.  God  left  it 
to  the  strong  man  to  do,  if  he  willed  ;  to  the  weak  He  has 
reserved,  as  a  gift  from  Himself,  to  will  unconquerably 
what  is  good  and  unconquerably  persevere  in  it.' 2 

Such  is  the  distinction  between  the  two  kinds  of  grace 
by  which  the  spiritual  wants  of  man  before  the  fall  and 
after  are  respectively  supplied, — the  grace  of  the  paradisal, 
and  the  grace  of  the  gospel  dispensation.  Under  the  former 
dispensation  grace  was  weak,  because  nature  was  strong ; 
under  the  latter,  grace  is  absolute,  because  nature  is  im 
potent.  Human  nature  is  too  corrupt  and  weak  now  to 
have  anything  left  to  itself  to  do ;  and  it  must  be  treated 
as  such,  and  be  taken  in  hand  with  the  understanding 
that  everything  must  be  done  for  it.  It  is  past  all  but  the 
strongest  remedy,  a  self-acting  one.  The  distinction  rests 
upon  the  doctrine  of  the  fall  of  man  and  the  change  it  in 
troduced  into  his  nature.  The  doctrine  of  the  fall  of  man 
asserts  an  essential  change  in  the  powers  of  his  moral  nature 
to  have  followed  from  that  event,  in  consequence  of  which 
he  cannot  will  or  do  anything  aright  now  of  his  own  natural 
strength.  But  if  man  in  natural  state  has  not  the  power 
to  will  aright,  he  has  not,  Augustine  says,  freewill.  Ac 
cordingly  it  is  assumed  in  this  argument  that  this  is  the 
difference  between  man  before,  and  man  after  the  fall ;  that 

1  '  Ut    divina    gratia    indeclina-       though  some  editions  have  '  inse- 
biliter    et  insuperabiliter  ageretur.'       parabiliter.' 
The    acknowledged    MS.    reading,  *  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  n.  38. 


T-3  Augustinian  CHAP.  YI. 

before  he  had  a  will  which  exerted  a  power  of  its  own1,  and 
after  has  not ;  and  Augustine  comes  to  the  question  of  the 
nature  of  Christian  grace,  with  the  understanding  that 
grace  has  now  to  deal  with  a  being  who  has  not  freewill. 
But  what  kind  of  grace,  he  then  naturally  argues^  is  to 
restore  and  reclaim  such  a  being,  to  raise  him  to  spiritual 
life,  and  make  him  persevere  in  it,  but  an  over-mastering 
and  controlling  grace?  Less  power  in  the  grace  would 
suffice  if  there  were  some  in  the  being ;  for  if  there  is  any 
power  in  nature,  the  complement  of  it  only  is  needed  from 
grace;  but  if  there  is  none,  grace  must  supply  the  whole. 
Had  man  freewill,  grace,  to  be  suited  to  his  condition,  must 
recognise  it,  leave  it  to  act,  and  suspend  its  own  effect  upon 
its  action.  But  when  man  has  freewill  no  longer,  to  leave 
the  effect  of  grace  dependent  upon  his  freewill  is  a  mockery. 
If  he  is  to  be  reclaimed  at  all,  he  must  then  be  reclaimed 
by  an  absolute  act  of  power,  and  grace  must  either  do  every 
thing  for  him  or  do  nothing. 

Here  there  is  a  clear  and  express  definition  of  irresis 
tible  or  efficacious  grace, — the  assistance  with  which  a 
thing  is  done — adjutorium  quo  aliquid  fit, — as  distin 
guished  from  assisting  grace — adjutorium  sine  quo  ali 
quid  non  fit ;  or,  as  abbreviated  by  the  Jansenist  divines, 
the  adjutorium  quo,  as  distinguished  from  the  adjutorium 
sine  quo  non.  According  to  this  definition,  if  the  grace 
defined  is  given,  the  effect  takes  place — aliquid  fit;  the 
renewal  and  conversion  of  the  man  follows  in  fact.  By 
this  definition,  then,  the  effect  is  made  the  test,  whether 
the  grace  is  given  or  not ;  and  a  grace,  of  which  the  bestowal 
is  thus  tested,  is  by  the  very  terms  an  irresistible  and  effi 
cacious  one. 

But,  while  preceding  statements  are  at  last  embodied 
in  a  definition,  the  definition  does  no  more  than  embody 
and  give  point  to  them ;  for  a  grace,  of  the  bestowal  of 
which  the  effect  is  the  test,  has  been  described  all  along. 
4  If  every  man  that  hath  learned  cometh  unto  Christ,  if 
any  man  hath  not  come,  neither  hath  he  learned.' 2 — '  If 

1  Potentia    liberi     arbitrii.— De  2  De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  xiv. 

Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xi. 


CHAP.  YJ.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  159 

every  one  that  hath  heard  and  learned  of  the  Father 
cometh,  whoever  hath  not  come  hath  not  heard  or  learned 
of  the  Father.  For  if  he  had  heard  or  learned,  he  would 
have  come.  For  there  is  no  one  that  hath  heard  or  learned, 
and  cometh  not ;  but  every  one,  as  saith  the  truth,  that 
hath  heard  and  learned  of  the  Father  cometh.' l  Here  the 
test  of  grace,  whether  it  is  given  or  not,  is  the  effect.  Tf 
a  man  is  admitted  to  hearing  and  learning,  i.e.  to  illumi 
nating  grace,  the  effect  of  a  new  life  or  corning  to  Christ 
follows :  if  this  effect  does  not  follow,  he  has  not  been  ad 
mitted  to  this  gTace.  We  do  indeed  sometimes  use  the 
words  hearing  and  learning  in  the  sense  of  a  man's  own  act 
of  attending  to  what  is  told  him,  and  profiting  by  what  is 
taught  him ;  and  in  this  sense  the  words  would  express 
here,  not  the  enlightening  grace  of  (rod,  but  a  man's  own 
use  of  that  grace  ;  and  therefore  not  the  giving  of  a  grace, 
but  a  man's  own  use  of  it,  would  be  the  thing  tested  here 
by  the  effect.  But  the  obvious  sense  of  this  passage,  and 
the  whole  nature  of  the  discussion,  to  which  it  belongs, 
exclude  such  a  meaning  of  the  words  hearing  and  learning 
here,  which  mean  the  fact  of  being  told  and  being  taught,  or 
the  act  of  another  telling  or  teaching.  A  certain  teaching 
of  God,  tHen2,  that  is  to  say,  a  grace,  is  the  thing  of  which 
the  bestowal  is  in  these  passages  tested  by  the  effect ;  and  to 
this  purpose  Augustine  criticises  the  common  saying,  that 
'  God's  mercy  to  us  is  in  vain  if  we  do  not  will,'  remarking, 
'  I  do  not  know  how  this  can  be  said,  for  if  God  has  mercy 
we  also  will — si  Deus  miseretur  etiam  volumus :  God  has 
mercy  on  no  man  in  vain — nullius  Deus  frustra  miseretur?* 
This  is  to  adopt  the  test  of  the  effect.  The  saying  '  Agis  si 
agaris — thou  actest  if  thou  art  acted  on 4 '  does  the  same, 
its  force  lying  in  the  contrast  and  inseparableness  at  the 
same  time  of  an  influence  on  the  man  and  an  act  of  him. 
The  saying  '  Grace  gives  merit,  when  it  is  given  itself— 
gratia  dat  rnerita  cum  donatur5^  the  term  merit  meaning 

1  DePrsed.  c.  viii.  n.  12,  13. 

2  Iste   docendi  modus    quo   per  4  Semi.  128.  c.  7. 
gratiatn  docet  Deus.                                     5  Ep.  ad  Vitalem,  217.  n.  5. 

8  De  Div.  QuKst.  ad  Simp.  1.  1. 


Augustinian 


CHAP.  vr. 


in  Augustine's  use  of  it  right  action,  does  the  same.  Again, 
6  Grace  is  given,  that  the  faults  both  of  nature  and  will 
may  be  conquered;  for  that  which  is  impossible  with  man 
is  easy  to  God.  But  those  to  whom  the  grace  of  God  is 
not  given  become  sinners,  unrighteous  men.  Though  these 
too  live  for  the  advantage  of  the  children  of  mercy,  that 
the  sight  of  them  may  subdue  their  pride  ;  reminding  them 
that  what  has  been  given  to  them  is  God's  free  gift,  and 
not  of  their  own  deserving.'1  The  test  of  the  effect  is 
clearly  adopted  here  ;  the  conquest  of  sin  and  continuance 
in  it  being  respectively  attached  to  the  bestowal  of  grace 
and  the  withholding  of  it.2 

A  general  body  of  language  to  the  same  effect  must  be 
noticed,  in  which  a  holy  disposition  and  conduct  is  put  for 
ward  as  a  Divine  gift  and  a  Divine  creation.  It  is  certain 
from  revelation,  that  God  is  the  Giver  of  every  good  thing  ; 
and  this  truth  is  applied  absolutely  by  Augustine  to  the 
subject  of  human  action,  which,  when  good,  is  described 
as  being  a  Divine  gift.  Conversion  is  a  Divine  gift  — 
donurn  Dei  etiam  ipsa  ad  Deum  nostra  conversion  :  so  is 
obedience  —  donum  obedientice  ;  a  good  life  —  bene  vivere 
donum  divinum;  merit  or  deserving  action  —  Dei  dona 
sunt,  et  Dei  gratia  conferuntur  universa  merita  justo- 
rum4  ;  perseverance  —  donum  Dei  perseverantia5  ;  faith 
in  its  beginning  —  4  gratuito  munere  nobis  datur6  ;'  even 
the  very  beginning,  '  when  men  begin  to  have  faith  which 
they  had  not  —  incipiunt  habere  fidem  quam  non  habe- 
bc/nt7  ;'  faith  in  its  increase  —  augmentum,  incrementum, 
supplement-urn  fidei  donum  Dei.8 

1  Op.  Imp.,  Contra  Jul.  1.  iv.  c.  dicatur   gratiam    tanquam  causam, 

129.  et    operationem   voluntatis    bonam 

-  'Nulla      omnino      medicinalis  relut   effectum,  esse,  tit  philosophi 

Christi  gratia  effectu  suo  caret  ;  sed  loquuntur,    convertibiles,    et  a    se 

omnis   efficit  ut  voluntas  velit,   et  mutuo  inseparabiles.'  —  Jansen.  De 

a.liquid  operetur.  .  .  .  Primo  igitur  Gratia  Christi  Salvatoris,  1.  2.  c.  25. 
hoe  probat,  quod  apud  Augustinum  De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.  c.  v. 

gratia  et   opus  bonum  ita  recipro-  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  ii. 

centur,  ut  quemadmodum  ex  gratia  Ibid.  c.  i. 

data   mox   effectum    operis    conse-  Ep.  194.  n.  12. 

cutum  inferre  solet;  ita  vice  versa,  Ibid.  217.  n.  29. 

ex  defoctu  operis  gratiam  non  esse  8  De  Prsed.  c.  ii. 

datam.     Quo  ratiocinandi  modo  in- 


CHAP.  vi.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  1 6 1 

Again,  it  is  certain  from  revelation  that  God  is  the 
Creator  of  every  thing  visible  and  invisible ;  and  this  truth 
is  also  applied  absolutely  by  Augustine  to  the  subject  of 
human  action;  which,  when  good,  is  described  as  being  a 
Divine  creation.  And  if  a  reason  is  asked  for  this  limita 
tion,  inasmuch  as,  according  to  the  argument,  God  would 
be  the  Creator  of  all  action,  good  as  well  as  bad,  the  an 
swer  is  ready,  that  bad  action,  or  sin,  is  not  a  thing ,  but 
only  a  negation.  Sin  is  c  nothing,'  according  to  Augustine. 
The  faculties  of  mind  and  body  which  are  used  in  a  sinful 
action,  are  indeed  things,  and  are  the  creatures  of  God: 
but  the  sin  itself  is  not  a  thing,  and  is  consequently  not  a 
creature.  God  is  indeed  the  Author  of  all  that  is,  of  every 
substance ;  but  sin  is  not  a  substance,  and  is  not.  It  is  a 
declination  from  substance  and  from  being,  and  not  a  part 
of  it ;  true  being  and  true  substance  being  necessarily 
good,  and  '  is  good,'  and  '  is '  being  convertible  proposi 
tions.  It  is  unnecessary  to  enter  at  large  here  into  this 
distinction.  It  is  obvious  that  some  explanation  or  other 
is  wanted  in  order  to  prevent  the  conclusion  that  God  is 
the  Author  of  evil ;  and  it  is  enough  to  say  that  this  diffi 
culty  is  seen  and  is  in  some  way  disposed  of. 

This  idea  of  human  virtue  and  piety,  as  a  Divine  crea 
tion,  is  indeed,  in  itself,  a  scriptural  one ;  a  point  which 
deserves  consideration.  The  attribute  of  God  as  Creator, 
in  the  strict  sense  of  the  word,  is  a  truth  almost  peculiar 
to  the  Bible  ;  for  though  this  truth  may  be  considered  a 
part  of  natural  religion,  it  has  not  practically  been  brought 
out  under  that  dispensation ;  the  more  general  notion 
having  been,  that  God  was  the  Former  of  the  world,  and 
put  it  into  shape,  but  was  not  the  Maker  of  its  substance. 
The  human  mind  appears  to  have  had  great  difficulty  in 
reaching  the  idea  of  positive  causation  of  existence,  making 
substance  out  of  nothing ;  such  a  power  appearing  even  to 
those  who  entertained  a  system  of  religion,  and  admitted 
the  existence  of  a  Deity  and  our  duties  to  Him,  incredible, 
fictitious,  and  monstrous.  A  material  was  accordingly 
provided  for  the  great  Architect,  ready  at  hand  for  Him 
to  work  upon  and  put  into  shape ;  and  matter  was  made 

M 


Augustinian 


CHAP.  YI. 


a  co-eternal  substance  with  the  Deity.  The  timidity  or 
fastidiousness  of  philosophy  thus  weakened  essentially  the 
great  idea  of  God's  omnipotence  ;  but  the  Bible  sustains  it 
in  a  remarkable  way  upon  this  head.  Exemplifying  the 
rule,  that  '  the  foolishness  of  God  is  wiser  than  men,  and 
the  weakness  of  God  is  stronger  than  men,'  Scripture  puts 
forward  prominently,  and  as  a  fundamental  truth,  that 
very  idea  which  appeared  thus  monstrous  and  untenable  to 
the  philosopher,  viz.  that  God  is  the  true  Creator  of  the 
world,  and  made  substance  out  of  nothing. 

This  difference  between  the  Bible  and  ancient  philo 
sophy  is  specially  important  as  regards  one  division  of  the 
creation,  viz.  the  world  invisible.      Philosophy  did  not 
speak  of  the  intelligent  soul  as  being  a  created  substance, 
but  rather  as  being  an  emanation  of  the  Divine  mind  ; 
thus  making  it  part  of  the  Deity  Himself,  and  forestalling 
the  peculiar  subjection  which  it  derives  from  creation.  But 
the  Bible  teaches  that  the  intelligent  soul  is  a  created 
substance,  as  truly  as  matter  is.     The   subjection  which 
belongs  to  the  creature  thus  attaches  to  the   soul  in  the 
system  of  the  Bible  ;  the  susceptibility  to  and  need  of  in 
fluence,  the  capacity  for  being  moulded  and  controlled  by 
that  Being  by  whom  it  was  originally  made,  and   depen 
dence  upon  this  moulding  and  controlling  Power.     The 
Divine  power  in  Scripture  thus  extends  from  the  first  act 
of  creating  the  substance  of  the  soul  to  the  kindred  one  of 
creating  it  morally  ;  of  forming  and  fashioning  the  inner 
man,  inspiring  holy  acts,  imparting  holy  dispositions,  and 
confirming  and  sustaining  them  afterwards.    This  absolute 
dominion  over  men  and  irresistible  power  over  their  hearts 
is  illustrated  by  the  similitude  of  a  potter,  who  makes  what 
he  pleases  of  his  clay  ;  now  forming  it  and  then  breaking 
it,  now  preserving  it  and  then  rejecting  it.1     The  New 
Testament  both  interprets  and  sustains  the  language  of 
the  Old  ;  appealing  to  this  similitude  and  describing  re 
newed  hearts  as  a  Divine  creation.    '  Shall  the  thing  formed 
say  to  Him   that   formed   it,  why  hast   Thou  made  me 
thus  ?  '  2    'If  any  man  be  in  Christ,  he  is  a  new  creature.'  3 

1  Isaiah,  xxix.  16  ;  xlv.  9  ;   Ixiv.  2  Rom.  ix.  20." 

8  ;  Jeremiah,  xviii.  6.  3  2  Cor.  v.  17. 


CHAP.  vi.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  163 

'  In  Christ  Jesus  neither  circumcision  availeth  anything, 
nor  uncircumcision,  but  a  new  creature.' 1  '  We  are  His 
workmanship,  created  in  Christ  Jesus  unto  good  works, 
which  (rod  hath  before  ordained,  that  we  should  walk  in 
them.' 2 

This  language,  however,  receives  in  Scripture  a  limita 
tion  of  meaning  from  the  general  doctrine  of  man's  freewill 
which  Scripture  inculcates.  But  Augustine  uses  this 
language  absolutely,  and  adds  to  its  strength  and  definite- 
ness.  Thus,  '  (rod  makes  men  good  in  order  that  they 
may  do  good  acts — ipse  ergo  illos  bonos  facit  ut  bona 
faciant' 3  God  '  makes  faith— fidem  gentium  facit' 4 
'  He  makes  men  believers — facit  credentes' h  God  '  makes 
men  to  persevere  in  good.' 6  '  God  calls  whom  He  vouch 
safes  to  call,  and  makes  whom  He  will  religious — Deus 
quos  dignatur  vocat,  et  quern  vult  religiosum  facit : '  a 
saying  of  S.  Cyprian's,  often  quoted,  on  which  he  affixes  a 
literal  meaning.  '  Man  never  does  good  things  which  God 
does  not  make  him  do — qua3  non  facit  Deus  ut  faciat 
homo.' 7  '  The  Holy  Spirit  not  only  assists  good  minds, 
but  makes  them  good — non  solum  mentes  bonas  adjuvat, 
verum  etiam  bonas  eas  facit.' 8  '  There  is  a  creation,  not 
that  by  which  we  were  made  men,  but  that  of  which  a  man 
already  created  spoke,  "  create  a  clean  heart  in  me ;  "  and 
that  of  which  speaks  the  Apostle,  "  If  any  man  be  in  Christ, 
he  is  a  new  creature."  We  are  therefore  fashioned  and 
created  in  good  works,  which  we  have  not  ourselves  pre 
pared,  but  God,  that  we  should  walk  in  them.'  9 

Nor  is  this  language  used  by  S.  Augustine  in  a  qualified 
sense,  simply  to  express  vividly  the  power  of  God's  assisting 
grace,  as  if  giving  and  creating  were  meant  by  Him  to  be 
conditional  upon,  and  supplemental  to,  a  certain  exertion 
of  man's  own  freewill,  understood  though  not  expressed  ; 
for  he  distinctly  disclaims  this  qualification,  making  a 
difference  in  this  very  respect  between  the  gift  of  obedience 

1  Gal.  vi.  15.  6  De  Corr.  et  Grat  c.  xii. 

2  Eph.  ii.  10.  7  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  2.  c.  xxi. 
1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xii.                        8  Ibid.  1.  4.  c.  vii. 

4  De  Prsed.  c.  ii.  9  De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.  c.  8. 

*  Ibid.  c.  xvii. 


Augustinian 


CHAP.  vi. 


or  holiness  and  the  ultimate  gift  of  eternal  life.  Eternal 
life  is  the  gift  of  God,  but  it  is  given  according  to  merit  ; 
that  is,  it  is  a  gift  upon  certain  conditions,  viz.  the  con 
ditions  of  obedience  and  holiness  in  the  persons  to  whom 
it  is  awarded.  But  the  conditions  themselves  of  obedience 
and  holiness  are  not  given  according  to  merit,  but  are  gifts 
unconditional  and  gratuitous.  The  gift  of  eternal  life  is  a 
reward,  and  not  a  gift  only  ;  but  that  for  which  it  is  a  reward 
is  not  itself  a  reward,  or  given  upon  condition  of  endeavours 
and  exercise  of  will  by  the  man  himself,  but  is  a  free  gift 

—  dona  sua  coronat  Deus,  non  merita  tua}  —  God  crowns 
His  gifts  and  not  thy  merits.     '  Eternal  life  is  the  recom 
pense  of  preceding  merits  ;  but  those  merits  of  which  it  is 
the  recompence  are  not  prepared  through  our  own  suffi 
ciency,  but  are  made  in  us  by  grace  ;  it  is  given  to  merits, 
but  the  merits  to  which  it  is  given  are  themselves  given 

—  data  sunt  et  ipsa  merita  quibus  daturS  2     God  at  the 
last  judgment  has  respect  to  His  own  gifts  in  those  who 
appear  before  Him,  not  distributing  eternal  life  to  this 
person  or  that,  according  to  His  own  sovereign  will  and 
pleasure  only,  but  according  to  a  rule  ;  that  is  to  say,  ac 
cording  as  persons  show  the  possession  of  certain  previous 
gifts  of  His  own  to  them  ;  but  those  gifts  themselves  are 
not  to  be  divested  of  their  proper  character  of  gifts  because 
a  reward  is  based  upon  them,  —  :the  second  gift  is  indeed 
upon  the  basis  of  the  first,  but  the  first  gift  is  upon  no 
basis  at  all  but  the  Divine  will  and  pleasure.     Here,  then, 
is  a  contrast  which  establishes  the  sense  of  the  term  gift 
as  used  of  the  qualifications  for  eternal  life,  as  the  more 
simple  and  natural  one  of  a  gift  absolute,  for  so  used  it  is 
opposed  to  the  gift  conditional. 

Thus  he  handles  the  text  '  Turn  unto  Me,  and  I  will 
turn  unto  you3  ;'  a  text  of  which  the  natural  meaning  is, 
that  if  a  man  does  his  part  according  to  the  power  of  free 
agency  which  he  possesses,  God  will  do  His  in  the  way  of 
pardon  and  reward.  '  They,  the  Pelagians,  gather  from 
this  text,  that  the  grace  wherewith  God  turns  to  us  is  given 
as  a  reward  for  our  own  turning  of  ourselves  to  God  ;  not 

1  See  Note,  p.  8.  2  Ep.  134.  n.  19.  3  Zech.  i.  3. 


CHAP.  vi.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  165 

considering  that  unless  this  very  conversion  to  God  were 
the  gift  of  God,  it  would  not  have  been  said,  "  Turn  us, 
Thou  God  of  Hosts,"1  and  '*  wilt  Thou  not  turn  again  and 
quicken  us,"  and  "  Turn  us  then,  0  God  our  Saviour,"2 
and  the  like.  What  else  is  coming  to  Christ  but  turning 
to  Him  by  faith  ?  and  yet  He  saith,  "  No  man  can  come 
unto  Me  except  it  were  given  him  of  my  Father."  '3  All 
that  this  passage  asserts  is,  that  obedience  is  a  gift  of  God 
as  well  as  salvation.  But  obedience  is  next  made  a  gift 
of  God  in  distinction  to  salvation.  '  When  the  Pelagians 
say,  that  that  grace  which  is  given  at  the  end — i.e.  eternal 
life,  is  awarded  according  to  preceding  merits, — I  reply, 
true,  if  they  understand  these  merits  themselves  to  be  gifts 
of  God.' 4  'But  how  could  the  just  Judge  award  the  crown, 
if  the  merciful  Father  had  not  given  the  grace  ?  How 
could  there  be  the  crown  of  righteousness,  if  the  righteous 
ness  by  grace  had  not  preceded  ?  How  could  this  final 
reward  be  given  to  merit,  if  the  merit  itself  had  not  been 
given  as  a  free  gift?'5  Here  the  qualified  sense  of  gift,  viz.  as 
a  gift  according  to  merit  or  upon  the  fulfilment  of  certain 
conditions,  is  allowed  of  the  ul'timate  gift  of  eternal  life, 
only  on  the  understanding  that  it  is  denied  of  the  prepara 
tory  gift  of  the  righteousness  which  qualifies  for  it.  The 
crown  of  righteousness  is  a  reward,  but  the  righteousness 
itself  is  not  a  reward ;  i.e.  anything  given  in  consideration 
of  preceding  endeavours  of  man's  own  will.  And  the  gift 
of  obedience  is  described  as  a  gift  residing  in  the  indi 
vidual  previous  to  action  of  his  own  ;  for  Augustine  lays 
it  down  as  the  object  of  the  institution  of  preaching,  that 
those  who  have  this  gift  may  be  instructed  as  to  the  appli 
cation  of  it — c  ui  qui  haberent  donum  obedientice.,  quibus 
jussis  obediendum  esset  audirent?* 

1  Ps.  Ixxx.  7.  gratia  est:  et  ipsa  enim  gratis  datur, 

2  Ps.  Ixxxv.  4.  6.  quia  gratis  data  est  ilia  cui  datur. 

3  John,  vi.  65 ;  De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Sed    ilia    cui    datur    tantummodo 
Arb.  c.  v.  gratia  est:  lisec  autem  quae  illi  datur, 

4  Ibid.  c.  vi.  quoniam  praemium  ejus  est,  gratia 

5  Again  :  '  Itaque,   charissimi,  si  est  pro  gratia,  tanquam  merces  pro 
vita  bona   nostra    nihil    aliud   est  justitia.' — C.  viii. 

quam  Dei  gratia,  sine  dubio  et  vita  6  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  xix. 

seterna  quse  bonee  vitae  redditur,  Dei 


Augustinian  CHAP. 


There  is  another  evidence  of  the  sense  in  which  Augus 
tine  uses  the  term  gift,  as  applied  to  a  holy  life  and  conduct, 
in  an  argument  in  constant  use  with  him,  drawn  from  the 
fact  of  prayer.  We  pray,  he  says,  not  only  for  external 
good  things,  but  for  spiritual  dispositions  and  habits  ;  for 
virtue,  holiness,  obedience,  both  for  ourselves  and  others. 
But  a  request  implies  that  we  suppose  the  thing  asked  for 
to  be  in  the  gift  of  him  from  whom  we  ask  it,  and  that  he 
is  able  to  bestow  it  or  not,  according  to  his  will  and  plea 
sure,  otherwise  there  is  no  reason  to  account  for  our  asking. 
If  we  ask  God  for  holiness  then,  and  obedience,  it  follows 
that  we  suppose  holiness  and  obedience  to  be  properly  in 
His  gift.1  '  If  God  so  prepared  and  worked  a  good  will  in 
a  man  as  only  to  apply  His  law  and  teaching  to  his  freewill, 
and  did  not  by  a  deep  and  occult  vocation  so  act  upon  his 
mind,  that  he  complied  with  that  law  and  teaching,  beyond 
a  doubt  it  would  be  enough  to  expound  and  preach  to  that 
man,  and  there  would  be  no  necessity  to  pray  that  God 
would  convert  him  or  give  him  perseverance  when  con 
verted.  If  these  things  are  to  be  prayed  for  then,  and  you 
cannot  deny  that  they  are  to  be,  what  remains,  but  that 
you  confess  that  these  things  are  gifts  ?  for  you  must  ask 
God  for  what  He  gives.'2 

It  is  evident  that  this  argument  defines  an  absolute 
gift  of  holiness  and  obedience,  for  the  force  of  the  argu 
ment  lies  in  pushing  the  act  of  prayer  to  its  extreme  con 
sequences  ;  and  this  is  the  logical  consequence  of  prayer, 
as  a  request  for  holiness  and  obedience  from  God,  It  is 
undoubtedly  of  the  very  nature  of  prayer  to  suppose  the 
subject  of  its  request  to  be  simply  in  God's  gift  ;  so  far  as 
a  thing  is  not  in  God's  power  to  give,  so  far  it  is  not  the 

1  '  Frequentationibus  autem  ora-  a   Deo   non  ostendit   dandum   esse 

tionum    simpliciter   apparebat   Dei  nisi  a  Deo,  cum  poscendum  ostendit 

gratia  quid  valeret  :  non  enim  pos-  a  Deo.     Qui  enim  non  infertur  in 

cerentur  de  Deo  quae  prsecipit  fieri,  tentationem  non  discedit  a  Deo.' 
nisi  ab  illo  donarentur,  ut  fierent.'—  '  Ecclesia  orat  ut  increduli  credant. 

De  Prsed.  Sanct.  c.  xiv.  Deus  ergo  convertit  ad  Mem.    Orat 

'Si   alia  documenta  non  essent,  ut  credentes  perseverent  :  Deus  ergo 

dominica  oratio   nobis   ad   causam  dat  perseverantiam  in  finem.'  —  De 

gratise  quam  defendimus  sola  sum-  Dono  Pers.  c.  vii. 
ceret.   Siquidem  ut  non  discedamus          2  Ep.  217.  ad  Vitalem,  n.  5. 


CHAP.  vr.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  167 

subject  of  prayer.  If  the  act  of  prayer,  then,  in  the  case 
of  asking  for  goodness  from  God,  is  to  be  pushed  to  its 
logical  consequences,  it  must  follow  from  it  that  goodness 
is  God's  absolute  gift.  Upon  the  doctrine  of  freewill, 
when  the  act  of  prayer  extends  to  such  requests  as  these, 
it  is  understood  in  such  a  sense  as  to  forestall  this  conse 
quence  of  it ;  but  Augustine  embraces  himself,  and  presses 
upon  others  the  extreme  consequences  of  prayer. 

He  adds  that  which  is  necessary  to  make  this  view  a 
consistent  one,  that  prayer  itself  also  is  the  gift  of  God ; 
for  it  would  be  evidently  inconsistent  to  make  other 
spiritual  habits  the  gift  of  God,  if  that  habit  which  was 
a  means  to  those  was  not  a  gift  of  God  too.1 

Another  convincing  proof  of  the  sense  in  which  Augus 
tine  uses  the  terms  gift  and  creation,  as  applied  to  a  holy 
life,  is  his  express  connection  of  this  gift  with  predesti 
nation,  and  the  referring  of  it  to  God's  secret  and  myste 
rious  will.  Had  he  simply  meant  by  these  terms  that  God 
crowned  man's  own  endeavours,  and  gave  the  increase  if 
man  make  a  beginning,  such  a  doctrine  would  have  ap 
proved  itself  naturally  to  our  sense  of  justice,  and  would 
not  have  needed  any  reference  to  mystery  for  its  defence. 
But  Augustine  bases  this  gift  of  holiness  and  obedience 
upon  mystery.  '  Deaf  as  thou  art,  hear  the  apostle  thank 
ing  God  that  they  have  obeyed  the  doctrine  from  the 
heart;  not  that  they  have  heard  the  doctrine  preached, 
but  that  they  have  obeyed  it.  For  all  have  not  obeyed 
the  Gospel,  but  those  to  whom  it  is  given  to  obey ;  just  as 
to  know  the  mysteries  of  the  kingdom  of  God  is  given  to 
some,  but  to  others  is  not  given.' 2 

Again ;  '  As  begun  and  as  perfected,  faith  is  alike  the 
gift  of  God ;  and  that  this  gift  is  given  to  some  and  not 
to  others  cannot  be  doubted  without  opposing  the  plainest 
declarations  of  Scripture.  Nor  should  this  disturb  any 
believer  who  knows  that  from  one  man  all  went  into  justest 
condemnation  ;  so  that,  were  none  rescued,  God  could  not 
be  blamed,  the  real  deserts  even  of  those  who  are  rescued 
being  the  same  with  those  of  the  damned.  It  belongs  to 
1  De  Dono  Pers.  e.  xxiii. ;  Ep.  194.  c.  iv.  2  Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  230. 


[68  Augustinian  CHAP.  vi. 

God's  unsearchable  judgments,  and  His  ways  past  finding 
out,  why  He  rescues  one  man  and  not  another.  0  man, 
who  art  thou  that  repliest  against  God  ?  Bow  to  the  re 
buke,  rather  than  speak  as  if  thou  knowest  that  which 
God  who  wills  nothing  unjust  has  yet  willed  to  be  secret.' l 
Again  :  '  God  converts  to  faith.  God  gives  perseverance. 
God  foreknew  that  He  would  do  this.  This  is  the  predes 
tination  of  the  saints  whom  He  elected  in  Christ  before 
the  foundation  of  the  world,  that  they  should  be  holy  and 
without  blame  before  Him  in  love,  having  predestinated  us 
unto  the  adoption  of  children  by  Christ  Jesus  to  Himself, 
according  to  the  good  pleasure  of  His  will ;  in  whom  we 
have  obtained  an  inheritance,  being  predestinated  accord 
ing  to  the  purpose  of  Him  who  worketh  all  things  after 

the  counsel  of  His  own  will But  why  is  not  the 

grace  of  God  given  according  to  merit  ?     I  reply,  because 
God  is  merciful.     And  why  is  He  not  merciful  to  all  ?     I 
reply,  because  He  is  just.     His  justice  on  some  shows  how 
freely  His  grace  is  given  to  others.     Let  us  not  then  be 
ungrateful,  because  according  to  the  pleasure  of  His  will, 
and  the  praise  of  His  glory,   the  merciful  God  frees   so 
many  from  a  just  perdition  when  He  would  not  be  unjust 
if  He  freed  nobody.     From  one  man  have  all  gone,  not 
into  any  unjust  condemnation,  but  a  just  one.     Whoever 
is  freed  then,  let  him  love  the  grace  ;  whoever  is  not  freed, 
let  him  acknowledge  the  justice.     God's  goodness  is  seen 
in   remitting,   His    equity  in  exacting,  His  injustice  in 
nothing.' 2     Again  on  the  text  '  It  is  He  that  made  us  and 
not   we   ourselves.'     '  He   therefore    makes   sheep — facit 
oves.  .....  Why  dost  thou  cast  freewill  in  my  teeth, 

which  will  not  free  for  righteousness  except  thou  be  a 
sheep  ?  He  it  is  who  makes  men  sheep,  who  frees  human 
wills  for  works  of  piety.  But  why,  when  there  is  with 
Him  no  respect  of  persons,  He  makes  some  men  sheep, 
and  not  others,  is,  according  to  the  Apostle,  a  question 
more  curious  than  becoming.  0  man !  who  art  thou  that 
repliest  against  God  ?  Shall  the  thing  formed  say  to  Him 
that  formed  it,  Why  hast  Thou  made  me  thus  ?  This  ques- 
1  De  Praed.  c.  viii.  2  De  Dono  perg  c  yii  ^^ 


-   ...  t    '• .  'l 

4rtne  of\ 
CHAP.  vi.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  169 

tion  belongs  to  that  abyss  from  which  the  Apostle  shrank 
with  dread,  exclaiming,  u  0  the  depth  of  the  riches  both 

of  the  wisdom  and  knowledge  of  God ! " ^Thy 

this  man  receives,  and  that  man  does  not  receive,  when 
neither  deserves  to  receive, measuring  thy  strength,  examine 
not ;  enough  that  we  know  that  there  is  no  iniquity  with 
Grod The  vessels  of  mercy  understand  how  en 
tirely  in  their  own  case  mercy  is  gratuitous,  when  those, 
with  whom  they  share  one  common  lump  of  perdition, 
receive  their  just  punishment.' 1 

In  these  passages  the  gift  of  obedience,  the  gift  of 
faith,  the  gift  of  perseverance.,  the  creation  of  the  holy 
and  good  man,  or  sheep  as  he  is  called,  are  treated  as  the 
effects  of  the  Divine  predestination,  and  are  accounted  for 
on  a  mysterious  principle.  It  is,  therefore,  a  proper  gift 
and  creation  of  which  he  is  speaking,  and  not  a  mere 
crowning  of  human  endeavours  after  holiness,  for  which 
such  an  account  would  be  both  superfluous  and  unsuitable. 
For  there  could  be  no  occasion  to  go  to  mystery  for  the 
explanation  of  a  proceeding  of  which  so  very  natural  and 
intelligible  account  could  be  given,  as  of  (rod's  giving  the 
advancing  and  perfecting  grace  in  proportion  as  man 
exerts  his  own  faculties  and  will. 

To  sum  up  briefly,  then,  the  evidences,  as  far  as  we 
have  gone,  of  the  Augustinian  doctrine  of  grace ;  there  is 
first  an  express  definition  of  the  nature  of  grace,  under 
the  Gospel  dispensation,  arrived  at  after  much  thought 
and  effort,  and  much  handling  and  discussing  of  the  sub 
ject;  a  definition  according  to  which  the  grace  of  the 
Gospel  is  an  assistance  productive  of  that  effect  upon 
man's  life  and  conduct  for  which  it  is  given — adjutorium 
cum  quo  fit.  And  this  definition  is  sustained  by  a  general 
body  of  language  describing  goodness  and  holiness  as  a 
Divine  gift  and  a  Divine  creation,  not  in  a  secondary  and 
qualified  but  a  natural  and  proper  sense  of  the  terms,  as 
shown  by  the  caution  annexed,,  that  this  gift  is  not  given 
according  to  merit— i.  e.  according  to  any  conditions  which 
man  himself  previously  fulfils ;  by  the  argument  from 
1  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  Pel.  1.  4.  c.  6. 


I '         \ 

170  Augustmian  CHAP.  vi. 

prayer,  and  by  the  express  referring  of  this  gift  and  this 
creation  to  the  mystery  of  the  Divine  predestination.  But 
a  grace  which  is  always  productive  of  the  effect  upon,  life 
and  conduct  for  which  it  is  given — a  grace  which  gives  and 
creates  goodness  absolutely  is  an  effective  or  irresistible 
grace. 

This  rationale  is,  then,  confirmed  by  examples  from 
Scripture.  4 1  wish,'  says  S.  Augustine  to  the  Pelagian 
who  accounted  for  change  of  heart  from  bad  to  good  by 
self-discipline  and  self-mortification  on  the  part  of  man, 
which  Divine  grace  seconded,  '  I  wish  you  would  tell  me 
whether  that  Assyrian  king  whose  bed  the  holy  Esther 
abhorred,  when  he  sat  on  the  throne  of  his  kingdom,  clad 
in  glorious  apparel,  and  covered  with  gold  and  precious 
stones,  and  was  very  dreadful,  and  looked  at  her  with  a 
countenance  inflamed  with  indignation,  so  that  the  queen 
fainted  with  fear — whether  that  king  had  already  "  run 
to  the  Lord,  and  desired  to  be  led  by  Him,  and  suspended 
his  will  upon  His  will,  and  by  cleaving  constantly  to  Him 
had  been  made  one  spirit  with  Him "  (he  quotes  the 
Pelagian  statement),  "by  the  power  of  his  freewill ;  whether 
he  had  given  himself  up  to  God,  and  mortified  all  his  will, 
and  put  his  heart  in  God's  hand."  It  would  be  madness 
to  think  so ;  and  yet  God  converted  him,  and  changed  his 
fury  to  mildness.  But  who  does  not  see  that  it  is  a  much 
greater  thing  to  convert  an  opposite  indignation  into  mild 
ness,  than  to  convert  a  heart  pre-occupied  with  neither 
the  one  nor  the  other  affection,  but  midway  between  the 
two?  Eead  then,  and  understand,  behold  and  confess, 
that  not  by  law  and  teaching  from  without,  but  by  a  mar 
vellous  and  ineffable  power  within,  God  produces  in  the 
hearts  of  men,  not  only  true  revelations,  but  also  good 
wills.'1 

The  particular  conclusion  from  this  passage  is,  that,  in 
the  change  from  a  bad  to  a  good  state  of  mind  in  the  case 
of  Ahasuerus,  Divine  grace  could  not  have  waited  for  any 
motive  of  the  will ;  his  will  having  been  up  to  the  very 
instant  of  that  effect  taking  place  violently  opposed  to  such 
1  De  Gratia  Christi,  n.  25. 


**rine  of , 

CHAP.  TI.  Doctrine^ of  Grace.  171 

a  change ;  the  general  one  is,  that  if  grace  alone  turned 
the  raging  and  hostile  will  of  that  monarch,  it  can  certainly 
do  the  same  with  other  wills  in  a  more  neutral  state. 

The  conversion  of  S.  Paul  is  appealed  to  as  another  in 
stance  of  the  operation  of  such  a  grace.  '  I  pardon  you,' 
he  says  to  his  Pelagian  opponent  Julian,  '  that  on  a  very 
deep  matter  you  are  mistaken,  as  a  man  may  be — ignos- 
cendum  est  quia  in  re  in  multum  abditd,  ut  homofalleris. 
God  forbid  that  the  intention  of  the  omnipotent  and  all- 
foreseeing  One  should  be  frustrated  by  man.  Little  do 
they  think  about,  or  small  power  have  they  of  thinking 
out  a  weighty  matter,  who  suppose  that  God  omnipotent 
wills  anything,  and  through  weak  man's  resistance  cannot 

do  it If,  as  you  say,  men  are  not  recalled  by  any 

necessity  from  their  own  evil  intentions,  how  was  the 
Apostle  Paul,  yet  Saul,  breathing  slaughter  and  thirsting 
for  blood,  recalled  from  his  most  wicked  intention  by  the 
stroke  of  blindness  and  the  terrible  voice  from  heaven, 
and  from  the  prostrate  persecutor,  raised  to  be  a  preacher 
and  the  most  laborious  one  of  all  ?  Acknowledge  the  work 
of  grace.  But  God  calls  one  man  in  this  way,  and  another 
in  that,  whomever  He  prefers  to  call,  and  the  wind  bloweth 
where  it  listeth.'  *  That  is,  acknowledge  the  work  of  God, 
not  only  in  this  particular  instance,  but  in  all  cases  of  con 
version  from  a  wicked  to  a  holy  life.  The  operation  of  a 
grace  absolutely  determining  the  will  of  man  comes,  as  it 
were,  visibly  before  us,  as  in  the  case  of  S.  Paul.  But 
God  calls  one  man  in  this  way,  and  another  in  that — 
alium  sic,  alium  autem  sic.  Because  He  does  not  call 
all  those  whom  He  calls  in  the  same  striking  and  visible 
manner  in  which  He  called  S.  Paul,  do  not  infer  any  differ 
ence  of  principle  upon  which  His  calls  are  conducted  ;  for 
the  laws  of  God's  spiritual  dealings  are  uniform,  and  He 
makes  one  saint  in  the  same  way  fundamentally  in  which 
He  makes  another.  In  the  gentlest  and  most  gradual 
conversions,  then,  acknowledge  the  operation  of  the  same 
power  which  operates  in  that  of  S.  Paul. 

S.  Peter  is  brought  forward  as  another  instance  of  the 
1  Op.  Imp.  1.  i.  c.  93. 


172  Augffi&inian  CHAP.  vr. 

operation  of  such  a  grace  upon  the  will ;  or  of  grace  alone 
and  by  itself  determining  it  or  causing  the  particular  will 
of  the  man  to  be  the  will  which  it  is.  '  What  will  you 
oppose  to  the  text  "  I  have  prayed  for  thee,  Peter,  that  thy 
faith  fail  not  ?  "  *  Will  you  dare  to  say  that  even  the  prayer 
of  Christ  could  not  have  procured  indefectible  faith  for 
Peter,  had  Peter  wished  that  it  should  fail ;  that  is,  had 
been  unwilling  to  persevere  ?  As  if  Peter  could  possibly 
will  anything  else  but  what  Christ  had  prayed  that  he 
should  will !  True,  indeed,  Peter's  faith  would  have  failed, 
if  Peter's  will  to  be  faithful  had  failed.  But  the  will  is 
prepared  by  the  Lord,  and  therefore  Christ's  prayer  for  him 
could  not  be  ineffectual.'2  This  passage  is  clear.  Peter's 
faith  would  have  failed  if  Peter's  will  had  ;  but  Peter's  will 
would  not  be  anything  else  but  what  God  had  determined 
it  to  be,  and  (rod  had  determined  that  it  should  be  faith 
ful. 

It  remains  now  to  inquire  whether  anything  is  said  of 
the  nature  or  quality  of  this  grace  in  itself— itself,  I  mean, 
as  distinguished  from  its  effects,  by  which  alone  it  has 
hitherto  been  described.  And  to  this  question  the  answer 
is,  that  Augustine  identifies  this  grace  with  the  disposi 
tion  of  love. 

Christian  love  is  a  general  affection  toward  God  and 
man,  productive  of  all  the  virtues  and  the  whole  of  obe 
dience.  '  Love  is  the  fulfilling  of  the  law.' 3  « If  we  love 
one  another,  God  dwelleth  in  us  and  His  love  is  perfected 
in  us.'4  But  this  love  is,  according  to  the  doctrine  of  free 
will,  a  result,  an  ultimate  habit,  gained  by  the  endeavours 
of  the  man  himself  assisted  by  Divine  grace.  But  in  the 
system  of  Augustine  it  appears  as  a  primary  disposition 
imparted  to  the  soul  by  an  act  of  free  grace  ;  not  the  reward 
and  effect  of,  but  a  gift  preceding  and  producing,  a  good 
course  of  life.  That  which  is  the  infallible  root  of  general 
obedience  is  implanted  in  the  man  at  the  outset.  The 
grace  of  love  is  infused  into  his  heart.  In  consequence  of 
the  indwelling  of  this  gift,  he  cannot  but  take  pleasure  in 

1  Luke,  xxii.  32.  »  Rom.  xiii.  10. 

De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  viii.  4  1  John,  iv.  12. 


CHAP.  vi.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  1 73 

God's  law,  obeying  it  not  out  of  servile  fear  and  in  the 
spirit  of  bondage,  but  in  the  freedom  of  a  renewed  and 
converted  inclination.  The  gift  of  love  makes  that  sweet 
to  him  which  before  was  difficult,  nay  impossible.  Not 
that  those  who  have  the  gift  enjoy  the  full  virtue  of  it  all 
at  once,  and  immediately  find  a  holy  life  pleasant  to  them  ; 
but  in  proportion  as  the  virtue  of  it  comes  out,  they  do  find 
this  result ;  and  the  gift  ultimately,  by  means  of  this  power 
inherent  in  it  of  accommodating  the  human  will  to  the 
Divine,  inclination  to  law,  does  produce  a  saving  and 
acceptable  obedience. 

Thus,  in  a  passage  which  has  been  quoted,  Augustine 
lays  down  one  root  of  good  men,  viz.  love,  and  another  root 
of  evil  men,  viz.  cupidity ;  adding,  '  The  virtue  of  love  is 
from  God,  and  not  from  ourselves,  for  Scripture  says,  "  Love 
is  God,  and  every  one  that  loveth  is  born  of  God  and 
knoweth  God  ;"  and  "  Whosoever  is  born  of  God  doth  not 
commit  sin,"  and  that  because  "  he  cannot  sin."  Nor  have 
our  preceding  merits  caused  this  love  to  be  given  us  ;  for 
what  good  merits  were  we  able  to  have  at  the  time  when 
we  did  not  love  God  ?  That  we  might  have  that  love,  we 
were  loved  before  we  had  it ;  as  the  Apostle  John  saith, 
"  Not  that  we  loved  God,  but  that  He  loved  us,"  and  "  We 
love  Him  because  He  first  loved  us."  For  what  good  could 
we  do  if  we  did  not  love,  or,  how  can  we  not  do  good  if 
we  do  love  1 1 ' 

Here  love,  which  is  described  as  a  necessary  root  of  good 
action,  or  involving  a  good  life  in  the  individual  who  has 
it,  is  also  made  an  original  and  primary  gift  of  God  to 
man.  '  Who  hath  it  in  his  power  to  secure,  either  that 
something  delighting  should  come  across  him,  or  that  it 
should  delight  him  when  it  does  ?  When  a  holy  life  delights 
us  then,  this  delight  is  inspired  and  given  by  the  grace  of 
God,  and  not  gained  by  our  own  will,  or  endeavours,  or 
works ;  this  very  will,  these  very  endeavours,  and  these  very 
works,  being  His  gifts.' 2 

Again :  '  When  we  ask  assistance  from  Him  to  work 

righteousness,  what  ask  we  but  that  He  should  open  what 

1  De  Grat.  Christi,  c.  xxi.^  seq.     2  De  Div.  Qwest,  ad  Simpl.  1.  1.  n.  21. 


AugMstinian  CHAP. 


was  hid,  and  make  sweet  what  was  unpleasant  ?  ..... 
There  precedes  in  the  will  of  man  a  certain  appetite  for  its 
own  power,  so  that  it  "becomes  disobedient  through  pride. 
Were  this  appetite  away,  nothing  would  be  difficult,  and 
man,  as  he  now  seeks  his  own  will,  would  quite  as  easily 
not  have  sought  it.  But  there  has  come  upon  him,  as  a 
just  punishment,  such  a  corruption  of  nature,  that  it  is  now 
disagreeable  to  him  to  obey  the  Divine  law.  And  unless 
this  corruption  is  overcome  by  assisting  grace,  no  one  is 
converted  to  obedience  ;  unless  healed  by  the  operation  of 
grace,  no  one  enjoys  the  peace  of  obedience.  But  by  whose 
grace  is  he  conquered  and  healed,  but  by  His  to  whom  it 
is  said,  "  Turn  us,  then,  0  God  our  Saviour,  and  let  Thine 
anger  cease  from  us  "?  which,  if  He  does  to  any,  He  does 
to  them  in  mercy  ;  while  to  those  to  whom  He  does  it  not 
He  does  it  not  in  judgment.  And  who  shall  say  to  Him 
(whose  mercy  and  judgment  all  pious  minds  celebrate), 
what  doest  Thou  ?  Wherefore  even  His  saints  and  faithful 
servants  He  heals  slowly  in  some  faults,  so  that  good  de 
lights  them  less  than  is  sufficient  for  fulfilling  the  whole 
law  ;  in  order  that,  tried  by  the  perfect  rule  of  His  truth,  no 
flesh  may  be  justified  in  His  sight.  Nor  is  such  imperfec 
tion  intended  for  our  condemnation,  but  only  our  humbling, 
and  to  remind  us  of  our  dependenca  on  this  same  grace  ; 
lest,  attaining  facility  in  everything,  we  think  that  our  own 
which  is  His  .....  Let  us  be  wise,  and  understand  that 
Grod  sometimes  does  not  give  even  to  his  saints,  with  respect 
to  any  work,  either  a  certain  knowledge,  or  a  victorious 
delight  —  victricem  delectationem  —  in  order  that  they  may 
know  that  not  from  themselves  but  from  Him  is  that  light 
by  which  their  darkness  is  illuminated,  and  that  sweetness 
by  which  their  land  yields  her  fruit.'  1 

Love,  which  he  calls  delight  and  sweetness,  is  described 
in  this  passage  as  a  '  conquering  '  or  irresistible  grace  ;  upon 
the  bestowal  of  which  certain  effects  of  life  and  conduct 
follow  naturally,  though  not  always  in  a  full  measure,  but 
only  in  proportion  to  the  amount  imparted  of  the  gift 
1  De  Pecc.  Mer.  et  Eem.  1.  2.  c.  xix. 


CHAP.  vi.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  175 

itself.  And  being  such  a  gift,  it  is  described  as  a  free  gift ; 
not  half  given  by  God,  half  attained  by  man,  or  given  in 
proportion  to  our  natural  striving  after  it.  For  why  it  is 
given  to  one  more  than  another  he  treats  as  a  mystery,  or 
a  question  belonging  to  the  secret  counsels  of  God ;  whereas, 
on  the  latter  supposition  there  would  have  been  no  diffi 
culty  to  account  for.  Moreover,  the  gift  is  described 
throughout  as  preceding  and  producing  action,  and  not 
following  it. 

Again  :  (  The  appetite  for  good  is  from  God  ;  the  most 
high,  unchangeable  good  ;  which  appetite  is  love,  of  which 
John  saith,  "  Love  is  of  God."  Not  that  its  beginning  is 
of  us,  and  its  perfecting  of  God,  but  that  the  whole  of  love 
is  from  God.  For  God  avert  such  madness  as  to  make 
ourselves  prior  in  His  gifts  and  Him  posterior ;  seeing,  it 
is  said,  "  Thou  preventest  him  with  the  blessings  of  sweet 
ness."  For  what  can  be  meant  here  but  that  appetite  for 
good  of  which  we  speak.  For  good  begins  to  be  desired 
as  soon  as  it  begins  to  be  sweet.  But  when  good  is  done 
through  fear  of  punishment,  and  not  through  love,  good  is 
not  done  well.  It  is  done  in  the  act,  but  not  in  the  heart, 
when  a  man  would  not  do  it  if  he  could  refuse  with  im 
punity.  The  blessing  of  sweetness  is  therefore  given  as 
a  grace  whereby  that  which  is  commanded  delights  us,  and 
is  desired  and  loved.'1  Again  :  '  If  grace  co-operates  with 
a  previously  existing  good  will,  and  does  not  prevent  and 
produce  that  will,  how  is  it  truly  said  that  "  God  worketh 
in  us  to  will,"  and  that  the  will  is  prepared  by  the  Lord, 
and  that  "  Love  is  of  God,"  love  which  alone  wills  beatific 
good  ? ' 2  Again  :  '  When  the  love  of  God  is  shed  abroad 
in  our  hearts,  not  that  love  is  meant  with  which  He  loves 
us,  but  that  love  by  which  He  makes  us  lovers  of  Him ; 
as  the  righteousness  of  God  is  that  by  which  He  makes 
us  righteous  of  free  grace,  and  the  salvation  of  God  that 
by  which  He  saves  us,  and  the  faith  of  Jesus  Christ  that 
by  which  He  makes  us  believers.'3  Again  :  God  alone  gives 

1  Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  2.  c.  riii.  8  De  Spirit,  et  Lit.  c.  xxxii. 

2  Op.  Imp.  1.  I.e.  95. 


1  76  Augustinian  CHAP.  TI. 

love;  for  "Love  is  of  God."  This  you  will  not  reckon 
among  your  assistances  of  grace,  lest  you  should  concede  the 
truth,  that  the  very  act  of  obedience  is  of  that  grace.'1 
Again  :  '  Thou  mentionest  many  things  by  which  God 
assists  us,  viz.  by  commanding,  blessing,  sanctifying,  coerc 
ing,  exciting,  illuminating  ;  and  then  mentionest  not,  by 
giving  love  ;  whereas  John  saith  "  Love  is  of  God,"  and 
adds,  "  Behold  what  manner  of  love  the  Father  hath 
bestowed  on  us,  that  we  should  be  called  the  sons  of  God."  '2 
Again  :  '  If  among  the  kinds  of  grace  you  refer  to  you 
would  place  love,  which  the  Scriptures  most  plainly  declare 
to  be  not  from  ourselves  but  from  God,  and  to  be  a  gift  of 
God  to  His  own  sons,  that  love  without  which  no  one  lives 
piously,  and  with  which  a  man  cannot  but  live  piously  ; 
without  which  no  one  has  a  good  will,  and  with  which  a 
man  cannot  but  have  a  good  will,  you  would  then  define  a 
true  freewill,  and  not  inflate  a  false  one.'  3 

Throughout  these  passages  the  gift  of  love  is  described 
as  a  disposition  of  mind  necessarily  productive  of  holy 
action,  and  at  the  same  time  it  is  described  as  the-  gift  of 
God  without  any  qualification  of  the  simple  and  natural 
sense  of  that  term.  And,  lastly,  this  gift  is  identified  ex 
pressly  with  efficacious  or  irresistible  grace,  as  that  grace 
was  formally  defined  above  ;  it  being  described  as  a  gift 
'with  which  a  man  cannot  but  live  piously  —  cum  qua 
nemo  nisi  pie  vivitj  which  is  a  repetition  of  the  language 
above  —  £  adjutorium  cum  quo  aliquid  jit  ;  donum  per 
quod  non  nisi  perseverantes  suntS  4 

Having  thus  shown,  what  it  was  the  object  of  this 
chapter  to  show,  that  Augustine  held  the  doctrine  of 
efficacious  or  irresistible  grace,  I  shall  conclude  with  two 
observations. 

It  is  evident,  then,  in  the  first  place,  that  this  doc 
trine  is  no  more  than  a  supplemental  one  to  the  doctrine 
of  predestination  described  in  the  preceding  chapter.  If 
there  be  a  Divine  decree  predestinating  from  all  eternity 
antecedently  to  any  acts  of  their  own  certain  individuals 


Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  e.  114.  "  Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  e.  122. 

Ibid.  1.  3.  c.  106.  *  Pp.  163.  165. 


CHAP.  vr.  Doctrine  of  Grace.  177 

of  the  human  race  to  everlasting  life,  there  must  be  an 
instrument  for  putting  this  decree  into  effect.  The  grace 
of  which  the  discussion  has  occupied  this  chapter  is  this 
instrument.  It  imparts  absolutely  to  the  predestinated 
persons  those  acts  and  dispositions  which  are  the  condi 
tions  of  this  final  reward.  The  Divine  decree,  in  ensuring 
this  end  to  certain  persons,  ensures  them  the  means  to  it ; 
but  piety  and  virtue  are  the  necessary  means  for  attaining 
this  end ;  this  decree  therefore  necessarily  involves,  as  its 
supplement,  a  grace  which  ensures  the  possession  of  piety 
and  virtue. 

In  the  next  place  I  will  guard  the  reader  against  a 
mistake  which  is  not  unlikely  to  arise  with  respect  to 
this  doctrine.  For  it  may  be  asked  whether  the  assertion 
of  an  efficacious  or  irresistible  grace  involves  more  than 
maintaining  that  there  is  such  a  grace  which  Gfod  chooses 
to  give  to  certain  select  and  privileged  persons,  without 
maintaining  that  it  is  the  only  grace  by  which  holiness 
and  salvation  can  be  obtained  ?  Whether  it  cannot  be 
held  that  God  gives  an  irresistible  grace  to  some,  and  also 
gives  a  sufficient  grace  to  the  rest?  Whether  the  higher 
gift  to  a  select  number,  which  ensures  holiness,  is  not  com 
patible  with  the  lower  one  to  the  rest,  which  gives  them 
the  power  to  attain  it  ? 

But,  indeed,  if  we  consider  the  matter,  such  a  question 
as  this  will  be  seen  to  proceed  from  a  confusion  of  thought 
on  this  subject.  For  upon  what  ground  does  any  one  hold 
that  there  is  this  irresistible  grace,  except  on  the  ground 
that  human  nature  needs  it,  and  cannot  do  without  it  ? 
but  if  human  nature  cannot  do  without  it,  nothing  short 
of  it  is  sufficient.  This  is  the  ground  on  which  Augustine 
raises  the  doctrine,  and  on  which  all  who  do  maintain  it 
do  maintain  it.  Indeed,  on  what  other  ground  can  it  be 
seriously  maintained  ?  For  whether  or  not  it  might 
attach  as  a  superfluity  to  a  nature  able  to  do  without  it,  its 
existence  could  not  be  other  than  a  mere  conjecture  in 
such  a  case.  For  asserting  its  existence  there  must  be  an 
adequate  reason  given ;  and  what  adequate  reason  can 
be  pretended,  except  that  which  is  given,  viz.  that  it  is 

N 


1 78          Augustinian  Doctrine  of  Grace.     CHAP.  TI. 

necessary  ?  Were  this  grace,  then,  maintained  as  a  super 
fluity,  there  might  consistently  be  maintained  together 
with  it  another  grace  short  of  it,  and  only  sufficient ;  but 
it  is  maintained  as  remedial  to  a  fatal  disease,  as  supple 
mental  to  an  absolute  want.  The  first  dispensation  did 
not  provide  it  because  man  could  do  without  it ;  the  second 
provides  it  because  he  cannot.  If  an  irresistible  grace  then 
is  maintained  at  all,  it  cannot  be  maintained  as  a  grace 
along  with  the  other  or  merely  assisting  one,  but  must  be 
maintained  as  the  grace  of  the  Grospel  dispensation, — the 
grace  by  the  operation  of  which  all  the  goodness  and  holi 
ness  there  is  in  men  arises.  To  endeavour,  then,  to  com 
bine  it  in  one  system  with  the  other  would  be  to  treat  it 
apart  from  and  in  opposition  to  the  very  ground  on  which 
we  suppose  it  to  exist.  The  doctrine  of  an  absolute  pre 
destination  cannot  combine  with  any  other  account  of  the 
origin  of  human  goodness ;  it  must  either  be  denied  alto 
gether,  or  applied  to  the  whole.  An  antecedent  moral 
inability  in  the  whole  human  mass  is  the  very  occasion 
of  that  decree,  which  is  made  for  no  other  reason  than 
to  provide  a  remedy  for  it.  It  follows,  that  while  those 
who  are  affected  by  its  remedial  provisions  are  endowed 
with  that  certainty  of  attaining  to  holiness  which  they 
impart ;  those  whom  the  decree  does  not  affect  remain  in 
their  original  inability ;  and  therefore,  that,  besides  those 
who  have  an  irresistible  grace,  there  are  none  who  have 
sufficient.1 

1  Bishop  Overall  appears  to  have  firmity,   and  that  the  salvation  of 

fallen  into  the  error  of  endeavour-  men  might  be   more   certain,  that 

ing  to  combine  irresistible  grace  to  He  thought  good  to  add  a  special 

some  with   sufficient  grace  to  all:  grace,   more   efficacious  and  abun- 

'  These  two  things  agree  very  well  dant,  to  be  communicated  to  whom 

together,   that   God,   in     the    first  He  pleased,  by  which  they  might 

place,  proposed  salvation  in  Christ  not  only   be   able   to   believe   and 

to  all,  if  they  believed,  and  common  obey,  if  so  inclined,  but  also  actu- 

and  sufficient  grace  in   the  means  ally  be  inclined,  believe,  obey,  and 

divinely  ordained,  if  men  were  not  persevere.'— Overall   on   the  Quin- 

wanting  to  the  Word  of  God  and  quarticular  Controversy,  quoted  by 

to  the  Holy  Spirit ;  then,  secondly,  Mr.  Goode,  '  Effects  of  Infant  Bap- 

that    He    might   help   human    in-  tism,'  p.  129. 


vii.     Doctrine  of  Final  Perseverance.  T  79 

CHAPTER   VII. 

AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE   OF    FINAL    PERSEVERANCE. 

IN  the  preceding  chapter  it  has  been  shown  that  the  grace 
of  the  Grospel  dispensation  is,  according  to  the  doctrine 
of  S.  Augustine,  an  efficacious  and  irresistible  one.  But 
the  question  still  remains  in  what  measure  this  grace  is 
given,  how  much  of  it  is  required  for  accomplishing  the 
object  for  which  it  is  designed,  viz.  the  individual's  salva 
tion.  Must  it  be  given  to  him  in  perfect  fulness,  i.e. 
every  moment  and  act  of  his  life  without  exception  ?  Or 
is  a  less  measure  of  it  sufficient  ?  and  if  so,  what  is  that 
measure  ? 

The  answer  to  this  question  is,  that  the  measure  of 
this  grace  which  is  required  for  salvation  is  the  same  as 
the  measure,  whatever  it  may  be,  of  goodness  and  holiness 
which  is  required.  As  this  grace  is  the  efficacious  cause 
of  goodne-s,  exactly  as  much  is  wanted  of  the  cause  as  is 
wanted  of  the  effect.  And  to  ask  this  question  is  exactly 
the  same  as  to  ask,  how  much  goodness  is  required  for 
salvation. 

If  the  question,  then,  be  asked,  how  much  goodness  is 
required  for  salvation  ?  while  it  is  plain  that  no  definite 
amount  can  be  fixed  upon  in  answer,  a  certain  indefinite 
one  can  be.  Disobedience  and  sin  for  an  indefinite  portion 
of  life  are  not  incompatible  with  it ;  but  a  man  must  on 
the  whole  have  manifested  a  good  character.  And  if  it  be 
asked,  further,  what  constitutes  such  a  manifestation,  and 
what  is  the  test  of  goodness  on  the  whole  ?  the  answer  is, 
the  end  of  life — that  which  the  man  is  at  the  close  of  the 
state  of  probation  in  which  he  has  been  placed. 

The  amount  of  efficacious  grace,  then,  which  is  required 
in  order  to  salvation,  is  that  which  produces  this  final  state 
of  goodness,  i.e.  the  grace  of  final  perseverance.  And 
therefore  I  shall  endeavour,  in  this  chapter,  to  explain  the 
doctrine  of  final  perseverance  ;  first  as  a  test,  and  secondly 
as  a  grace. 

H  2 


iSo  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  TH. 

I.  It  will  be  evident,  on  slight  consideration,  that  the 
doctrine  of  final  perseverance,  so  far  as  that  doctrine  is 
simply  the  adoption  of  a  particular  test  of  an  acceptable 
and  saving  obedience,  is  no  predestinarian  one,  but  simply 
one  of  morals  and  religion.  Some  test  is  wanted  of  what 
constitutes  in  the  individual  goodness  on  the  whole ;  and 
this  doctrine  supplies  a  test,  viz.  the  character  of  the  indi 
vidual  at  the  end  of  life.  The  doctrine  does  not,  indeed, 
in  form  adopt  the  end  of  life,  but  continuance  up  to  the 
end,  as  this  test.  But  it  is  evident  that  in  continuance 
up  to  the  end,  nothing  is  ruled  as  to  when  that  course  of 
goodness  which  is  to  be  thus  continued  is  to  begin.  The 
literal  and  absolute  end  of  life  is,  indeed,  excluded  as  such 
a  point  of  commencement ;  for  there  cannot  be  continuance 
up  to  the  end  if  the  end  takes  place  immediately.  But, 
interpreting  the  end  of  life  liberally,  it  is  left  open  in  this 
test  whether  such  goodness  commences  at  the  beginning 
of  life,  or  at  the  middle,  or  at  the  end.  And  though  an 
obedience  which  continues  up  to  the  end  is  doubtless  more 
valuable  if  it  commenced  at  the  beginning  of  life  than  if 
it  commenced  at  the  middle,  and  if  it  commenced  at  the 
middle  of  life  than  if  it  commenced  at  the  end,  still  so 
long  as  it  begins  in  sufficient  time  to  be  a  fair  and  sub 
stantial  continuance  in  goodness,  it  fulfils  the  requirements 
of  the  test. 

The  principle,  then,  on  which  such  a  test  goes,  and  on 
which  it  recommends  itself  to  adoption,  is  the  obvious  and 
natural  one,  embodied  in  the  old  maxim  rs\os  opa,  look 
to  the  end,  the  principle,  that  the  end  determines  the 
character  of  the  whole  to  which  it  belongs.  This  rule 
applied  to  the  case  of  man's  moral  character  leads  us  to 
decide,  that  if  he  ends  virtuously  he  is  on  the  whole  a  good 
man ;  or,  on  the  other  hand,  that  if  he  ends  immorally,  he 
is  on  the  whole  a  bad  man.  Solon,  indeed,  applied  this 
rule  to  determine  the  question,  not  of  a  man's  moral  cha 
racter,  but  of  his  happiness  in  life ;  and  here  it  does  not 
literally  apply.  For  it  cannot  be  said  to  be  true,  that  the 
happiness  of  a  man's  life  does  depend  on  the  happiness  or 
misery  of  its  end  ;  because  happiness  being  a  thing  of 


CHAP.  VIT.  of  Final  Perseverance.  181 

present  sensation,  if  the  sensation  has  been,  there  has  been 
happiness.  The  fact  has  already  taken  place,  then,  before 
the  end  comes ;  and  whatever  that  end  may  be,  it  cannot 
cause  what  has  taken  place  not  to  have.  A  man  therefore 
who  has  had  uninterrupted  happiness  up  to  the  end  of  his 
life,  but  has  then  fallen  into  misfortune,  has  undoubtedly 
had  more  happiness  than  one  who  has  been  miserable  up 
to  the  end  of  his  life,  but  has  then  become  prosperous. 
Solon's  assertion  applies  properly  not  to  the  state  and  con 
dition  of  the  persons  themselves,  but  to  their  position  in 
the  minds  of  the  survivors ;  for  we  naturally  think  of  a 
man  afterwards  as  we  last  knew  him.  However  pros 
perous,  therefore,  a  man  has  been  up  to  the  end,  if  at  the 
end  he  falls,  then,  inasmuch  as  that  is  the  last  we  saw  of 
him,  and  he  disappeared  from  that  time,  and  was  no  more 
seen,  we  carry  his  image  in  our  minds  connected  with  this 
fall  and  adversity.  If  the  melancholy  association  is  the 
last  in  order,  it  cannot  be  corrected,  but  is  fixed  and  un 
changing  ;  and  the  same  is  true  of  the  contrary  one.  It 
was  a  natural  law  of  association,  then,  which  the  philoso 
pher  observed,  of  which  this  was  the  result.  When  he 
said  that  a  man's  happiness  in  life  was  decided  by  its  end, 
that  end  was  imagined  as  still  going  on  ;  it  was  not  the 
real  termination  of  life  but  an  ideal  continuation  of  it,  and, 
as  being  ideal,  unending,  for  we  can  always  summon  the 
idea.  The  two  young  men  who,  after  their  work  of  piety 
in  drawing  their  sacred  mother  to  the  temple,  fell  asleep 
in  the  holy  precincts  and  died,  enjoy  an  eternal  rest  in 
OUT  minds.  Their  sweet  and  blissful  repose  still  in  idea 
goes  on.  And  so  the  other  who  died  in  victory  fighting 
for  his  country  enjoys  an  eternal  transport  in  our  minds. 
The  image  of  repose,  and  the  image  of  glory  stay  for  ever. 
Such  an  ideal  end  of  life,  were  it  real,  would  indeed  be  the 
test  of  a  man's  happiness  in  life ;  because  the  eternal  con 
tinuation  of  a  life  is  the  greater  portion  of  it,  and  the 
happiness  of  the  greater  portion  is  the  happiness  of  the  life 
as  a  whole.  But  the  literal  end  of  life  is  no  such  test. 

But  a  test  which  is  deceptive  as  applied  to  the  estima 
tion  of  a  man's  happiness  is  true  as  applied  to  the  estimation 


Augustinian  Doctrine 


CHAP.  YTI. 


of  his  goodness.  For  there  is  a  peculiarity  in  the  composi 
tion  or  organisation  of  moral  character  which  makes  it 
apply.  It  might  appear,  indeed,  at  first  sight,  that  as 
happiness  is  present  sensation,  so  goodness  is  present  action; 
and  therefore,  that  if  any  portion,  large  or  small,  of  a  man's 
life  has  been  conducted  well,  there  has  been  so  much  good 
ness  which  cannot  be  reversed,  whatever  state  of  sin  may 
succeed  it.  But  this  is  not  a  true  statement  of  the  case. 
Present  action  is  certainly  present  goodness,  goodness  for 
the  time  ;  but  goodness  for  the  time  is  not  goodness  abso 
lutely.  Moral  character  is  subject  to  this  law,  that  change 
in  it  affects  not  only  the  individual's  present  life,  but  his 
relation  to  his  former,  disconnecting  him  with  it.  The 
change  from  bad  to  good  conduct  disconnects  him  with  the 
bad  ;  the  change  from  good  to  bad  disconnects  him  with 
the  good,  (rood  after  bad  and  bad  after  good,  exert  each 
a  rejective  power  over  the  past,  to  his  loss  and  to  his  relief 
respectively.  For  a  man  cannot  turn  from  bad  to  good 
conduct  sincerely  and  heartily  without  such  a  sense  of 
aversion,  grief,  and  disgust  for  his  former  life  as  amounts 
to  a  putting  it  away  from  him,  a  severance  of  it  from  his 
proper  self;  and  in  like  manner  he  cannot  turn  from  a  good 
behaviour  to  a  bad  entirely,  without  such  an  indifference  to 
or  contempt  of  virtue  as  amounts  to  a  disowning  and  rejec 
tion  even  of  his  own.  Thus  he  loses  his  property  in  one 
set  of  actions  as  he  turns  to  another.  The  actions,  indeed, 
that  he  has  performed  remain  for  ever  his  in  the  sense  that 
he  is  the  person  that  performed  them  ;  but  they  cease  to  be 
his  in  the  sense  that  they  affect  his  character.  From  this 
law,  then,  it  follows  necessarily,  that  the  character  of  the 
man  is  the  character  which  he  has  at  last,  inasmuch  as  he  has 
no  other  but  that,  being  dispossessed,  by  the  fact  of  having 
it,  of  any  different  one  which  he  may  have  had  before.  The 
question  of  property  in  acts  is  the  whole  of  the  question  of 
the  goodness  or  badness  of  the  man  ;  for  how  can  his  pre 
vious  actions,  good  or  bad,  affect  Mm,  except  they  belong 
to  him  ?  This  law,  then,  determines  the  question  of  pro 
perty  in  acts,  and  it  determines  it  by  the  fact  of  what  come 
latest.  The  man's  previous  virtue  or  vice  for  the  time  are 


CHAP.  vii.  of  Final  Perseverance.  183 

not  his  absolutely,  unless  they  are  his  then ;  they  wait  in 
suspense  for  that  final  appropriation.  The  question  of 
property  in  the  case  of  happiness  or  pleasure  is  perfectly 
simple ;  for  happiness  being  only  a  present  sensation,  can 
only  belong  to  the  present  possessor,  but  goodness  is  more 
than  present  action,  and  therefore  wants  another  proprietor 
besides  the  present  agent. 

Indeed,  one  view  which  is  held  of  change  of  character 
in  persons  rejects  the  idea  of  real  or  substantial  change  in 
them  altogether,  and,  whatever  they  become  at  last,  regards 
them  as  having  been  really  of  that  character  from  the  first. 
According  to  this  view,  change  is  interpretative  simply  and 
not  actual,  as  regards  the  man's  substantial  temper  ;  it  only 
shows  that  his  former  character  was  superficial,  and  that 
he  had  at  the  time  another  underneath  it,  which  was  really 
his  character,  in  spite  of  appearances.  Thus  the  end  in 
terprets  the  whole  of  life  from  its  beginning,  and  we  wait 
in  suspense  till  it  arrives,  in  order  to  ascertain  not  what  a 
man  will  on  the  whole  turn  out,  but  what  he  has  been  all 
along.  This  view  rests  for  its  ground  upon  a  certain  pre 
sumed  necessity  for  a  unity  of  the  moral  being.  It  appears 
to  be  dividing  one  person  into  two,  to  say  that  he  was  once 
a  good  man,  and  is  now  a  bad  man ;  and  the  division  of 
his  moral  unity  is  considered  to  be  as  much  a  contradiction 
as  the  division  of  his  personal.  The  popular  aspect,  then, 
of  change  of  character,  as  an  actual  change  or  division  of 
it,  is  used  as  a  convenience,  just  as  a  metaphor  might  be 
used  which  expressed  a  truth  with  practical  correctness  and 
perhaps  even  greater  vigour  than  a  literal  statement  would, 
while  another  and  a  deeper  view  is  really  taken  of  such 
change. 

And  this  explanation  of  change  of  character  is  un 
doubtedly  a  natural  and  true  one,  properly  understood,  and 
with  a  certain  limitation.  A  man  who  changes  his  cha 
racter  cannot  indeed  be  said  to  have  had  his  later  character 
before  in  the  same  sense  in  which  he  has  it  after,  nor  can 
such  a  meaning  be  intended ;  at  the  same  time  he  must 
have  had  this  character  before  in  the  sense  of  having  its 
seed  or  root, — that  out  of  which  it  grew.  For  it  is  contrary 


184  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vn. 

to  experience  and  common  sense  to  suppose  that  a  change 
of  character  can  take  place  all  at  once,  without  previous 
preparation  and  growth ;  nor  can  there  be  any  doubt  that 
men  have  even  the  sure  root  of  alteration  in  them  a  longer 
or  shorter  time  before  they  actually  alter — i.e.  the  altered 
character  itself,  before  it  comes  out  and  manifests  itself ; 
the  substance  having  existed  in  the  shape  of  secret  habits 
of  mind,  of  which  the  formation  may  date  very  far  back. 
But  if  the  idea  of  moral  unity  is  pushed  further  back  than 
this,  and  the  root  which  contains  the  man's  subsequent 
character  be  made  coeval  with  the  man,  this  cannot  be 
done  without  entrenching  upon  freewill ;  and  therefore  such 
a  supposition,  though  it  may  be  entertained  as  an  approach 
to  some  truth  on  this  subject  with  which  we  are  unac 
quainted,  cannot  be  entertained  absolutely.  I  will  add, 
that  we  find  in  Scripture  both  aspects  of  change  of  charac 
ter;  the  popular  aspect  of  it  as  real  change,  and  the  esoteric 
as  only  external.  The  prophet  Ezekiel  uses  the  former 
when  he  says,  '  If  the  wicked  will  turn  from  all  his  sins 
that  he  hath  committed  and  keep  all  My  statutes,  and  do 
that  which  is  lawful  and  right,  he  shall  surely  live,  he  shall 
not  die.  All  his  transgressions  that  he  hath  committed 
they  shall  not  be  mentioned  unto  him  ;  in  his  righteousness 
that  he  hath  done  he  shall  live.  But  when  a  righteous 
man  turneth  away  from  his  righteousness,  and  committeth 
iniquity,  and  doeth  according  to  all  the  abominations  that 
the  wicked  doeth,  shall  he  live?  All  his  righteousness 
that  he  hath  done  shall  not  be  mentioned :  in  his  trespass 
that  he  hath  trespassed,  and  in  his  sin  that  he  hath  sinned, 
in  them  shall  he  die.' l  St.  John  uses  the  latter  when  he 
says,  '  They  went  out  from  us,  but  they  were  not  of  us ; 
for  if  they  had  been  of  us  they  would  no  doubt  have  con 
tinued  with  us ;  but  they  went  out  that  they  might  be  made 
manifest  that  they  were  not  all  of  us.' 2 

The  doctrine  of  final  perseverance,  then,  so  far  as  it  is 
the  adoption  of  a  test  of  saving  goodness,  is  only  the  doc 
trine  of  trial  and  probation  explained.     The  doctrine  of 
trial  and  probation  is,  that  we  are  placed  in  this  world  in 
1  Ezekiel,  xviii.  21,  22,  24.  z  l  john}  H   19> 


CHAP.  vir.  of  Final  Perseverance.  185 

order  to  prove  by  our  actions  whether  we  are  worthy  of 
reward  or  punishment  in  an  eternal  world  to  come.  The 
doctrine  of  final  perseverance  is,  that  those  actions  are  not 
estimated  simply  with  regard  to  quantity,  but  also  with 
regard  to  order ;  that  what  constitutes  a  good  or  bad  life 
is  not  the  mere  aggregate  of  them,  in  which  case  it  would 
not  signify  whether  they  came  at  the  beginning  or  end  of 
life,  for  so  long  as  there  was  enough  of  them  to  satisfy  the 
Judge,  it  would  be  indifferent  how  the  number  was  made 
up ;  but  their  succession,  whether  prior  or  posterior  in  life  : 
in  other  words,  not  the  acts  themselves,  but  their  relation 
to  the  man,  whether  they  are  appropriated  by  him  or  not ; 
for  this  is  what  their  order  of  prior  or  posterior  tests. 

And  as  the  doctrine  of  final  perseverance  as  a  test  is 
only  the  doctrine  of  trial  and  probation  explained  ;  so  the 
objections  to  it  on  the  ground  of  justice  are  only  of  the  kind 
which  attaches  to  the  general  doctrine  of  trial  and  proba 
tion.  The  doctrine  indeed  that  the  whole  period  of  trial 
must  be  judged  by  its  termination,  prominently  suggests 
the  question,  in  the  case  of  a  bad  termination  of  it,  Why 
is  this  period  terminated  now  ?  As  the  end  makes  all  the 
difference,  why  could  not  that  end  have  been  postponed  ? 
Why  could  not  the  period  have  been  extended  to  sufficient 
length  to  give  room  for  another,  and  so,  by  a  small  addi 
tion  to  its  duration,  the  whole  of  its  effects  have  been  re 
moved  ?  But  it  is  evident  that  this  objection  applies  to 
the  end  of  all  trial  whatever,  and  upon  whatever  rule  pro 
ceeding,  whether  that  of  the  order  of  actions  or  of  the 
aggregate  simply.  In  either  case  a  longer  period  might, 
as  far  as  we  see,  have  produced  a  different  issue  from  that 
of  a  shorter  one.  The  whole  doctrine  of  trial  and  proba 
tion  is  indeed  incomprehensible  to  us  ;  for,  whereas  proba 
tion  must  in  the  nature  of  the  case  be  limited,  we  cannot 
understand  how  a  limitation  of  it  can  be  so  arranged  as  to 
be  perfectly  just  and  equitable  ;  how  it  is  that  a  person  at 
a  particular  time  is  completely  tried  and  proved  :  notwith 
standing  which  difficulty,  the  doctrine  of  trial  and  proba 
tion  is  a  doctrine  both  of  revelation  and  natural  religion. 

The  test  of  final  perseverance  does  indeed,  in  some  of 


1 86  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vn. 

its  applications,  appear  to  be  open,  not  only  to  this  objec 
tion,  which  applies  to  all  limited  probation,  that  we  do  not 
see  its  justice,  but  to  a  positive  charge  of  injustice.  For 
in  the  case  of  a  person  who  has  lived  uprightly  and  reli 
giously  up  to  the  end  of  life,  but  has  then  yielded  to  some 
temptation  and  fallen  into  sin,  it  does  appear  unjust  that 
the  end  should  undo  the  whole  of  the  life  previous,  and 
deprive  him  of  any  advantage  from  it ;  and  the  rule  of  final 
perseverance  seems  at  first  to  impose  such  a  result.  But 
this  will  be  found,  upon  consideration,  not  to  be  the  case. 
The  rule  of  final  perseverance  is  the  rule,  that  a  man  must 
be  judged  according  to  his  final  character  ;  but  what  in  a 
particular  case  is  the  final  character  it  does  not  and  can- 
nob  determine.  Some  rules  indeed  are  of  such  a  kind  that 
they  appear  when  laid  down  to  decide  their  own  applica 
tion  ;  and  the  rule  which  identifies  a  man's  character,  good 
or  bad,  with  his  final  one,  will  appear,  unless  we  are  on  our 
guard,  to  decide  the  particular  fact  of  his  final  character, 
its  goodness  or  badness  ;  the  change  which  is  presented  to 
observation  in  the  particular  case  appearing  to  be,  without 
any  further  reflection,  the  change  which  is  supposed  in  the 
rule.  But  it  is  evident  that  we  should  be  deceived  here 
by  an  apparent  connection  between  two  things  which  are 
really  separate.  No  rule  can  possibly  decide  its  own  appli 
cation  ;  it  supposes  the  case  to  which  it  applies  and  does 
not  discover  or  select  it.  On  the  question,  whether  such 
and  such  a  case  is  one  of  change  of  character,  we  must  take 
the  best  evidence  which  our  own  experience  and  observa 
tion  can  apply,  as  we  would  on  any  other  question  of  fact. 
In  the  case  of  a  man  who  at  the  end  of  a  life  of  steady 
virtue  falls  into  sin,  we  ought  certainly  to  be  slow  to  believe 
th;it  such  sin  is  a  real  change  of  character.  His  previous 
good  life,  though  of  no  avail  as  a  counterbalance,  supposing 
a  real  change  from  it,  is  yet  legitimate  evidence  on  the 
question  whether  there  is  such  change  ;  and  evidence,  as 
far  as  it  goes,  against  it.  For  there  is  a  difficulty  in  sup 
posing  that  one  who  had  evinced  such  steadiness  and  con 
stancy  should*fall  away  really,  however  he  might  appear 
to  do  so;  and  both  reason  and  charity  direct  us  to  a 


CHAP.  VIT.  of  Final  Perseverance.  187 

favourable  supposition,  except  something  very  peculiar  in 
the  case  prevents  it.1 

The  rule  of  final  perseverance,  then,  as  a  test,  is  not 
itself  unjust ;  but  whether  it  is  unjust  or  not  in  its  applica 
tion  depends  upon  our  discrimination  and  charity  in  apply 
ing  it.  This  rule  is  not  intended  to  over-ride  our  natural 
ideas  of  justice,  as  if  because  we  admitted  it,  we  allowed  a 
self-applying  power  to  it,  to  which  those  ideas  must  suc 
cumb ;  but  those  ideas  of  justice  must  be  our  guide  in 
applying  the  rule.  We  must  apply  it  then  in  the  particular 
case,  according  to  the  evidence  ;  and  remember  that,  after 
all,  we  cannot  apply  it  with  certainty,  because  God  only 
knows  the  final  state  of  man's  heart.  There  cannot  in  that 
case  be  any  unjust  application  of  the  rule^  because  its 
application  will  be  suspended  altogether.  Indeed  this  rule, 
when  we  go  to  the  bottom  of  it,  issues  after  all  in  being 
substantially  no  more  than  the  rule  that  a  man  must  be 
judged  according  to  his  character ;  for  by  a  man's  character 
we  meanhis  final  character,  and  no  character  previous  to  it. 
The  rule  then  is  certain,  because  it  is  no  more  than  the  rule, 
that  the  good  are  rewarded  and  the  bad  punished ;  but  it 
cannot  be  applied  to  the  individual  with  certainty,  because 
we  do  not  know  who  are  the  bad,  and  who  are  the  good. 

II.  Final  perseverance  has  thus  far  been  treated  of  as 
a  testy  in  which  sense  the  doctrine  is  no  predestinarian  one, 
but  only  one  of  ordinary  religion  and  morality.  But  it 
remains  to  see  what  produces,  in  the  Augustinian  system,, 
this  saving  obedience  of  which  final  perseverance  is  the 
test,  that  is,  to  consider  final  perseverance  as  a  grace. 

Final  perseverance,  then,  is  maintained  by  S.  Augustine 
to  be  the  free  gift  of  God;  that  is  to  say,  not  a  gift 
bestowed  in  consideration  of  the  man's  previous  acts,  or  as 
an  assistance  to  his  own  efforts,  but  an  absolute  gift  bestowed 
upon  certain  individuals  of  the  human  race,  in  accordance 

1  The  following  is  not  a  cautious  tari  potest,  si  donee  moreretur  fide- 
statement  of  S.  Augustine's,  though  liter  vixit,  quam  multorum  annorum, 
it  admits  of  explanation  :  Potius  si  exiguum  temporis  ante  mortem  a 
hanc  perseverantiam  habuit  unius  fidei  stabilitate  defecit. — De  Dono 
anni  fidelis  et  quantum  infra  cogi-  Perseverantise,  c.  1. 


1 88  Augmtinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vn. 

with  an  eternal  Divine  decree  which  has  predestinated  them 
to  the  privilege  of  it.  This  is  quite  evident  from  the  pre 
vious  chapter,  and  requires  strictly  no  further  proof.  For 
there  is  no  necessity,  after  it  has  been  shown  that  all  good 
ness  under  the  Christian  dispensation  is  on  the  Augustinian 
doctrine  a  free  and  absolute  Divine  gift,  to  show  that  a 
particular  measure  and  degree  of  it  is  upon  the  same  doc 
trine  such  a  gift ;  and  final  perseverance  is,  as  I  have  shown, 
only  a  particular  measure  and  degree  of  goodness  ;  such  a 
one,  viz.,  as  avails  for  the  man's  salvation.  What  is  said 
of  the  whole  is  of  course  said  of  the  part.  Nevertheless, 
the  grace  of  final  perseverance  occupies  so  prominent  a 
place  in  the  Augustinian  system,  that  it  appears  proper  to 
explain  the  position  of  this  grace  in  particular,  and  to 
show  that  what  is  said  of  grace  in  general  is  said  of  this 
measure  of  it. 

In  the  first  place,  then,  S.  Augustine  says  generally  that 
final  perseverance  is  a  gift.  '  Will  any  one  dare  to  assert 
that  final  perseverance  is  not  the  gift  of  Grod  ?  .  .  .  .  We 
cannot  deny  that  final  perseverance  is  a  great  gift  of  Grod, 
coming  down  from  Him  of  whom  it  is  written, "  Every  good 
gift  and  every  perfect  gift  is  from  above,  and  corneth  down 
from  the  Father  of  lights."  ' *  '  Perseverance  is  the  gift  of 
Grod,  by  virtue  of  which  a  man  perseveres  in  Christ  unto 
the  end.' 2  '  We  pray  that  the  unbelieving  may  believe  : 
faith,  therefore,  is  the  gift  of  Grod.  We  pray  that  the 
believing  may  persevere :  final  perseverance,  therefore,  is 
the  gift  of  Grod.' 3  '  Why  is  perseverance  asked  of  Grod,  if 
it  is  not  given  by  Grod  ?  It  is  mocking  Him  to  ask  Him 
for  what  you  know  He  does  not  give,  for  what  you  can  give 
yourself.  We  pray  "  Hallowed  be  Thy  name  :"  that  is  to 
say,  we  pray  that,  having  been  sanctified  in  baptism,  we 
may  persevere  in  that  beginning.  We  pray,  therefore,  for 

perseverance  in  sanctification If  we  receive  that 

perseverance,  then,  we  receive  it  as  the  gift  of  God,  that 
great  gift  by  which  His  other  gifts  are  preserved.' 4 — '  He 
makes  men  to  persevere  in  good  who  makes  men  good.  He 

1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  vi.  3  Ibid.  c.  iii. 

2  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  i.  *  Ibid.  c.  ii. 


CHAP.  vii.  of  Final  Perseverance. 

gives  perseverance  who  makes  men  stand.  The  first  man 
did  not  receive  this  gift  of  God,  perseverance.'1 

Final  perseverance,  then,  is,  according  to  S.  Augustine, 
a  Divine  gift.  And  that  he  uses  the  word  gift  here  in  its 
natural  sense  as  a  free  gift,  not  a  conditional  one,  depending 
on  man's  own  disposition  and  conduct,  is  evident  from  the 
following  considerations. 

First,  he  makes  final  perseverance  a  gift  in  the  same 
sense  in  which  the  end  of  life  is  a  gift :  but  the  end  of  life 
is  undoubtedly  an  absolute  gift  of  God  ;  gift,  I  say,  because 
we  are  supposing  a  case  here  in  which  it  is  advantageous  to 
the  person,  and  not  the  opposite, — it  is  entirely  an  arrange 
ment  of  Providence  when  death  takes  place. 

S.  Augustine  urges  strongly  that  in  certain  cases,  the 
,end  of  life,  that  is  to  say,  the  circumstance  of  the  end  of 
life  taking  place  at  the  time  it  does,  makes  final  perseve 
rance.  He  takes  the  case  of  persons  who  die  young,  or  when 
their  characters  are  unformed,  but  die  while  their  minds 
are  as  yet  innocent  and  uncorrupted.  Such  persons,  he 
says,  attain  final  perseverance,  because  they  do  as  a  fact 
continue  in  goodness  up  to  the  end ;  but  their  final 
perseverance  is  evidently  made  by  the  occurrence  of  the 
end  while  they  are  in  a  good  state  of  mind,  not  by  their 
own  stability  and  constancy.  That  it  is  not  any  stability 
of  principle  in  the  person  which  constitutes  in  such  cases 
final  perseverance  is  plain,  he  argues,  because  final  per 
severance  takes  place,  even  where  no  principle  of  stability 
exists,  but  the  very  reverse  ;  because  it  takes  place  even  in 
cases  where  the  person,  had  he  lived,  would  have  lapsed : 
and  he  quotes  for  this  assertion  the  text  from  the  Book  of 
Wisdom,  '  Speedily  was  he  taken  away,  lest  that  wickedness 
should  alter  his  understanding,  or  deceit  beguile  his  soul/ 
Here,  he  observes,  is  manifestly  a  case  in  which  the  person's 
lapse,  had  he  lived  longer,  was  foreseen,  and  yet  final  per 
severance  takes  place  ;  in  which,  therefore,  it  is  manifest 
that  final  perseverance  takes  place  not  by  the  stability  of  the 
man,  but  by  the  act  of  God  in  putting  an  end  to  his  life  at 
the  time  He  does,  which  is  purposely  fixed  so  as  to  prevent 
1  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xii. 


T go  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vn. 

a  lapse.  And  if  the  want  of  authority  in  the  Book  of 
Wisdom,  as  not  being  part  of  the  sacred  book,  is  alleged,  he 
replies  that  he  can  do  without  the  text ;  because  even  were 
the  certainty  of  a  lapse  lost  to  his  argument,  all  that  his 
argument  really  wants  is  the  danger  of  one  l ;  for  that,  if 
there  is  the  danger  of  a  lapse,  it  cannot  be  the  man's  stability 
which  constitutes  his  final  perseverance,  but  the  act  of  God 
in  forestalling  his  trial.  What  makes  final  perseverance  in 
such  cases  then,  is,  he  concludes,  the  Divine  location  of  the 
end  of  life.  And  thence  he  argues  immediately  that  in  such 
cases  final  perseverance  itself  is  a  Divine  gift.  '  Consider 
how  contradictory  it  is  to  deny  that  perseverance  up  to  the 
end  of  this  life  is  the  gift  of  God,  when  He  undoubtedly 
gives  the  end  of  life  whenever  He  pleases  ;  and  the  giving  of 
the  end  of  life  before  an  impending  lapse  makes  final  per 
severance.'  2  '  How  is  not  perseverance  unto  the  end  of  God's 
grace,  when  the  end  itself  of  life  is  in  God's  power,  and 
God  can  confer  this  benefit  even  on  one  who  is  not  about 
to  persevere  ? '  3 

Having  proved  one  kind  of  final  perseverance  by  this 
argument  to  be  a  Divine  gift,  he  then  infers  that  all  final 
perseverance  whatever  is  the  same.  There  may  be  a  wide 
interval  between  the  final  perseverance  of  one  who  is 
snatched  from  impending  trial  by  some  sudden  illness  or 
accident,  and  that  of  one  who  has  been  reserved  for  trial 
and  has  sustained  it  without  falling  ;  but  if  the  one  kind 
is  the  gift  of  God,  the  other  is  too.  (  He  who  took  away 
the  righteous  man  by  an  early  death,  lest  wickedness  should 
alter  his  understanding,  preserves  the  righteous  man  for 
the  length  of  a  long  life,  that  wickedness  does  not  alter 
his  understanding.' 4  '  Perseverance  amid  hindrances  and 
persecutions  is  the  more  difficult ;  the  other  is  the  easier : 
but  He  to  whom  nothing  is  difficult  can  easily  give  both.'5 

The  substance  of  this  argument  is,  that  the  power  of 
resisting  temptation  is  as  much  a  gift  of  God  as  the  re 
moval  from  temptation.  Death  can  only  be  effective  of 

(  De  Prsed.  c.  xiv.  *  De  Prsed.  c.  xiv.  (980.) 

2  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  xvii.  5  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  2. 

8  Ep.  217.  c.  vi. 


CHA.P.  vii.  of  Final  Perseverance.  191 

final  perseverance  as  being  a  removal  for  ever  from  temp 
tation.  And  therefore  to  say  that  perseverance,  which 
consists  in  sustaining  temptation,  is  as  much  a  gift  of  God 
as  that  which  is  caused  by  the  occurrence  of  death,  is  only 
to  say,  that  the  power  of  sustaining  temptation  is  as  much 
a  gift  of  God  as  the  removal  from  temptation.  And  so 
the  argument  is  sometimes  put  by  S.  Augustine,  the  sub 
stance  being  given  apart  from  this  particular  form  of  it, 
which  alludes  to  the  end  of  life.  'God  is  able  to  convert 
the  averse  and  adverse  wills  of  men  to  His  faith,  and  work 
in  their  hearts  a  sustaining  of  all  adversities  and  an  over 
coming  of  all  temptation ;  inasmuch  as  He  is  able  not  to 
permit  them  to  be  tempted  at  all  above  that  they  are  able  ;' 
the  resistance  to  temptation  is  pronounced  to  be  in  the 
power  of  God  to  give,  because  the  protection  from  tempta 
tion  is  in  His  power.1 

Such  an  argument  is,  indeed,  more  ingenious  than 
sound  ;  for  it  does  not  follow  that  because  God  spares  some 
persons  on  particular  occasions  the  exercise  of  a  certain 
power  of  choice  and  original  agency  inherent  in  their  nature, 
that  therefore  such  a  power  does  not  exist,  and  would  not 
have  been  called  into  action  by  another  arrangement  of 
Providence.  But  the  argument  itself,  which  is  all  that  we 
are  concerned  with  here,  certainly  shows  the  sense  in  which 
S.  Augustine  uses  the  term  '  gift'  of  final  perseverance.  For 
there  can  be  no  doubt  that  removal  from  temptation  is  an 
absolute  and  free  gift  of  God  ;  it  being  entirely  an  arrange 
ment  of  His  providence  what  temptations  we  encounter  in 
the  course  of  our  life,  and  what  we  do  not.  If  perseve 
rance,  therefore,  in  spite  of  temptation,  is  as  much  a  gift 
of  God  as  the  removal  from  temptation,  it  is  a  gift  simple 
and  absolute.  And  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  the  occur 
rence  of  the  end  of  life  at  a  particular  time  is  an  arrange 
ment  solely  of  God's  providence.  If  all  perseverance, 
then,  is  alike  the  gift  of  God,  while  one  kind  of  it  is  said 
to  be  constituted  by  the  occurrence  of  the  end  of  life  at  a 
particular  time,  all  perseverance  is  a  gift  of  God  simple 
and  absolute. 

1  De  Dono  PITS.  c.  ix. 


192  A  ugustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vn. 

Again,  he  places  the  gift  of  perseverance  on  the  same 
ground  as  the  gift  of  baptism,  with  respect  to  the  principle 
or  law  upon  which  it  is  bestowed.  Some  persons,  he  ob 
serves,  have  baptism  given  to  them,  and  others  have  not ; 
and  in  like  manner  some  have  the  gift  of  perseverance 
given  to  them,  and  others  have  not.1  Now,  it  is  obvious 
that  the  gift  of  baptism  is  a  free  gift,  the  bestowal  of 
which  depends  solely  on  Grod's  will  and  pleasure,  who  gives 
it  to  whom  He  pleases  and  from  whom  He  pleases  with 
holds  it.  Thus  the  population  of  Europe  is  baptized,  the 
population  of  Asia  is  not ;  evidently  not  because  the  inha 
bitants  of  Europe  have  done  anything  to  deserve  it  which 
the  inhabitants  of  Asia  have  not  done,  but  simply  owing 
to  an  arrangement  of  Providence.  We  see  with  our  eyes 
that  a  man's  baptism  results  from  causes  wholly  irrespec 
tive  of  his  own  conduct,  such  as  the  part  of  the  world  he 
was  born  in,  in  what  communion,  from  what  parents. 
There  can  be  no  more  genuine  instance,  then,  of  a  free  gift 
than  baptism  ;  and,  therefore,  if  final  perseverance  is  a  gift 
in  the  same  way  in  which  baptism  is,  final  perseverance  is 
a  free  gift. 

It  remains  to  add,  that  the  notes  of  genuineness  which 
were  observed  in  the  last  chapter  to  attach  to  the  word 
4  gift,'  as  used  by  S.  Augustine,  of  grace  in  general,  attach 
to  the  word  equally  as  used  by  him  of  this  particular 
measure  of  grace,  final  perseverance.  These  notes  were 
contained  in  the  caution  that  grace  was  not  given  accord 
ing  to  merit ;  in  the  argument  from  prayer ;  and  in  the 
entire  reference  of  the  matter  to  a  ground  of  mystery,  the 
bestowal  or  withholding  of  grace  being  attributed  wholly 
to  (rod's  secret  counsels  and  sovereign  will.  All  this  is 
applied  in  particular  by  S.  Augustine  to  the  grace  of  final 
perseverance.  It  is  not  given  according  to  merit;  it  is 
given  in  the  same  sense  in  which  other  gifts  which  the  act 
of  prayer  assigns  to  Grod's  absolute  bounty  are  given  ;  and 
the  reason  why  it  is  given  to  one  man  and  not  to  another  is 
altogether  a  mysterious  and  incomprehensible  one,  belong 
ing  to  the  secret  counsels  of  Grod.  A  considerable  part  of 
1  De  Dono  Pers.  cc.  ix.  x. ;  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  Tiii. 


CHAP.  vii.  of  Final  Perseverance.  193 

the  books  '  De  Dono  Perseverantice1 '  and  '  De  Correptione 
et  Gratia ' 2  is  devoted  to  proving  that  the  gift  of  final 
perseverance  is  not  given  according  to  merit ;  that  is  to 
say,  in  consideration  of  any  previous  acts  or  efforts  of  the 
man  himself.  And  the  whole  of  the  beginning  of  the 
former  book  is  occupied  with  proving  that  final  perse 
verance  must  be  God's  gift,  inasmuch  as  we  ask  God  for  it, 
both  in  our  own  behalf  and  that  of  others,  and  what  we 
ask  God  for  we  necessarily  confess  to  be  in  His  power  to 
give  or  to  withhold. 

With  respect  to  the  law  upon  which  the  gift  of  perse 
verance  is  given  to  one  man  and  not  to  another,  he  says, 
4  If  any  one  asks  me  why  God  does  not  give  perseverance 
to  those  who  by  His  grace  lead  a  Christian  life  and  have 
love,  I  reply,  that  I  do  not  know,  I  recognise  my  measure 
in  that  text,  "  0  man,  who  art  thou  that  repliest  against 
Gol?  0  the  depth  of  the  riches  botn  of  the  wisdom  and 
knowledge  of  God !  How  unsearchable  are  His  judgments, 
and  His  ways  past  finding  out."  So  far  as  He  deigns  to 
reveal  His  judgments,  let  us  be  thankful;  so  far  as  He 
hides  them,  let  us  not  murmur.  Say  you,  who  oppose 
yourself  to  Divine  grace,  you  are  a  Christian,  a  Catholic, 
and  boast  of  being  one,  do  you  admit  or  deny  that  final 
perseverance  is  the  gift  of  God  ?  If  you  allow  it  to  be, 
then  you  and  I  are  alike  ignorant  why  one  receives  it,  and 
another  does  not ;  then  you  and  I  are  alike  unable  to  pene 
trate  the  unsearchable  judgments  of  God.'3  Again:  'Of 
two  children,  why  one  is  taken  and  the  other  left  (i.e. 
baptized  and  not  baptized),  of  two  adults,  why  one  is  so 
called,  that  he  follows  the  caller,  and  the  other  either  not 
called  at  all  or  not  so  called,  belongs  to  the  inscrutable 
judgments  of  God.  Of  two  pious  men,  why  final  perseve 
rance  is  given  to  one  and  not  to  the  other,  belongs  to  His 
still  more  inscrutable  judgments.' 4  Again :  '  It  is  evident 
that  both  the  grace  of  the  beginning  and  the  grace  of  per 
severing  to  the  end  is  not  given  according  to  our  merits, 
but  according  to  a  most  secret,  most  just,  most  wise,  most 

1  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  viii.  et  se([.  3  Ibid-  c.  viii. 

2  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xii.  *  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  ix. 


194  Augustinian  Doctrine  CFAP.  TH. 

beneficent  will ;  inasmuch  as  whom  He  hath  predestinated 
those  He  hath  also  called  with  that  call  of  which  it  is  said, 
"  The  gifts  and  calling  of  Grod  are  without  repentance." ' l 
Again  :  'Wonderful  indeed,  very  wonderful,  that  to  some  of 
His  own  sons,  whom  He  has  regenerated  and  to  whom  He 
has  given  faith,  hope,  and  charity,  God  does  not  give  per 
severance  !  that  He  who  oftentimes  pardons  and  adopts  the 
stranger's  (unbeliever's)  son,  should  withhold  such  a  gift 
from  His  own  !  Who  but  must  wonder,  be  astonished,  and 
amazed  at  this  !  ' 2  Again  :  '  I  am  speaking  of  those  who 
have  not  the  gift  of  perseverance,  but  have  turned  from 
good  to  evil,  and  die  in  that  declination  ;  let  them  (his 
opponents)  tell  me  why  Grod  did  not  take  such  persons  out 
of  this  world  while  they  were  yet  unchanged  ?  Was  it 
because  He  could  not  ?  or  was  it  because  He  foresaw  not 
their  future  wickedness  ?  They  cannot  assert  either  of 
these  without  perversity  and  madness.  Then  why  did  He 
do  so  ?  Let  them  answer  this  question  before  they  deride 
me,  when  I  exclaim,  "  How  unsearchable  are  His  judg 
ments,  and  His  ways  past  finding  out!"  Either  Grod 

gives  that  gift  to  whom  He  will,  or  Scripture  lies 

Let  them  confess  this  truth  at  once,  and  why  Grod  gives 
that  gift  to  one  and  not  to  another, — condescend  without 
a  murmur  to  be  ignorant  with  me.' 3 

Final  perseverance,  then,  is,  upon  the  Augustinian 
doctrine,  the  true  and  absolute  gift  of  Grod  to  certain 
members  of  the  human  race  ;  to  whom,  according  to  an 
eternal  decree,  He  has  determined  to  give  it :  and  it  has 
that  prominent  place  which  it  has  in  the  predestinarian 
scheme,  because  it  is  that  measure  of  Divine  grace  which 
is  sufficient  for  salvation.  The  predestinarian  doctrine  is 
that  certain  persons  are  predestined  by  Grod  from  all 
eternity  to  be  saved ;  but  Grod  only  saves  the  righteous, 
and  not  the  wicked.  It  must  therefore  be  provided,  in 
accordance  with  this  doctrine,  that  those  persons  shall  ex 
hibit  as  much  goodness  of  life  as  is  necessary  for  the  end 
to  which  they  are  ordained ;  and  final  perseverance  is  this 
measure  of  goodness. .  The  gift  of  final  perseverance,  then, 
1  De  Dono  Pers.  c.  xiii.  »  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  viii.  «  Ibid.  c.  viii. 


CFAP.  vii.  of  Final  Perseverance.  195 

is  the  great  gift  which  puts  into  execution  God's  eternal 
decree  with  respect  to  the  whole  body  of  the  elect.  He 
may  predestine  some  to  a  higher  and  others  to  a  lower 
place,  but  He  predestines  all  the  elect  to  a  place  in  the 
kingdom  of  heaven  ;  and  therefore,  while  He  provides  that 
some  shall  exhibit  higher  and  others  lower  degrees  of  sanc 
tity  and  goodness,  He  provides  that  all  shall  exhibit  enough 
for  admission  ;  which  sufficiency  is  final  perseverance. 


CHAPTER  VIII. 

AUGUSTINIAN    DOCTRINE    OF    FREEWILL. 

THE  preceding  chapters  have  exhibited  a  full  and  sys 
tematic  scheme  of  predestinarian  doctrine,  as  held  by  S. 
Augustine,  who  asserts  in  the  first  place  an  eternal  Divine 
decree,  whereby  one  part  of  mankind  has  been,  antece 
dently  to  any  moral  difference  between  the  two,  separated 
from  the  other,  and  the  one  ordained  to  eternal  life,  and 
the  other  to  eternal  punishment ; 1  and  next  supplies  a 
grace  for  putting  it  into  effect.2  But  while  he  lays  down 
this  doctrine  of  predestination  and  irresistible  grace,  S. 
Augustine  at  the  same  time  acknowledges  the  existence  of 
freewill  in  man — liberum  arbitrium  ;  an  admission,  which, 
understood  in  its  popular  sense,  would  have  been  a  counter 
balance  to  all  the  rest  of  his  scheme.  The  question,  how 
ever,  immediately  arises,  what  he  means  by  freewill; 
whether  he  uses  the  word  in  the  sense  which  the  ordinary 
doctrine  of  freewill  requires,  or  in  another  and  a  different 
sense.  Persons  are  apt  indeed  to  suppose,  as  soon  as  ever 
they  hear  the  word  freewill,  that  the  word  must  involve  all 
that  those  who  hold  the  regular  doctrine  of  freewill  mean 
by  it.  It  remains,  however,  to  see  whether  this  is  the  case 
in  S.  Augustine's  use  of  the  word. 

The  doctrine  of  freewill  consists  of  two  parts ;  one  of 
1  Chap.  V.  2  Chaps.  VI.  and  VII. 

o  2 


Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  YUI. 


which  has  respect  to  the  existence  of  the  will,  and  the 
other  to  the  mode  in  which  it  is  moved  and  determined. 
That  part  which  respects  the  existence  of  the  will,  the 
doctrine  of  freewill,  and  the  contrary  doctrine,  hold  in 
common.  No  person  in  his  senses  can  deny  the  fact  of  the 
will,  that  we  will  to  do  this,  that,  and  the  other  thing,  that 
we  act  with  intention,  design,  deliberation.  We  are  directly 
conscious  of  all  this.  No  predestinarian,  therefore,  how 
ever  rigid,  denies  it  ;  and  the  whole  set  of  sensations  which 
are  connected  with  willing,  or  the  whole  fact  of  the  will,  in 
its  minutest  and  most  subtle  particulars,  is  the  common 
ground  both  of  him  and  his  opponent.  But  the  fact  of  the 
will  admitted,  the  further  question  remains,  how  this  will 
is  determined  ;  that  is,  caused  to  decide  on  one  side  or 
another,  and  choose  this  or  that  act.  The  doctrine  of 
freewill  is  that  the  cause  of  this  decision  is  the  will  itself, 
and  that  the  will  has  a  power  of  self-determination  inhe 
rent  in  it.  This  appears  to  the  maintainers  of  this  doc 
trine  the  natural  inference  from  that  whole  fact  of  willing, 
of  which  they  are  conscious,  so  that  they  could  not  draw 
any  other  without  seeming  to  themselves  to  contradict 
plain  reason.  Nobody  can  assert  indeed  that  he  is  con 
scious  distinctly,  and  after  the  mode  of  clear  perception, 
of  a  power  of  determining  his  own  will,  for  all  that  he  is 
distinctly  conscious  of  is  his  will  itself.  Nevertheless,  the 
will  as  we  feel  and  experience  it,  acting  with  struggle, 
effort,  resolution,  summoning  up  of  force,  and  deliberate 
choice  of  alternatives,  has  so  much  the  appearance  of  being 
self-determining  and  original,  that  when  the  notion  is  sug 
gested  that  it  is  not,  such  a  notion  is  felt  to  be  contrary 
to  an  idea  which  we  naturally  and  instinctively  have  re 
specting  our  will,  its  originality  appearing  to  be  implied 
in  this  kind  of  motion  and  operation.  Nor  is  this  self- 
determining  power  of  the  will  interfered  with  by  the  doc 
trine  of  assisting  grace,  which  is  so  formed  as  to  admit  the 
human  will  as  an  original  agent,  co-operating  with  grace. 
The  doctrine  of  freewill,  then,  is  that  the  will  is  deter 
mined  by  itself,  or  is  an  original  agent,  as  distinguished 
from  the  assertion  simply  of  a  will  in  man,  which  latter  it 


CHAP.  -mi.  of  Freewill.  197 

holds  in  common  with  the  rival  and  opposite  doctrine  re 
specting  the  will. 

The  validity  indeed  of  this  whole  distinction  between 
the  will  itself  and  the  will  as  self-determining,  i.e.  the 
existence  of  this  self-determining  power  in  the  will  over 
and  above  the  fact  of  willing,  is  denied  by  the  school  of 
metaphysicians,  who  take  against  the  common  doctrine  of 
freewill  and  favour  that  of  necessity.  They  maintain  free 
will  to  consist  in  the  simple  fact  of  will ;  that  we  act  wil 
lingly  and  without  constraint ;  and  they  deny  that  we  can 
go  any  further  than  this,  or  see  anything  whatever  more 
than  this  fact,  however  far  we  may  try  to  look.  They  say 
that  in  this  consists  the  whole  of  freewill,  that  this  is  all 
we  mean  or  can  mean  by  it ;  and  that  if  we  try  to  go 
any  deeper,  we  involve  ourselves  in  confusion  and  absurdity. 
This  position  is  among  others  maintained  by  Locke,  whose 
great  fairness  of  mind  and  anxiety  to  represent  faithfully 
and  exactly  the  truth  respecting  the  human  mind  and  its 
constitution  entitle  his  opinions  on  this  subject  to  much 
consideration,  because  he  does  not  appear  to  have  started 
with  any  bias  one  way  or  another  on  the  examination  cf 
the  question,  but  to  have  decided  according  to  what  he 
thought  the  plain  facts  of  the  case.  I  cannot  but  think, 
however,  that  his  love  of  exact  truth  and  the  test  of  actual 
perception  and  apprehension  which  his  philosophy  applies, 
have  been  carried  too  far  in  this  instance,  and  led  him  into 
a  mistake.  For  this  test  cannot  be  applied  with  absolute 
strictness  in  all  cases,  as  I  have  often  said ;  there  being 
truths  of  reason,  which  do  not  admit  of  it,  truths  in  their 
very  nature  indeterminate  and  indistinct ;  to  which  class 
belongs  the  truth  now  in  question,  that  of  the  self-deter 
mining  power  of  the  will. 

Locke's  elaborate  argument  on  this  subject  divides 
itself  into  two  questions  ;  one  whether  the  will  is  free,  the 
other  whether  the  man  or  the  agent  is  free  to  will. 

The  first  question  is  not  really  the  question  at  issue 
between  the  two  sides ;  for  what  those  who  maintain  the 
self-determining  power  of  the  will  mean  by  the  will  being 
free,  is,  that  the  agent  is  free  to  will :  nor  does  their  posi- 


198  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHA?.  vm. 

tion  at  all  necessarily  involve  the  particular  expression, — 
freedom  of  the  will,  which  Locke  first  impugns  in  his  argu 
ment,  though  they  use  it  as  a  convenient  mode  of  stating 
the  real  truth  for  which  they  contend,  Locke,  however, 
first  examines  this  expression,  and  starts  the  question  in 
this  particular  form,  whether  the  will  is  free  ;  and  he  de 
cides  against  its  freedom  on  the  ground  that  freedom  is  a 
power  and  the  will  a  power,  and  that  a  power  cannot  be 
predicated  of  a  power,  power  being  the  attribute  of  an 
:^agent.  Freedom,  he  says,  is  the  power  to  act  as  we  will. 
'  So  far  as  a  man  has  power  to  think  or  not  to  think,  to 
move  or  not  to  move,  according  to  the  preference  or  direc 
tion  of  his  own  mind,  so  far  is  a  man  free The 

idea  of  liberty  is  the  idea  of  a  power  in  any  agent  to  do  or 
forbear  any  particular  action,  according  to  the  determina 
tion  or  thought  of  his  mind.'  *  Freedom,  then,  being  the 
power  to  act  as  we  will,  assert  this  power  of  the  will,  he 
says,  and  what  does  it  become  ? — the  power  of  the  will  to 
act  as  it  wills  ;  i.e.  for  this  is  the  only  act  the  will  can  do, 
the  power  of  the  will  to  will  as  it  wills.  But  this  is  a 
power  which  is  contained  in  the  very  act  of  willing,  and 
does  not  go  at  all  beyond  the  mere  fact  of  will.  So  that, 
he  argues,  when  we  would  attribute  this  power — i.  e.  free 
dom — to  the  will,  we  find  immediately  that  we  are  making 
no  assertion  beyond  that  of  the  will  itself,  not  advancing 
a  step  farther,  but  going  on  like  a  rocking  horse  upon  the 
same  ground.  Though  in  a  certain  incorrect  way  he  allows 
this  freedom  to  be  asserted  of  the  will,  because  its  exertion 
is  thus  ipso  facto  freedom.  '  If  freedom  can  with  any 
propriety  of  speech  be  applied  to  power,  it  may  be  attri 
buted  to  the  power  that  is  in  man  to  produce  or  forbear 
producing,  by  choice  or  preference,  which  is  that  which 
denominates  him  free,  and  is  freedom  itself.  But  if  any 
one  should  ask  whether  freedom  were  free,  he  would  be 
suspected  not  to  understand  well  what  he  said  ;  and  he 
should  be  thought  to  deserve  Midas'  ears,  who,  knowing 
that  rich  was  a  denomination  for  the  possession  of  riches, 
should  demand  whether  riches  themselves  were  rich.'  * 
1  Essay,  book  2.  c.  21.  2  Essay,  book  2,  c.  21. 


CHAP.  V1IJ. 


of  Freewill.  199 


But  the  question  whether  the  will  is  free  being  thus 
decided,  the  next  follows,  whether  the  man  is  free  to  will ; 
which  is,  as  has  been  just  said,  the  real  question  at  issue 
between  the  two  sides.  On  this  question,  then,  he  first 
decides — and  no  one  will  oppose  him — that  the  man  is  not 
free  in  the  case  of  any  proposed  action,  generally  and  alto 
gether  in  respect  of  willing  ;  but  that  he  must  will  one 
thing  or  another,  either  doing  the  act  or  abstaining  from 
it.  '  Willing  or  volition  being  an  action,  and  freedom 
consisting  in  a  power  of  acting  or  not  acting,  a  man  in 
respect  of  willing  or  the  act  of  volition,  when  an  action  in 
his  power  is  once  proposed  to  his  thoughts  as  presently  to 
be  done,  cannot  be  free.  The  reason  whereof  is  very  mani 
fest  ;  for  it  being  unavoidable  that  the  action  depending 
on  his  will  should  exist  or  not  exist,  and  its  existence  or 
not  existence  following  perfectly  the  determination  and 
preference  of  his  will,  he  cannot  avoid  willing  the  existence 
or  not  existence  of  that  action ;  it  is  absolutely  necessary 

that  he  will  the  one  or  the  other This,  then,  is 

evident,  that  in  all  proposals  of  present  action,  a  man  is 
not  at  liberty  to  will  or  not  to  will,  because  he  cannot  for 
bear  willing.' 

It  being  decided,  then,  that  the  man  must  will  one  way 
or  another — i.e.  is  not  free  to  will  neither  way — Locke 
comes  at  last  to  the  question,  which  is  the  only  real  one 
between  the  two  sides,  and  upon  which  the  whole  contro 
versy  turns — Is  he  free  to  will  either  way  ?  And  he  settles 
it  thus  summarily.  '  Since,  then,  it  is  plain  that  in  most 
cases  a  man  is  not  at  liberty,  whether  he  will  or  no,  the 
next  thing  demanded  is,  Whether  a  man  be  at  liberty  to 
will  which  of  the  two  he  pleases  ?  This  question  carries 
the  absurdity  of  it  so  manifestly  in  itself,  that  one  might 
thereby  be  sufficiently  convinced  that  liberty  concerns  not 
the  will.  For  to  ask  whether  a  man  be  at  liberty  to  will 
either  motion  or  rest,  speaking  or  silence,  which  he  pleases, 
is  to  ask  whether  a  man  can  will  what  he  wills,  or  be 
pleased  with  what  he  is  pleased  with.  A  question  which, 
I  think,  needs  no  answer ;  and  they  who  can  make  a  ques 
tion  of  it,  must  suppose  one  will  to  determine  the  acts 


2oo  Augustinian  Doctrine          CHAP.  vm. 

of  another,  and  another  to  determine  that,  and  so  on  in 
infinitum.' 

Upon  this  ground  it  is  decided  that  the  man  or  agent 
does  not  determine  his  own  will.  But  is  not  this  an  argu 
ment  which  simply  takes  advantage  of  the  difficulties  of 
language,  with  which  questions  like  these  are  beset  ?  The 
position  that  the  man  determines  his  own  will  is  stated  in 
a/orm  in  which  it  becomes  absurd,  and  then  the  charge 
of  absurdity  is  brought  against  the  position  itself.  It  is 
described  as  the  assertion,  that  '  the  man  is  at  liberty  to 
will  which  of  the  tiuo  he  pleases?  or  wills.  And  certainly 
in  this  form  the  position  is  absurd ;  for  it  assumes  the 
previous  existence  of  a  particular  decision  of  the  will,  as 
the  condition  of  the  power  or  liberty  of  the  man  to  make 
it.  But  though  in  loose  speech  the  self-determining  power 
of  the  will  may  sometimes  be  expressed  in  this  way,  the 
truth  really  intended  and  meant  does  not  depend  on  such 
an  expression  of  it.  The  truth  which  is  meant,  is  not  the 
man's  power  to  will  as  he  wills  or  pleases,  but  simply  his 
power  to  will ;  that  his  will  rises  ultimately  and  originally 
from  himself  as  the  agent  or  possessor  of  the  will :  in  other 
words,  that  that  whole  affair  of  the  man  willing  is  an 
original  event. 

The  question  of  such  a  self-determining  power  in  the 
will  may  be  called  « an  unreasonable,  because  unintelligible 
question  ; ' 1  and  the  other  ground  be  preferred,  as  simpler 
and  more  common  sense  and  straightforward,  that  will  is 
will,  and  that  that  is  all  that  can  be  said  about  it.  But  if 
truths  are  to  be  rejected  because  they  are  indistinct,  in 
definite,  and  incapable  of  consistent  statement,  we  must 
reject  a  large  class  of  most  important  truths  belonging  to 
our  rational  nature.2  This  self-determining  power  in  the 
will  cannot  be  stated  accurately,  nor  can  it  be  apprehended 
accurately  ;  but  have  we  not  a  perception  in  this  direction  ? 
Is  there  not  a  rational  instinct  which  speaks  to  our  origi 
nality  as  agents,  as  there  is  a  rational  instinct  which  tells 
us  of  substance,  of  cause,  of  infinity  ?  And  does  not  this 
instinct  or  perception  see  a  certain  way,  so  that  we  have 
1  Essay,  book  2.  c.  21.  s.  14.  »  See  Chap.  II. 


CHAP.    Till. 


of  Freewill.  201 


some  sort  of  idea  of  the  thing  in  our  minds  ?  Locke's  re 
jection  of  this  power  in  the  will  on  such  a  ground  appears 
to  be  inconsistent  with  his  admission  of  the  class  of  indis 
tinct  ideas  ?  *  For  if  we  admit  such  a  kind  and  order  of 
truths,  we  are  arbitrarily  to  exclude  such  a  truth  as  this 
from  the  benefit  of  it — a  truth  which  is  felt  and  asserted 
by  the  great  mass  of  mankind  ?  But  this  is  the  line  which 
Locke  takes  on  this  question.  He  sees  there  is  no  distinct 
idea  of  originality  or  self-determination  in  the  human 
mind  ;  and  he  does  not  allow  such  an  idea  a  place  as  an 
indistinct  one.  He  thus  rests  ultimately  in  the  simple 
fact  of  will,  as  the  whole  of  the  truth  of  the  freedom  of 
the  will.  c  For  how  can  we  think  any  one  freer,  than  to 
have  the  power  to  do  what  he  will  ?  .  .  .  .  We  can  scarce 
tell  how  to  imagine  any  being  freer  than  to  be  able  to  do 
what  he  wills.' 2 

It  must  be  added,  that  important  results  in  theology 
follow  the  decision  of  this  question  respecting  the  will,  one 
way  or  another.  On  the  supposition  of  a  self-determining 
power  in  the  will,  and  so  far  as  it  is  a  true  one,  the  Divine 
justice  is  freed  from  all  substantial  difficulty  ;  for  moral 
evil  is  brought  instantly  home  to  the  individual,  who  is 
made  responsible  for  it,  and  so  justly  subject  to  punish 
ment.  But  deny  this  power,  and  suppose  the  will  to  be 
moved  from  without,  and  the  Divine  justice  is  imme 
diately  challenged,  and  we  are  involved  in  whatever  diffi 
culty  accompanies  the  depravation  of  moral  beings  from  a 
source  external  to  themselves,  and  their  punishment  when 
their  depravation  has  proceeded  from  such  a  source.  I  am 
speaking  of  the  latter  doctrine  as  held  definitely  or  exclu 
sively.  It  may  be  said,  indeed,  that  the  will  which  is  thus 
moved  from  without  is  still  will,  the  will  of  the  individual, 
— that  it  has  all  the  properties  which  we  can  distinctly 
conceive  of  will ;  but  these  characteristics  of  will  will  not 
prevent  the  difficulties  which  arise  from  this  theory  of  its 
motion  or  determination,.  And  this  perhaps  is  worth  the 
consideration  of  those  who  not  so  much  deny  the  self- 
determining  power  of  the  will,  as  set  the  question  aside  as 
1  NOTE  IV.  .*  Essay,  book  2.  c.  21.  s.  21. 


2O2  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vin. 

unimportant ;  as  if  the  acknowledgment  of  will  as  a  fact 
were  the  only  thing  of  real  importance.  Of  course,  if  this 
is  so,  it  is  impossible  to  be  in  the  wrong  on  this  subject ; 
for  nobody  in  his  senses  can  deny  the  fact  of  the  will. 
But  the  farther  question  of  its  determination  cannot  be 
said  to  be  unimportant,  both  in  itself,  and  as  involving 
these  theological  results.  It  makes  a  difference  in  what 
way  we  decide  it. 

A  distinguished  writer  of  the  present  day,  Archbishop 
Whately,  adopts  this  line  :  '  Let,  then,  necessitarians  of  all 
descriptions  but  step  forth  into  light,  and  explain  their 
own  meaning ;  and  we  shall  find  that  their  positions  are 
either  obviously  untenable,  or  else  perfectly  harmless  and 
nearly  insignificant.  If  in  saying  that  all  things  are  fixed 
and  necessary,  they  mean  that  there  is  no  such  thing  as 
voluntary  action,  we  may  appeal  from  the  verbal  quibbles 
which  alone  afford  a  seeming  support  to  such  a  doctrine  to 
universal  consciousness ;  which  will  authorise  even  those 
who  have  never  entered  into  such  speculations  as  the  fore 
going,  to  decide  on  the  falsity  of  the  conclusion,  though 
they  are  perplexed  with  the  subtle  fallacies  of  the  argu 
ment.  But  if  nothing  more  be  meant  than  that  every  event 
depends  on  causes  adequate  to  produce  it,  that  nothing  is 
in  itself  contingent,  accidental  or  uncertain,  but  is  called 
so  only  with  reference  to  a  person  who  does  not  know  all 
the  circumstances  on  which  it  depends, — and  that  it  is 
absurd  to  say  anything  could  have  happened  otherwise  than 
it  did,  supposing  all  the  circumstances  connected  with  it 
to  remain  the  same, — then  the  doctrine  is  undeniably  true, 
but  perfectly  harmless,  not  at  all  encroaching  on  free  agency 
and  responsibility,  and  amounting  in  fact  to  little  more 
than  an  expansion  of  the  axiom,  that  it  is  impossible  for 
the  same  thing  to  be  and  not  to  be.' T 

Archbishop  Whately  in  this  passage  more  than  tolerates 
necessitarianism,  because  he  adopts  it.  He  asserts  that 
*  nothing  is  in  itself  contingent,  accidental,  uncertain,'  and 
that,  supposing  all  the  circumstances  connected  with  it  to 
remain  the  same, « it  is  absurd  to  say  anything  could  have 
1  Appendix  to  Archbp.  King,  On  Predestination,  p.  99. 


CHAP.  viii.  of  Freewill.  203 

happened  otherwise  than  as  it  did?  This  is  the  doctrine 
of  necessity.  Suppose  two  men  under  exactly  the  same 
circumstances  as  regards  a  particular  temptation  to  which 
they  are  subjected-  the  same  even  to  the  minutest  parti 
culars.  Let  the  circumstances  which  are  thus  identical  be 
not  external  only,  but  internal  ones.  Let  them  have  the 
same  amount  of  inward  bias  or  inclination,  and  let  this 
inclination  be  acted  upon  from  without  by  a  whole,  com 
plex,  manifold  and  intricate  machinery  of  invitations  and 
allurements,  precisely  the  same  in  both  cases.  Lei-  every 
thing,  in  short,  which  is  properly  circumstantial — i.e.  is 
not  the  very  act  of  the  will  itself — be  by  supposition  the 
same  in  both  cases.  Now,  the  doctrine  of  freewill  is,  that 
these  two  agents  may,  under  this  entire  and  absolute  iden 
tity  of  circumstances,  act  differently  ;  the  doctrine  of  neces 
sity  is  that  they  must  act  the  same.  According  to  the 
doctrine  of  freewill  there  is  an  ultimate  power  of  choice  in 
the  human  will,  which,  however  strongly  it  may  be  drawn, 
or  tempted,  or  attracted  to  decide  one  way  or  another  by 
external  appeals  or  motives,  is  not  ruled  and  decided  by 
such  motives,  but  by  the  will  itself  only.  This  is  the  self- 
determining  power  of  the  will,  the  assertion  of  which  is  the 
characteristic  of  that  doctrine.  Under  this  identity  of  cir 
cumstances,  an  original  act  or  motion  of  the  will  is  said  to 
take  place,  which  may  be  different  in  the  two  persons,  and 
be  the  one  single  difference  in  the  whole  of  the  two  cases. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  necessitarian  maintains  that  where 
the  circumstances,  external  and  internal,  are  really  and 
completely  alike,  there  is  not  room  for  this  further  differ 
ence  ;  but  that  the  issue  will  be  the  same  in  both  cases, 
and  both  will  act  alike.  Archbishop  Whately's  position, 
that  '  supposing  all  the  circumstances  connected  with  it  to 
remain  the  same,  it  is  absurd  to  say  anything  could  have 
happened  otherwise  than  as  it  did,'  is  identical  with  this 
necessitarian  one.  He  adds,  that  this  assertion  that  the 
event  must  always  be  the  same  under  the  same  circum 
stances,  is  '  little  more  than  an  expansion  of  the  position 
that  it  is  impossible  for  the  same  thing  to  be  and  not  to 
be.'  Of  course,  supposing  it  true  that  the  whole  of  the 


2O4  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  VIH. 

circumstances  of  an  act  or  event  amount  to  and  really  are 
and  constitute  that  act  or  event  itself,  it  immediately  fol 
lows,  that  to  say  that  under  the  same  circumstances  the 
same  event  will  take  place,  is  an  identical  assertion.  But 
that  the  assertion  should  be  thus  identical  supposes  that 
circumstances  do  constitute  the  act  or  event ;  i.e.  it  sets 
aside  and  ignores  an  original  motion  of  the  will  under  the 
circumstances,  as  if  it  had  no  place  in  the  question,  and 
there  were  no  such  thing  :  which  is  the  necessitarian  as 
sumption.  The  Archbishop  slightly  qualifies  his  remark 
indeed,  and  only  calls  the  two  assertions  nearly  identical : 
the  assertion  that  the  same  event  must  take  place  under 
the  same  circumstances  '  amounts  to  little  more  than  an 
expansion  of  the  axiom  that  it  is  impossible  for  the  same 
thing  to  be  and  not  to  be.'  But  surely  the  two  assertions 
must  be  either  absolutely  and  completely  identical,  or  not 
at  all.  For  if  it  is  not  true,  wholly  and  entirely,  that 
identity  of  circumstances  is  the  identity  of  the  act,  what 
is  the  reason  of  this  defect  of  truth  ?  It  is — for  there  can 
be  no  other, — that  there  is  an  original  motion  of  the  will, 
which  may  be  different  in  spite  of  the  circumstances  being 
the  same.  But  if  there  is  an  original  motion  of  the  will  in 
the  case,  then  the  whole  position  that  the  same  circum 
stances  will  produce  the  same  event  or  act  falls  at  once  to 
the  ground ;  another  principle  comes  in,  which  altogether 
upsets  the  necessary  force  of  circumstances,  and  produces 
the  widest  possible  differences  of  acts  under  circumstances 
exactly  the  same.1 

1  A  position  maintained  in  ano-  longs  to  them  in  their  primary 
ther  passage  in  Archbp.  Whately's  sense)  of  compulsion,  and  of  one 
Essay,  is  in  tendency  and  language,  person  submitting  to  another  ;  where- 
necessitarian,  though  it  admits  of  as  here  they  are  only  used  figu- 
an  explanation.  'But  some  may  ratively,  the  terms  "weak"  and 
say,  have  I  the  power  of  choosing  "  strong,"  when  applied  to  motives, 
among  several  motives  at  once  pre-  denoting  nothing  but  their  greater 
seat  to  my  mind?  or  must  I  obey  or  less  tendency  to  prevail  (that  is, 
the,  strongest  ?  for  if  so,  how  can  I  to  operate  and' take  effect)  in  prac- 
enjoy  freewill  ?  Here,  again,  is  an  tice,  so  that  to  say  "  the  stronger 
entanglement  in  ambiguous  words  :  motive  prevails"  is  only  another 
must  and  "obey  "and  "strong-  form  of  saying  that  "that  which 
est  suggest  the  idea  (which  be-  prevails  prevails !" '—P.  95.  Now, 


CHAP.  Till. 


of  Freewill.  205 


The  writer,  indeed,  appears  to  think  that  the  admission 
of  the  fact  of  the  will,  or  '  voluntary  action,'  is  itself  a 
safeguard  against  necessitarianism  ;  and  that  necessitarians 
have  to  be  driven  by  argument  into  the  acknowledgment 
of  this  fact ;  the  admission  of  which,  when  they  are  forced 
to  see  and  confess  it,  makes  them  virtually  cease  to  be  such. 
But  all  necessitarians  acknowledge  in  limine,  and  without 
any  difficulty,  the  fact  of  the  will ;  indeed,  every  one  of 
sound  mind  must. 

I  will  not,  however,  understand  Archbishop  Whately  in 
this  passage  as  more  than  neutral ;  tolerating  the  necessi 
tarian,  and  treating  the  question  between  him  and  his 
opponent,  provided  the  fact  of  the  will  is  admitted,  as  one 
of  no  importance.  But  perhaps  even  this  assertion  should 
be  modified.  It  is  true,  indeed,  that,  so  long  as  men  ac 
knowledge  a  will,  responsibility,  and  moral  obligations,  there 
is  nothing  in  necessitarianism  to  interfere  with  practical 
religion.  But  still  the  theory  has  important  consequences 
in  theology,  and  largely  affects  our  idea  of  the  Divine 
dealings,  which  it  represents  under  an  aspect  repulsive  to 
our  natural  feeling  and  sense  of  justice.  And  though  a 
mystery  must  be  acknowledged  on  this  subject,  it  is  a 
different  thing  to  hold  the  predestinarian  doctrine,  as  the 

when  persons  talk  of  the  stronger  comes  the  more  strongly  felt  mo- 
motive  prevailing,  they  sometimes  tive  ;  and  the  man  acts  on  the  right 
make  the  assertion  in  a  sense  in-  side.  In  this  sense,  then,  there  is 
volving  an  original  act  of  the  will  no  doctrine  of  necessity  involved  in 
itself.  A  man  is  drawn  by  some  the  position  that  a  man  must  act 
.strong  temptation  towards  a  bad  upon  the  strongest  motive.  For  in 
act,  while  conscience  dissuades :  the  every  act  of  choice  between  good 
bad  motive  is  at  the  first  much  the  and  evil,  the  will  either  does  or  does 
stronger  of  the  two  ;  he  feels  the  not  create  this  good  stronger  mo- 
former  as  almost  overwhelming,  tive  ;  in  either  case  it  is  the  man's 
while  the  latter  is  but  feebly  felt;  will  acting  well  or  ill,  and  not  the 
but  his  will  now  comes  in  and  de-  power  of  externally  caused  motives, 
liberately  increases  and  strengthens  which  produces  the  result.  But 
the  conscientious  motive,  calling  up  understanding  by  the  term  motive 
every  consideration  of  present  or  something  simply  acting  from  with- 
future  interest  to  outweigh  the  other,  out  upon  the  mind,  to  say  that  the 
and  putting  the  advantages  of  the  stronger  motive  must  prevail,  is  to 
right  side  as  vividly  before  the  say  that  the  individual's  act  is  de- 
mind  as  possible.  Thus  in  time  cided  by  causes  outside  of  himself, 
what  was  the  more  feebly  felt  be-  :  . 


206  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  TUT. 

Church  at  large  does,  as  a  mystery  and  with  a  reserve,  and 
to  hold  it  as  a  definite  and  complete  doctrine. 

The  language  of  S.  Augustine  respecting  the  will  may 
be  pat  under  two  heads ;  under  the  first  of  which  it  does 
not  come  up  to  the  received  doctrine  of  freewill,  and  under 
the  second  is  opposed  to  it. 

I.  First,  freewill,  as  maintained  by  S.  Augustine,  does 
not  mean  so  much  as  the  freewill  above  described,  or  a 
self-determining  will ;  but  only  a  ivill ;  his  language  not 
advancing  beyond  that  point  up  to  which  the  doctrine  of 
freewill  and  the  opposite  doctrine  agree. 

In  examining  the  language  of  Augustine  on  this  sub 
ject  we  must  take  care  to  distinguish  between  what  he  says 
of  the  freewill  of  man  in  his  former  perfect,  and  that  of 
man  in  his  present  corrupt  state.  In  the  book  De  Libero 
Arbitrio,  a  freewill  is  indeed  described  which  comes  up  to 
the  above  definition  of  it  as  original  and  self-determining. 
The  Manichean  there,  not  content  with  the  fact  of  the 
human  will  as  accounting  for  moral  evil  in  the  world, 
demands  the  cause  of  that  will ;  and  Augustine  replies  : 
'  The  will  being  the  cause  of  sin,  you  ask  the  cause  of  the 
will :  should  I  discover  it,  will  you  not  ask  then  the  cause 
of  that  cause ;  and  what  limit  of  inquiry  can  there  be,  if 
you  will  go  deeper  than  the  very  root  ?  .  .  .  .  What  cause 
of  will  can  there  be  before  will  ?  For  either  this  cause  is 
will,  and  we  are  no  nearer  the  root  than  we  were  before ;  or 
it  is  not  will,  and  in  that  case  there  is  no  sin.' 1  Here  a 
will  is  described  which  is  truly  an  original  agent  in  nature, 
having  no  cause  but  itself.  But  the  will  thus  described  is 
the  will  of  man  in  his  created,  not  in  his  fallen  state.' 2  In 
some  passages,  again,  quoted  in  a  former  chapter,  a  will 
was  described  which  was  self-determining  and  original ;  for 
it  was  said  that  the  first  man  '  had  such  an  assistance  given 
him  as  he  could  use  if  he  willed,  and  neglect  if  he  willed  ; 
not  one  by  which  it  was  caused  that  he  did  will.' 3  His  will, 
therefore,  had  no  cause  beyond  itself,  or  was  self-caused, 

1  L.  3.  c.  xvii.  qua  homo  factus    est    loquimur. — 

2  Cum  autem  de  libera  voluntate       L.  3.  c.  18. 

faciendi  loquimur,  de  ilia  scilicet  in          8  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  e.  xi. 


CHAP.  viii.  of  Freewill.  207 

that  is  to  say,  self-determined  and  original :  but  this,  he 
expressly  says,  was  the  will  of  the  first  man  in  his  state  of 
integrity,  and  not  of  man  as  now  existing. 

When  Augustine  comes  to  describe  the  will  of  man  as 
now  existing,  he  describes  it  simply  by  the  fact  of  will  or 
willing.  There  are  various  passages  in  his  works,  especially 
a  passage  in  the  book  De  Libero  Arbitrio,  another  in  the 
book  De  Spiritu  et  Literd,  and  another  in  his  Retracta 
tions  explanatory  of  a  passage  in  the  book  De  Diversis 
Qucestionibus  ad  Simplicianum,  in  which  it  is  defined 
with  much  minuteness  and  labour  what  the  freedom  of  the 
will  is,  and  in  what  it  consists ;  and  this  definition  termi 
nates  in  the  fact  of  a  will.  First,  freedom,  itself  is  defined  ; 
and  it  is  said  to  consist  in  power.  We  are  free  when  it  is 
in  our  power  to  do  a  thing.  But  what  is  power  ?  for  if, 
becomes  necessary  now  to  say  what  power  is,  if  there  is 
anything  to  be  said  about  it.  He  proceeds  accordingly  to 
define  next  what  is  meant  by  its  being  in  our  power  to  do 
a  thing ;  and  this  he  defines  by  saying  that  it  is  our  having 
the  power  to  do  it  if  ^ve  will.  '  What  need  for  further 
question  ?  we  call  that  power  where  to  the  will  is  joined 
the  ability  to  do.  That  is  in  a  man's  power  which  he  does 
if  he  wills ,  does  not  do  if  he  does  not  will — quod  si  vult  ^ 
facit,  si  non  vult  non  facit.1  Freedom  being  thus  defined,  |7  f , 
it  only  remains  to  apply  this  definition  of  freedom  to  the 
will,  which  is  a  simple  and  easy  process.  Freedom  is  a  » 
power  to  do  a  thing  if  we  will.  Freedom  of  the  will, 
therefore,  is  the  power  to  will  if  we  will — a  power,  he  adds, 
which  unquestionably  every  man  possesses ;  for  if  we  will, 
we  are  necessarily  not  only  able  to  will,  but  do  will :  there 
is  the  act  itself  of  willing,  and  therefore  certainly  the  power 
for  it.'2  '  It  must  be  that  when  we  will,  we  will  with  free 
will  —necesse  est  %it  cum  volumus,  libero  velimus  arbitrio.'* 

1  '  Quid  igitur  ultra  quserimus :  2  Nihil   tarn   in  nostra  potestate 

quandoquidem  hanc  dicimus  potes-  quam   ipsa  voluntas  est.     Ea  enim 

tatem,  ubi  voluntati  adjacet  facultas  prorsus  nullo  intervallo  mox  ut  vo- 

faciendi  ?     Unde  hoc  quisque  in  po-  lumus  praesto  est. — De  Lib.  Arb.  1. 

testate  habere  dicitur,  quod  si  vult  3.  c.  3. 
facit,  si  non  vult,  non  facit.' — De  *  De  Civit.  Dei,  1.  5.  c.  10. 

Spir.  et  Lit.  c.  xxxi. 


208  Augustinian  Doctrine          CHAP.  Yin. 

The  definition  of  freewill  thus  stops  at  the  fact  of  will 
as  the  ultimate  truth  beyond  which  nothing  can  be  said  ; 
the  basis  of  this  definition  of  will  being  a  particular  defini 
tion  of  power.  The  question  of  freedom  is  first  correctly 
stated  as  being  a  question  of  power  —  what  it  is  which 
constitutes  the  power  to  act  in  this  or  that  way  ;  and  the 
constitution  of  power  is  decided  by  making  the  will  a 
necessary  element  in  it.  A  distinction  is  acknowledged, 
indeed,  between  power  and  will  ;  but  a  man  is  still  not 
allowed  to  have  the  whole  power  to  do  a  thing  unless  he 
has  the  will  also  —  lit  potentate  aliquidfiat  voluntas  aderit; 
4  in  order  that  anything  may  be  done  by  power,  there  must 
be  the  will  ;'  and  will  is  a  condition  of  power  and  a  true 
ingredient  in  its  composition.  Freedom  is  thus  first  defined 
by  power,  and  power  is  then  condition  ated  upon  will,  and 
there  the  definition  stops,1  leaving  the  ultimate  test  of 
freewill,  and,  as  all  that  is  meant  by  it,  simple  will.  We 
have  freewill  or  the  power  to  will  if  ive  will. 

It  will  be  seen  that  this  definition  of  freewill  exactly 
coincides  with  Locke's,  quoted  above.  Both  writers  define 
freedom  to  be  the  power  of  doing  what  we  will  ;  Augus 
tine's  ubi  voluntati  adjacet  facultas  faciendi  just  tallying 
with  Locke's  '  How  can  we  think  any  one  freer  than  to 
have  the  power  to  do  what  he  will  ?  '  Both  writers,  applying 
this  freedom  to  the  will,  immediately  discover  the  freedom 
of  the  will  to  consist  in  willing  as  it  wills  :  Augustine  say- 
m<7,  '  Nihil  tarn  in  nostra  potestate  quam  ipsa  voluntas 
est  ;  ea  enim  prorsus  nullo  intervallo  mox  ut  volumus 
prcesto  est  :'  Locke  stating  freewill  as  '  the  man's  liberty 
to  will  which  of  the  two  things  he  pleases^  and  challenging 
any  one  to  ask  '  whether  freedom  itself  were  free.' 

Augustine  meets  the  difficulty  raised  against  the  free 
dom  of  the  will  from  the  Divine  foreknowledge  with  the 
same  answer  ;  viz.  that  as  a  matter  of  fact  we  have  will,  and 
that  will  is  as  such  free.  '  Whatever  may  be  the  tortuous 


1  A  dictum  of  S.   Anselm's,  ex-  The  will  is  the  original  supposition, 

presses  the  principle  of  it  scientifi-  on  which  the  definition  of  power  is 

cally  —  In  libcro  arbitrio  posse  non  raised. 
prcBcedit  sed  sequitur    voluntatem. 


CHAP.  vin.  of  Freewill.  209 

wrangiings  and  disputes  of  philosophers,  we,  as  we  acknow 
ledge  one  supreme  and  true  God,  so  acknowledge  His 
supreme  will,  power,  and  foreknowledge.  Nor  do  we  fear 
on  that  account  that  we  do  not  do  with  our  will  what  we 
do  with  our  will — nee  timemus  ne  ideo  non  voluntate 

faciamus,  quod  voluntate  facimus We  say  both 

that  God  knows  all  things  before  they  take  place,  and  that 
we  act  with  our  will,  inasmuch  as  we  feel  and  know  we  do 
not  act  except  with  our  will.' [ 

This,  however,  being  S.  Augustine's  definition  of  free 
will,  it  must  be  admitted  that  a  considerable  body  of  lan 
guage,  especially  his  language  at  the  commencement  of 
the  book  De  Gratia  et  Libero  Arbitrio,  and  in  the  two 
Epistles  2  relating  to  the  occasion  on  which  that  book  was 
written,  appears  at  first  sight  to  advance  upon  this  defini 
tion,  and  to  imply  an  original  and  self-determining  power 
in  the  will.  He  argues  for  freewill  as  a  doctrine  of  Scrip 
ture,  and  uses  the  common  arguments  which  the  maintainers 
of  the  ordinary  doctrine  of  freewill  use  ;  viz.  that  Scripture 
employs  commands,  promises,  and  threats,  and  speaks  to 
men  as  if  they  had  freewill.  Such  an  argument  proves  that 
he — i.e.  Scripture  as  interpreted  by  him — acknowledges  a 
will  in  man  which  is  truly  and  properly  the  subject  of  com 
mands,  promises,  and  threats ;  and  can  such  a  will,  it  may 
be  asked,  be  anything  but  a  self-determining  one  ?  Does 
not  such  a  mode  of  addressing  man  suppose  an  original 
power  of  choice  in  him  ?  But  though  this  would  be  sound 
and  correct  as  a  popular  inference  from  such  language,  it 
is  not  as  a  logical  one.  Logically  all  that  can  be  inferred 
from  the  use  of  commands  and  threats  in  the  Divine  deal 
ings  with  man  is,  that  man  has  a  capacity  for  choosing, 
obeying,  and  acting  upon  motives  3  ;  but  these  are  opera- 

1  De  Civ.  Dei,  1.  5.  c.  9.  ...  Non  sic  autem  Deus.     Semper 

2  Ep.  214,  215.  seque  determinate  vult.     Per  meri- 
8  Non   eodem    modo    se    habent       turn  innotescit  hominibus,  dsemoni- 

Deus  et  homo  ad  reddendum  prae-  bus,  et  forsitan  Angelis,  quale  prae- 

mium.     Homo    namque  sicut   Rex  mium  quis  habebit.  .  .  .  Cum  dici- 

publico  edicto  promulgat,  monetque  tur,  Deus  vult  istum  propter  merita 

ipse  indifferens  et  indeterminatus  in  praemiare,  hoc  est,  Deus  vult  istum 

voluntate  sua  circa  sibi  subjectos.  praemiare  propter  merita   finaliter 


Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vm. 

tions  of  the  will,  and  are  wholly  performed,  if  there  is  only 
a  will  to  perform  them,  without  going  into  the  question 
what  decides  that  will.  If  man  has  a  will,  which  will  is 
intended  to  act  in  the  particular  way  of  choice  and  obe 
dience,  he  must  be  addressed  in  a  manner  suitable  to  such 
a  design  ;  he  must  be  commanded,  in  order  that  he  may 
obey,  and  he  must  have  the  alternative  placed  before  him 
in  order  that  He  choose.  But  such  a  mode  of  addressing 
him  does  not  necessarily  prove  any  more  than  that  he  is 
possessed  of  a  will  to  which  those  operations  belong.  While, 
therefore,  in  the  case  of  Scripture  we  are  justified  in  taking 
such  language  to  imply  an  original  and  self-determining 
will  in  man,  because  Scripture  is  addressed  to  the  popular 
understanding,  and  this  is  the  popular  inference  to  draw 
from  such  language  ;  in  the  case  of  a  philosophical  writer 
like  Augustine, — who  treats  of  the  human  will  and  the 
questions  belonging  to  it  in  a  scientific  and  subtle  way, 
and  from  whose  language  therefore  we  are  not  justified 
in  inferring  more  than  it  logically  contains, — we  cannot 
take  it  as  implying  more  than  the  existence  of  a  will  in 
a  man. 

Indeed,  the  fact  of  a  will  is  all  the  conclusion  which  he 
himself  arrives  at  by  this  argument,  and  all  thai^  he  presses 
upon  his  readers.1  'These  commands  would  not  be  given 
unless  man  had  a  will  truly  belonging  to  him  with  which 
to  obey  them — nisi  homo  haberet  propriam  voluntatem, 
qua  divinis  prceceptis  obediret.'' — '  To  the  man  who  says  I 
cannot  do  what  is  commanded,  because  he  is  conquered  by 
concupiscence,  the  Apostle  says,  "  Will  not  to  be  overcome 
of  evil,  but  overcome  evil  with  good  ; "  will  not  to  be 
overcome — noli  vinci  implying  certainly  a  choice  of  his 
will ;  for  to  will  and  not  to  will  is  of  the  individual's  will 
— arbitrium  voluntatis  ejus  sine  dubio  convenitur,  velle 
enim  et  nolle  proprice  voluntatis  est.' — '  Freewill  is  suffi- 

ordinanda,  i.e.  vult  quod   tails  sit  denda.  .  .  .  Deusprimovulthomini 

finis   talium  meritorum    secundum  prsemium  et  gloriam  tanquam  finem, 

ordinem   ab    ipso   talibus    prsesti-  et   ideo  vult  sibi    et   facit    merita 

tutum,  ita  quod  merita  nullo  modo  congrua.' — Bradwardine,  p.  150.  et 

antecedenter,   causaliter,    a   priori,  seq. 

monent,   determinant,    vel   actuant  !  De  Grat.   et  Lib.  Arb.  c.  ii.  et 

Yoluntatem  divinam  ad  prsemia  red-  seq. 


CHAP.  vnr.  of  Freewill.  2 1  r 

ciently  proved  by  Scripture  saying,  will  not  this,  and  will 
not  that,  and  demanding  an  act  of  the  will  in  doing  or  not 
doing  anything.  Let  no  one  then  blame  God  in  his  heart, 
but  impute  it  to  himself  when  he  sins.  Nor,  when  he  does 
anything  according  to  Grod's  will,  let  him  alienate  it  from 
his  own.  For  when  he  does  it  willingly,  then  it  is  a  good 
work,  then  a  reward  attaches  to  it — quando  volens  facit 
tune  dicendum  est  opus  bonum."1  Again  on  the  text 
'  All  men  cannot  receive  this  saying,  save  they  to  whom  it 
is  given  ;'  he  says,  '  Those  to  whom  it  is  not  given  either 
will  not  or  do  not  what  they  will :  those  to  whom  it  is 
given  so  will  that  they  do  what  they  will.  That  which  is 
not  received  by  all,  but  is  received  by  some,  is  both  the 
gift  of  Grod  and  also  is  freewill — et  "Dei  donum  eat,  et 
liberum  arbitrium.'  That  is  to  say,  it  is  freewill  in  him, 
because,  from  whatever  source  it  comes,  when  he  has  it,  it 
is  his  own  will.  These  explanations  all  appeal  to  the  fact  of 
a  will  in  man,  as  being  sufficient  to  constitute  a  free  agent, 
and  a  proper  subject  of  promises  or  threats,  of  reward  or 
punishment.  Indeed,  what  these  arguments  are  designed 
to  remove  is  not  any  part  of  the  predestinarian  doctrine, 
but  only  a  false  practical  inference  from  it ;  for  the  occa 
sion  on  which  this  treatise  was  written  was,  that  certain 
persons  had  begun  to  argue,  that  if  that  doctrine  was  true, 
it  did  not  signify  what  kind  of  lives  men  led,  because  they 
were  not  responsible  for  them.  Augustine  corrects  this 
inference  by  reminding  them,  that  the  predestinarian  doc 
trine  did  not  exclude  a  will  in  man  ;  and  that  if  he  had  a 
will,  that  made  him  responsible. 

Augustine's  doctrine  of  freewill,  then,  does  not  come 
up  to  that  which  is  ordinarily  understood  as  that  doctrine ; 
not  advancing  beyond  that  point  up  to  which  the  doctrine 
of  freewill  and  the  opposite  doctrine  agree.  He  acknow 
ledges  a  will  in  man,  that  which  makes  him  act  willingly, 
as  distinguished  from  acting  by  compulsion  and  con 
straint  ;  but  this  is  saying  nothing  as  to  how  that  will  is 
determined. 

II.  But,  in  the  second  place,  we  come  to  the  question 
p  2 


212  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  TIII. 

of  the  determination  of  this  will,  and  under  this  head 
Augustine's  language  is  not  only  less  than,  but  is  opposed 
to,  the  common  doctrine  of  freewill. 

The  doctrine  of  freewill  is,  as  has  been  stated,  that  the 
will  has  a  self-determining  power,  which  produces  right 
acts  or  wrong,  according  as  it  is  exercised.  On  the  other 
hand,  the  opponents  of  the  doctrine  of  freewill  object  that 
this  is  an  absurd  and  self-contradictory  cause  to  assign  to 
human  actions ;  for  that,  if  the  power  of  acting  one  way  or 
another  be  the  cause  of  the  distinction  in  human  actions, 
— i.e.  of  the  good  or  bad  act  which  really  ensues, — the 
same  cause  can  produce  opposite  effects.  The  objection 
proceeds  on  the  assumption  that  human  actions  must  have 
a  cause  ;  which  granted,  it  follows  of  course  that  such  a 
cause  cannot  be  a  neutral  or  flexible  thing,  as  this  freewill 
or  power  of  choice  is  described  to  be. 

Now,  there  is  a  passage,  which  I  have  already  quoted,1 
in  which  the  doctrine  of  freewill,  as  thus  stated,  comes 
under  the  notice  of  Augustine.  The  doctrine  is  stated  in 
this  passage  thus  :  that  'We  have  a  power  of  taking  either 
side — possibilitas  utriusque  partis, — implanted  in  us  by 
God,  as  a  fruitful  and  productive  root,  to  produce  and 
bring  forth  according  to  men's  different  wills,  and  either 
shine  with  the  flower  of  virtue,  or  bristle  with  the  thorns 
of  vice,  according  to  the  choice  of  the  cultivator.'  This  is 
a  plain  statement  of  the  ordinary  doctrine  of  freewill. 
There  is  a  power  of  taking  either  side  inherent  in  our 
nature  ;  that  power  determines  our  wills,  and  according  as 
our  wills  are  determined  we  do  good  or  bad  actions.  To 
this  doctrine,  then,  thus  stated,  Augustine  objects  on  the 
same  ground  as  that  which  has  been  just  mentioned,  viz., 
that  it  gives  an  absurd  and  self-contradictory  cause  to 
human  actions.  Such  a  doctrine  he  says,  '  establishes  one 
and  the  same  root  of  the  good  and  the  bad, — unam 
eandemque  radicem  constituit  bonorum  et  malorum.1 
That  is,  he  says,  it  maintains  one  and  the  same  ultimate 
or  original  condition  of  the  man,  out  of  which  the  opposite 
lives  and  actions  of  the  two  issue  ;  to  maintain  which  is  to 
1  De  Gratia  Christi,  c.  18. 


CHAP.   VHI. 


of  Freewill.  2 1 3 


give  the  same  cause  to  opposite  effects.  Augustine's  argu 
ment  proceeds  on  the  supposition  of  the  necessity  of  a 
cause  for  human  actions,  and  is  substantially  the  same  ar 
gument  with  that  used  by  Edwards,  that  '  an  act  of  the 
will  cannot  directly  and  immediately  arise  out  of  a  state  of 
indifference  ;'  because  the  act  implies  '  an  antecedent  choice,' 
which  choice  cannot  be  simultaneous  with  indifference  ;]— 
the  assumption  in  this  latter  argument  being  that  actions 
must  have  a  cause  out  of  which  they  spring ;  which  cause 
can  only  be  calculated  to  produce  one  effect,  and  not  either 
one  or  the  other  of  two  effects.  The  advocates  of  freewill, 
on  the  other  hand,  do  not  admit  this  assumption,  and  so 
answer  the  argument  which  is  raised  upon  it.  They  allow 
that  this  power  of  choice  is  no  cause  of  the  determination 
of  the  will,  nor  do  they  profess  it  to  be  such  ;  but  they 
maintain  that  for  a  determination  of  the  will  one  way  or 
another,  it  is  not  necessary  to  assign  a  cause,  such  deter 
mination  being  an  original  motion  of  the  will.  It  must  be 
added,  however,  that  in  using  such  an  argument  as  this, 
Augustine  is  inconsistent,  for  he  admits  in  the  case  of  the 
first  man  this  power,  this  freewill  in  the  complete  sense, 
this  power  of  either  side  ;  appealing  to  it,  as  throwing  the 
responsibility  of  sin  upon  him,  and  removing  it  from  God ; 
after  which  admission,  he  is  properly  precluded  from  argu 
ing  upon  abstract  grounds  against  such  a,  power. 

The  power  of  choice,  as  the  account  of  the  evil  and 
good  actions  and  lives  of  men,  being  thus  set  aside,  S. 
Augustine  proceeds  to  lay  down  a  rationale  of  two  dif 
ferent  roots  or  causes  for  the  two.  '  Our  Lord  says,  that  a 
good  tree  cannot  bring  forth  evil  fruit,  nor  an  evil  tree 

1  '  If  the  act  springs  immediately  soul,  while  it  yet  remains  in  a  state 

out  of  a  state  of  indifference,  then  it  of  perfect  indifference,  chooses  to  put 

does  not  arise  from  antecedent  choice  itself  out  of  that  state  and  to  turn 

or  preference.     But  if  the  act  arises  itself  one  way,  then  the  soul  ig  al- 

directly  out  of  a  state  of  indifference,  ready  come  to  a  choice,  and  chooses 

without  any  intervening   choice  to  that  way.     And  so  the  soul  is  in  a 

determine  it,  then  the  act  not  being  state  of.  choice,  and  in  a   state  of 

determined  by  choice  is  not  deter-  equilibrium,  both  at  the  same  time.' 

mined  by  the  will.'     ...  An  ante-  — On  the  Freedom  of  the  Will,  part 

cedent  choice,  then,  he  says,  must  ii.  sect.  7. 
be  granted.     But  if  it   is,  '  if  the 


214  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  Tin. 

good  fruit.  And  the  Apostle  Paul,  when  he  says  that 
cupidity  is  the  root  of  all  evil,  intimates  also  that  love  is 
the  root  of  all  good.  If  therefore  the  two  trees  good  and 
evil  are  two  men  good  and  evil,  what  is  the  good  man  but 
the  man  of  good  will ;  that  is,  the  tree  of  good  fruit  ?  And 
what  is  the  evil  man  but  the  man  of  an  evil  will ;  that  is, 
the  tree  of  an  evil  root  ?  And  the  fruits  of  these  two  trees 
are  acts,  words,  thoughts,  which  if  good  proceed  from  a 
good  will,  and  if  evil  from  an  evil  will.  And  man  makes  a 
good  tree  when  he  receives  the  grace  of  God.  For  he  does 
not  make  himself  good  out  of  evil  by  himself ;  but  of  Him, 

and  through  Him,  and  in  Him  who  is  good And 

he  makes  an  evil  tree,  when  he  makes  himself  evil,  when 
he  departs  from  immutable  good ;  for  the  origin  of  an  evil 
will  is  that  departure.' l  In  this  passage  the  lives  and  ac 
tions  of  the  good  and  evil  man  are  referred  in  the  first 
place  to  two  immediate  or  proximate  roots,  and  then  to 
two  ultimate  or  original  ones.  The  proximate  roots  of 
the  two  respectively  are  a  good  and  evil  will,  which  he  calls 
also  love  and  cupidity.  The  original  roots,  or  those  from 
which  this  good  and  evil  will  themselves  spring,  are  grace 
and  sin.  (  Man  makes  a  good  tree  or  root,  [tree  and  root 
being  synonymous  here]  when  he  receives  the  grace  of 
God  ;  for  he  does  not  make  himself  good  by  himself,  but  of 

1  Habemus  autem,  inquit,  possi-  bona  et  mala  sunt,  duo    homines, 

bilitatem  utriusque  partis  a  Deo  in-  bonus    et    malus,    quid    est   bonus 

sitam,  velut  quandam,  ut  ita  dicam,  homo,  nisi  voluntatis  bonse,  hoc  est 

radicem  fructiferam  atque  fecxindam  arbor    radicis  bonse?    et  quid    est 

quse  ex  voluntate  hominis  diversa  homo  malus,  nisi  voluntatis  malse, 

gignat   et  pariat,  et  quse   possit  ad  hsec  est  arbor  radicis  malse  ?    Fruc- 

proprii  cultoris  arbitrium,  vel  nitere  tus  autem    harum    radicum    atque 

flore  virtutum,  vel  sentibus  horrere  arborum    facta    sunt,    dicta    sunt, 

vitiorum.     Ubi   non    intuens  quod  cogitata  sunt,  quse  bona   de    bona 

loquatur,  unam  eandemque  radicem  voluntate    procedunt,    et    mala   de 

constituit  bonorum  et  malorum,  con-  mala.     Facit  autem  homo  arborem 

tra  evangelicam    veritatem   doctri-  bonam,  quando  Dei  accipit  gratiam. 

namque  apostolicam.     Nam  et  Do-  Non  autem   se  ex  malo  bonum  per 

minus    nee    arborem   bonam   dicit  seipsum  facit,  sed  in  illo  et  per  ilium, 

posse  facere  fructus  malos,  nee  ma-  et  in  illo  qui  semper  est  bonus.  .  . 

lam  bpnos;    et    Apostolus    Paulus  Malam  vero   arborem   facit  quando 

cum  dicit  radicem  malorum  omnium  seipsum    malum    facit,    quando    a 

esse   cupiditatem,  admonet    utique  bono  immutabili  deficit. — De  Gratia 

intelligi  radicem  bonorum  omnium  Christi,  c.  18,  19. 
charitatem.     Unde  si  duae  arbores 


CHAP.   Till. 


of  Freewill.  2 1 5 


Him : '  that  is,  his  own  preparation  of  his  will,  by  which  he 
makes  it  a  good  will,  is  itself  derived  from  grace  ;  man  is 
the  immediate,  but  grace  the  original  agent.  On  the  other 
hand,  '  Man  makes  an  evil  tree  or  root  when  he  makes 
himself  evil,  and  departs  from  immutable  good,'  as  he  did 
by  his  transgression  in  Paradise,  for  so  the  general  doctrine 
of  Augustine  interprets  this  allusion.  A  rationale  of  two 
different  roots  or  causes  of  the  lives  of  good  and  evil  men 
is  thus  laid  down,  in  the  place  of  one  and  the  same  moral 
condition  out  of  which  they  are  supposed  to  arise  on  the 
doctrine  of  freewill. 

The  same  argument  is  repeated  in  a  passage  from  the 
book  De  Peccatorum  Meritis  et  Remissione :  '  It  is  strange 
if  the  will  can  stand  at  a  certain  point  midway,  so  as  to  be 
neither  good  nor  bad — voluntas  mirum  si  potest  in  medio 
quodam  ita  consistere,  ut  nee  bona  nee  mala  sit.  For 
either  we  love  righteousness,  and  it  is  good,  or  we  do  not 
love  righteousness,  and  it  is  bad ;  the  bad  will  not  coming 
from  God,  the  good  one  coming  from  God,  and  being  the 
gift  whereby  we  are  justified  ...  a  gift  which  to  whomso 
ever  God  gives  it,  He  gives  in  His  mercy,  and  from  whom 
soever  He  withholds  it,  He  withholds  it  in  His  judgment 
...  for  the  law  of  His  secret  justice  rests  with  Him  alone.' x 
The  writer  here  refuses  to  comprehend  a  neutral,  and 
simply  determinable  will,  and,  setting  aside  such  a  ra 
tionale  of  human  conduct,  lays  down  two  separate  wills, 
good  and  bad,  which  have  each  possession  of  the  agent 
prior  to  all  action. 

These  two  distinct  wills,  or  roots  or  causes  of  human 
action,  then,  are,  as  has  already  appeared,  and  as  the  whole 
doctrine  of  Augustine  shows,  original  sin  and  grace. 

I.  The  will  of  fallen  man  is  determined  to  evil  by  a 
cause  out  of  and  beyond  the  personal  will  or  the  will  of 
the  individual ;  i.e.  by  the  transgression  of  the  first  man, 
or  original  sin ;  which  captive  will,  however,  is,  notwith 
standing,  freewill,  for  the  following  reasons. 

In  the  first  place,  Augustine  defends  its  freedom  upon 
the  simple  ground  which  has  been  maintained.  In  reply 

1  De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Kern.  1.  2.  c.  18. 


216  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP,  vm, 

to  the  Pelagian,  who  presses  him  continually  with  the  con 
sequences  of  his  doctrine,  and  asks  how  a  being,  who  is 
literally  unable  to  turn  to  good  from  the  moment  of  his 
birth,  can  be  treated  as  a  free  agent  and  responsible  for 
his  acts,  he  answers  simply  that  he  is  so,  inasmuch  as  he 
has  a  will.  He  does  what  he  does  with  his  will,  and  not 
against  it.  No  force  has  compelled  him  to  act  contrary  to 
his  inclination,  but  he  has  acted  according  to  his  inclina 
tion.  He  has  therefore  acted  as  a  free  agent,  and  he  is 
responsible  for  his  acts.  What  more  is  wanted  for  respon 
sibility  than  that  a  man  has  acted  willingly,  and  without 
constraint?  'Why  perplex  a  very  plain  subject.  He  is 
free  for  evil  (i.e.  a  free  agent  in  doing  evil)  who  acts  with 
an  evil  will.  He  is  free  for  good  (i.e.  a  free  agent  in  doing 
good)  who  acts  with  a  good  will.' l — 'Men  are  not  forced 
by  the  necessity  of  the  flesh  into  sin,  as  if  they  were  un 
willing  (quasi  inviti) ;  but  if  they  are  of  an  age  to  use 
their  own  choice,  they  are  both  retained  in  sin  by  their  will, 
and  precipitated  from  one  sin  to  another  by  their  will.  For 
he  who  persuades  and  deceives  them  does  not  work  anything 
in  them,  but  that  they  sin  with  their  will.2 ' — '  The  will  is 
that  with  which  we  sin,  and  with  which  we  live  well — 
voluntas  est  qua  et  peccatur  et  recte  vivitur.' 3  It  is 
enough  for  freedom,  according  to  these  statements,  if  we 
sin  by  or  with  the  consent  of  our  will. 

Another  answer  to  this  difficulty  is  more  subtle  and 
intricate.  The  sin  of  our  nature  is  voluntary,  and  men  are 
responsible  for  it,  because  this  sin  proceeds  from  a  self- 
determining  human  will  in  the  first  instance  ;  the  sin  of 
the  first  man  or  the  original  sin  having  been  committed 

1  Quid  aperta  implicas  loquacitate  bitrio  ,  et  in  peccato  sua  voluntatc 

perplexa?     Ad  malum  liber  est,  qui  retinentur,  et  a  peccato  in  peccatum 

voluntate  agit  mala  :  ad  bonum  au-  sua  voluntate  prsecipitantur.    Neque 

tern    liber   est   qui    voluntate  agit  enim  agit  in  eis  qui  suadet  et  decipit, 

bona.— Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  120.  nisi  ut  peccatum  voluntate  commit- 

1  '  Non  itaque,    sicut  dicunt  nos  tant.' — Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  I.e.  3. 
quidem  dicere,  et  iste  audet  insuper  '  Liberum  arbitrium   usque  adeo 

scribere,  "  omnes  in  peccatum,  velut  in  peccatore  non  periit,  ut  per  illud 

inviti,    carnis   suse   necessitate   co-  peccent,    maxime   omnes   qui    cum 

guntur:"  sed,  si  jam  in  ea  setate  delectatione peccant.' — Ibid.  1.  I.e.  2. 
guut  ut  proprise  mentis  utantur  ar-  8  Ketract.  1.  I.e.  9. 


CHAP.    VHl. 


of  Freewill.  2 1 7 


when  man  had  a  self-determining  will.  The  root  or  origin, 
therefore,  of  sin  is  entirely  free,  and  it  must  be  judged  by 
its  root  or  origin.  Subsequently,  indeed,  to  its  origin,  sin 
becomes  not  free  in  this  sense,  but  necessary,  and  our  nature 
is  captive  to  it :  but  this  does  not  undo  the  freedom  of  its 
origin.  '  Sin  cannot  be  without  the  will,  in  the  same  way 
in  which  we  say  that  the  fruit  cannot  be  without  the  root. 
.  .  .  Without  the  will  of  him  (Adam)  from  whom  is  the 
origin  of  all  that  live,  the  original  sin  was  not  committed. 
But  the  contagion  of  it  could  pass  to  others  without  the 
will.  It  must  exist  with  the  will,  in  order  that  it  might 
pass  to  others  without  the  will,  as  a  tree  must  have  a  root 
below,  in  order  that  it  may  be  above  without  a  root.  .  .  . 
Sin  is  both  with  the  will  and  without  the  will :  it  is  with 
the  will  in  so  far  as  it  must  begin  to  be  with  it ;  it  is  with 
out  the  will  in  so  far  as  it  remains  without  it.' *  When  it 
is  said  in  this  passage  that  sin  remains  without  the  will,  it 
is  not  of  course  meant  that  it  remains  apart  from  all  will 
whatever,  for  some  kind  of  will  must  go  along  with  a  sinful 
act  to  make  it  the  man's  act ;  but  will  is  here  used  in  the 
highest  sense  as  a  self-determining  will,  such  a  will  as  the 
first  man  in  his  perfect  state  had.  The  meaning  of  this 
passage,  then,  is  this  :  that  sin  began  in  a  self-determining 
will ;  and  that,  therefore,  though  when  once  existing,  it 
remains  in  the  human  race  without  such  a  will,  it  ever 
carries  about  with  it  the  freedom  and  responsibility  of  its 
commencement.  The  human  will  is  viewed  as  one  stream 
of  will,  so  to  call  it,  flowing  first  from  a  fountain  head  in 
the  will  of  the  first  man,  as  he  came  from  the  hands  of  his 
Creator,  undergoing  a  change  of  its  powers  and  condition  at 
the  fall,  and  with  that  internal  change  passing  into  all  the 
individual  members  of  the  human  race,  as  they  are  succes- 

1  Ego  sic  dixi  peccatum  sine  vo-  alia  loca    transire    sine     radicibus 

luntate   esse    non    posse,  quoraodo  possent.  .    .    .  Sine   voluntate   non 

dicimus   poma    vel   frumenta    sine  potest  esse,  nam  sine  voluntate  non 

radicibus  esse  non  posse.  .  .   .  Sine  potrst   existere  ut  sit ;  sine  autem 

voluntate  esse  non  posset,  ut  esset  voluntate  potest  esse,  quia  sine  vo- 

quod  in   alios  sine  voluntate  tran-  luntate  potest  manere  quod  existit. 

siret ;  sicut  frumenta  sine  radicibus  — Op.  Imp.  1.  4.  cc.  97.  99. 
esse  non  possent,  ut  essent  quae  in 


218  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vnr. 

sively  born.  At  its  fountain  head  this  will  is  self-deter 
mining  and  free  in  the  complete  sense ;  but  at  the  fall 
it  loses  this  freedom,  and  receives  into  itself  an  inclination 
to  evil,  which  operates  necessarily.  Thus  biassed,  it  passes 
into  the  successive  generations  of  individual  men,  as  they 
are  born,  constituting  them  sinful  beings,  and  issuing  in 
sinful  desires  and  acts.  If  mankind  complain,  then,  of  this 
captive  condition,  and  ask  why,  when  their  will  acts  under 
a  necessity  they  are  treated  as  free  and  responsible  beings 
subject  to  punishment  for  their  acts,  they  are  told  that 
their  will  was  originally  free  and  self-determining ;  that  it 
only  lost  that  power  by  its  own  fault ;  and  that  a  loss  which 
it  has  brought  upon  itself  does  not  give  it  immunity.  An 
analogy  is  instituted  between  the  effect  of  original  sin 
upon  the  will,  and  the  effect  of  habit  or  custom.  The  will 
of  the  man  who  is  born  under  the  influence  of  original  sin 
is  treated  as  identical  with  the  will  which  committed  that 
sin ;  just  as  the  will  of  an  individual  who  is  under  the 
force  of  a  bad  habit  is  identical  with  the  will  which  con 
tracted  that  habit.  And  this  view  accounts  for  an  apparent 
contradiction  which  we  meet  with  in  Augustine,  in  speaking 
of  the  will.  He  talks  of  will  as  being  essentially  original 
and  the  cause  of  itself,  or  self-determining ;  being  this,  as 
being  will l ;  and  he  also  speaks  of  will  as  if  the  fact  of  a 
will,  whatever  were  its  cause,  made  a  true  and  genuine  will. 
He  is  first  speaking  of  will  as  a  whole,  and  secondly  of  will 
in  a  particular  stage.  Will  as  a  whole  must  be  original 
and  self-determining  ;  that  is,  there  must  have  been  a 
time  in  the  history  of  the  will  when  it  was  so  :  otherwise 
we  make  sin  simply  necessary  in  the  world,  and  fasten  its 
authorship  on  the  Deity.  But  will  in  a  particular  stage  or 
condition  may  be  the  conscious  fact  of  willing,  and  no 
more,  acting  really  under  a  necessity.  Such  an  explanation, 
however,  is  wholly  mystical. 

II.  The  will  of  man  is  determined  to  good  by  grace, 
and  yet  it  is  freewill ;  just  as  his  will,  when  so  determined 
by  original  sin  to  evil,  was  free :  because  it  is  true  will ; 

1  P.  206. 


CHAP  vin.  of  Freewill.  219 

because  the  man  acts  willingly  and  without  constraint. 
'  The  human  will  is  not  taken  away,  but  is  changed  from 
evil  to  good  by  grace — voluntas  humana  non  tollitur,  sed 
ex  mala  mutatur  in  bonamS  ! — '  Freewill  is  one  of  the 
gifts  of  Grod  ;  not  only  itself  but  the  goodness  of  it — non 
tantum  ut  sit  sed  etiam  ut  bonum  sit.' 2 — '  It  is  certain 
that  when  we  will,  we  will ;  but  it  is  He  who  makes  us  to 
will — certum  est  nos  velle  cum  volumus,  sed  ille  facit  ut 
velimus  bonum.  It  is  certain  that  when  we  do  we  do ; 
but  He  makes  us  to  do,  by  giving  the  most  effective  strength 
to  the  will — cerium  est  nos  facer e  cum  facimus,  sed  ille 
facit  ut  faciamus,  prcebendo  vires  efficacissimas  volun- 
tati.' 3 — '  Some  will  to  believe,  others  do  not ;  because  the 
will  of  some  is  prepared  by  God,  the  will  of  others  is  not 
— aliis  prceparatur  aliis  non  prceparatur  voluntas  a 

Domino Mercy  and  justice  have  been  respectively 

exerted  in  the  very  wills  of  men — misericordia  et  judi- 
cium  in  ipsis  voluntatibus  facia  sunt.' 4  That  is  to  say, 
the  will  is  moved  and  determined  by  Divine  grace,  but  it 
is  still  will,  and  freewill. 

A  higher  sense,  however,  than  that  of  freedom  from 
constraint  and  force,  or  simple  willingness,  though  at  the 
same  time  including  this  latter  sense,  is  sometimes  given 
to  the  term  freewill ;  viz.,  that  of  freedom  from  the  yoke 
and  bondage  of  sin,  the  dominion  of  evil  inclinations  and 
passions.  The  term  freedom  is  raised  from  its  neutrality 
and  appropriated  to  a  good  condition  of  the  will ;  such 
condition  being  still,  however,  not  freedom  in  the  sense  of 
power  of  choice,  but  a  state  of  servitude  to  good, — the 
contradictory  of  servitude  to  evil. 

S.  Paul  speaks  of  two  bondages,  a  bondage  to  righte 
ousness  and  a  bondage  to  sin  ;  and  of  two  freedoms,  a  free 
dom  from  righteousness  and  a  freedom  from  sin.  And 
S.  Augustine,  following  him,  says  :  '  The  will  is  always  free 
in  us,  but  not  always  good;  for  either  it  is  free  from 
righteousness,  and  under  bondage  to  sin,  or  it  is  free  from 

1  De  Grati4  et  Lib.  Arb.  n.  41.  s  De  Gratia  et  Lib.  Arb.  n.  32. 

2  De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Kern.  1.  2.  4  De  Prsed.  Sanct.  c.  6. 
c.  6. 


220  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vm. 

sin,  and  under  bondage  to  righteousness.' l  Here  the  term 
free  is  evidently  used  not  in  the  sense  of  free  for  evil  or 
good,  i.e.  with  the  power  of  doing  either;  but  as  meaning 
free  from  evil,  and  free  from  good.  There  is  a  state  of 
mind  in  which  the  good  principle  is  dominant  and  supreme, 
and  the  man  in  entire  subjection  to  it  or  under  its  yoke ; 
a  state  of  mind  in  which  the  will  has  reached  such  a  point 
of  strength  on  the  good  side,  as  that  the  man  could  not 
act  against  it,  without  such  a  violence  as  it  would  be  ab 
surd  to  suppose  him  committing  toward  himself.  There 
is  a  state  of  mind  also  in  which  evil  has  this  dominance 
and  supremacy.  Freewill  is  here  understood  as  will,  which 
is  either  free  from  this  yoke  of  good,  or  free  from  this  yoke 
of  evil.  In  this  sense  of  the  word  free,  then,  the  freedom 
of  the  will  is  inconsistent  with  a  power  of  choice ;  for, 
according  to  this  use  of  the  term,  a  freewill,  so  far  from 
having  ability  to  do  evil  or  good,  has  its  very  name,  be 
cause  it  is  either  not  able  to  do  evil  on  the  one  hand,  or 
not  able  to  do  good  on  the  other.  It  is  not  a  will  which 
has  yet  to  make  its  choice,  but  which  is  already  determined, 
and  is  an  acting  will  on  one  side  or  the  other.  Nor  has 
such  a  freewill  arisen  in  the  first  instance  by  a  power  of 
choice,  because  such  a  freewill  there  has  always  been  on 
the  evil  side  or  the  good  ;  '  the  will  is  always  free  in  us,' 
i.e.  is  always  in  one  of  these  states  of  freedom  or  the  other. 
Were  the  change  from  the  bondage  of  evil,  of  which  Angus- 
tine  speaks,  a  change  from  this  bondage  to  evil  to  a  power 
of  choosing  evil  or  good  (and  this  is  what  on  the  common 
doctrine  of  freewill  is  understood  by  the  freedom  of  grace 
as  distinguished  from  the  bondage  of  nature),  a  power  of 
choice  in  the  will  would  then  come  in.  But  this  change 
is  simply  an  exchange  of  one  bondage  for  another, — a 

1  'Semper  est  in  nobis  voluntas  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.  n.  31. 
libera,   sed   non    semper  est  bona,  '  Liberum  arbitrium  et  ad  malum 

Aut  enim  a  justitia  libera  est,  quan-  et  ad  bonum  faciendum  confitendum 

do  servit  peccato,  et  tune  est  mala :  est  nos  habere  :  sed  in  malo  faciendo 

aut  a  peccato  libera  est,  quando  ser-  liber  est  quisque  justitige  eervusque 

vit  justitise,  et  tune  est  bona.  Gratia  peccati ;  in    bono    autem    liber  est 

vero  Dei  semper  est   bona,  et  per  nullus,  nisi  fuerit  liberatus  ab  illo.' 

hanc  fit  ut  sit  homo  bonse  voluntatis,  — De  Corr.  et  Grat.  n.  2. 
qui  prius  fait  voluntatis  malse.'— De 


CHAP.  viir.  of  Freewill.  221 

bondage  to  good  for  a  bondage  to  evil;  and,  therefore, 
there  is  no  room  for  the  introduction  of  this  power. 

A  state  of  bondage  to  righteousness,  then,  or  a  state 
in  which  the  will  is  necessarily  good,  is,  according  to  this 
scheme,  a  state  of  freewill ;  only  as  yet  it  has  that  name 
in  common  with  the  corresponding  state  on  the  side  of 
evil.  S.  Paul  uses  the  terms  bondage  and  freedom,  instead 
of  in  a  respectively  favourable  and  unfavourable  sense,  in 
a  neutral  one ;  and  S.  Augustine  follows  him.  But  the 
application  of  the  term  is  afterwards  restricted  and  appro 
priated  to  the  good  side ;  and  the  good  state  of  the  will  is 
called  the  freedom,  in  contrast  with  the  other,  which  is 
called  the  slavery  of  the  will.1 

It  appears,  then,  upon  a  general  examination  of  the 
language  of  Augustine  respecting  freewill,  first,  that  it 
does  not  come  up  to  that  which  we  call  the  doctrine  of 
freewill,  not  going  beyond  that  simple  acknowledgment  of 
a  will  in  which  that  doctrine  and  its  opposite  agree ;  and, 
secondly,  that  it  is  opposed  to  that  doctrine,  his  language 
being  that  the  will  has,  notwithstanding  its  freedom,  no 
&elf-determining  power,  but  is  determined  to  evil  and  to 
good  respectively  by  original  sin  and  by  grace. 

It  is  true,  indeed,  that  language  of  an  apparently 
opposite  kind  to  this  is  to  be  found  occasionally  in  S. 
Augustine ;  but  when  such  language  is  examined,  it  will 
be  found  to  be  only  verbally  opposite  to,  and  really  in 
harmony  with,  the  doctrine  which  has  been  exhibited. 
S.  Augustine  uniformly  indeed  holds  a  co-operation  of 
the  human  will  with  Divine  grace,  and  co-operation  seems 
to  imply  two  original  agencies  meeting  and  uniting  in 
the  same  work  ;  but  on  examination  we  find  that  the  term, 
in  S.  Augustine's  use  of  it,  does  not  imply  this.  The 
co-operation  of  the  human  will  with  Divine  grace  only 
commences,  according  to  S.  Augustine,  after  the  human 
will  has  undergone  that  whole  process  which  has  been  just 
described;  that  is  to  say,  after  it  has  been  moved  by 
the  sole  action  of  Divine  grace  into  a  state  of  efficiency. 

1  '  In  tantum  libera  est  (voluntas)       nante  cupiditate).' — Eetract.    1.    1. 
in  quantum  liberata   est   (a   domi-       c.  15. 


222  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vnr. 

'  He  works  in  us  that  we  will,  and  that  is  the  beginning, 
He  co-operates  with  us  when  we  will,  and  that  is  the  per 
fecting,  of  the  work.  Being  confident  of  this  very  thing, 
says  the  Apostle,  that  He  which  hath  begun  a  good  work 
in  you  will  perfect  it  until  the  day  of  Jesus  Christ.  That 
we  will,  therefore  He  works  in  us  without  us ;  and  when 
we  will,  and  so  will  that  we  do,  He  co-operates  with  us— 
ut  ergo  velimus  sine  nobis  operatur,  cum  autem  volumus 
et  sic  volumus  ut  faciamus,  nobiscum  operatur.  And  we 
can  do  no  good  works  of  piety  without  Him  first  operating 
that  we  will,  and  then  co-operating  with  us  when  we  will. 
Of  (rod  operating  that  we  will  it  is  said,  "  It  is  God  that 
worketh  in  us  to  will."  Of  (rod  co-operating  with  us  when 
we  will,  and  so  will  that  we  do,  it  is  said,  "  We  know  that 
all  things  work  together  for  good  to  them  that  love  God." '  * 
The  condition  of  the  human  will  is  here  divided  into  two 
stages,  in  the  former  of  which  God  simply  operates  upon 
it,  in  the  latter  co-operates  with  it.  The  former  stage 
lasts  till  the  will  is  effective,  till  we  will  and  so  will  that 
we  do ;  that  point  attained  the  latter  stage  commences, 
and  God  co-operates  with  this  will,  and  this  will  co 
operates  with  Him.  It  is  evident  from  the  very  terms  of 
this  division  what  the  nature  of  this  co-operating  human 
will  is ;  that  it  is  not  an  original  agent,  but  a  will  that  has 
been  made  to  be  what  it  is  by  grace  wholly.  That  such 
a  will  co-operates  with  grace  is  no  more  than  to  say,  that 
grace  co-operates  with  grace ;  for  that  which  the  pure 
effect  does,  the  cause  does  really  and  properly.  Grace  is 
the  original,  the  will  is  only  an  instrumental  co-operator. 
The  dictum  '  Gratia  ipsa  meretur  auger  i,  ut  aucta  merea- 
tur  perficij  expresses  the  same  doctrine,  making  the  simple 
bestowal  of  grace  the  reason  of  its  farther  bestowal,  so  that 
grace  is  its  own  augmenter,  and  increases  upon  an  internal 
law  of  growth. 

It  is  such  a  mode  of  co-operation  as  this  which  the 
following  passage  describes :  c  It  is  plain  that  human 
righteousness,  although  it  is  not  done  without  the  human 
will,  is  to  be  attributed  to  the  operation  of  the  Divine, 

1  De  Grat.  et  Lib.  Arb.  c.  xvii. 


CHAP.  VIII. 


of  Freewill.  22, 


which  is  the  reason  we  cannot  deny  that  the  perfection  of 
that  righteousness  is  possible  even  in  this  life ;  because  all 
things  are  possible  to  God,  both  what  He  does  when  His 
own  will  solely  operates,  and  what  He  does  when  the  wills 
of  His  creatures  operate  with  Him — sive  qucc  facit  sola 
sua  voluntate,  swe,  quce  co-op  erantibus  creaturce  succ 
voluntatibus,  a  se  fieri  posse  constitute?  *  Here  is  a  co 
operation  mentioned  of  the  human  will  with  the  Divine, 
but  it  is  a  co-operation  subordinated  to  an  absolute  power 
in  the  Divine  will.  Whatever  therefore  such  co-operation 
in  the  human  will  involves,  it  does  not  involve  any  de 
pendence  of  the  issue  upon  it,  inasmuch  as  such  issue  is 
secured  by  the  absolute  power  of  the  Divine  will  to  pro 
duce  it.  The  power  is  on  one  side,  the  co-operation  on 
another;  co-operation  abstracted  from  power  is  instru 
mental  co-operation. 

The  same  mode  of  co-operation  is  described  in  the 
following  extract :  '  When  God  wills  the  salvation  of  a 
man,  no  will  of  man  resists  Him.  For  to  will  or  not  to 
will  is  in  the  power  of  the  willing  or  unwilling  man  in  such 
sense  only  that  it  does  not  impede  the  Divine  will  or  frus 
trate  the  Divine  power — sic  enim  velle  seu  nolle  in  volen- 
tis  aut  nolentis  est  potestate.,  ui  Divinam  voluntatem  non 
impediat,  nee  super  et  potestatem.' 2  Here  it  is  said  that 
in  a  particular  sense  a  man's  will  is  in  his  own  power,  and 
were  the  sense  in  which  this  were  allowed  a  free  and 
natural  one,  nothing  more  would  be  wanted  for  a  testimony 
on  the  side  of  freewill.  But  we  see  at  once  that  it  is  any 
thing  but  a  free  and  natural  sense  in  which  this  power  is 
conceded ;  for  it  is  conceded  under  the  salvo,  that  this 
power  does  not  interfere  with  the  natural  operation  of 
another  power,  which  other  power  is  absolute.  But  what 
is  power  which  is  itself  the  subject  of  absolute  power? 
Had  S.  Augustine  wished  to  admit  a  real  power  in  the 
human  will,  there  are  many  plain  and  simple  modes  in 
which  he  might  have  done  it,  as  a  common  language  in 
theology,  both  ancient  and  modern,  on  this  subject  shows. 
But  he  only  admits  a  power  which  is  negatived  by  an  entire 
1  De  Lit.  et  Spirit,  c.  5  2  De  Corr.  et  Grat.  c.  xiv. 


224  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vm. 

subordination  to  another  power ;  and  a  will  with  such  a 
negatived  power  over  itself  is  not  an  original  but  an  in 
strumental  co-operator  with  the  Divine  will. 

One  passage,  however,  has  attracted  remarkable  atten 
tion,  in  consequence  of  one  particular  phrase,  contained 
in  it,  appearing  at  first  to  involve  very  decidedly  the  posi 
tion  of  a  self-determining  will :  '  If  it  be  said  that  we  must 
beware  of  interpreting  the  text,  "  What  hast  thou  which 
thou  hast  not  received  ?  "  of  the  believing  will,  and  assert 
ing,  because  this  proceeds  from  a  freewill  which  was  a 
Divine  gift  at  our  creation,  that  therefore  it  is  itself  a 
Divine  gift,  lest  we  attribute  to  God  the  authorship  of  sin 
as  well ; — I  say,  that  a  believing  will  is  not  to  be  attributed 
to  God  solely  because  it  proceeds  from  freewill,  but  because 
it  depends  upon  the  Divine  persuasion,  either  external  or 
internal ;  though  it  belongs  to  the  individual's  will  to  agree 
with  or  dissent  from  this  persuasion.  God's  mercy  always 
anticipates  us,  and  He  works  in  man  the  will  to  believe ; 
but  to  assent  to  or  dissent  from  the  Divine  will  belongs  to 
the  individual  will.  Nor  does  this  at  all  contradict  the 
text,  "  What  hast  thou  which  thou  hast  not  received  ?  " 
but  rather  confirms  it.  The  soul  cannot  receive  these 
gifts  without  consenting ;  because,  what  it  has  and  what 
it  receives  is  from  God  :  to  have  and  receive  belongs  to  a 
possessor  and  receiver.'  He  then  decides  why  this  Divine 
persuasion,  to  which  this  assent  of  the  will  is  necessary,  is 
effectual  with  some,  and  not  with  others,  and  decides  it  by 
a  reference  to  the  inscrutable  will  of  God.1 

1  '  Si  autem  respondetur,  caven-  secus,  per  evangelicas  exhortationes 

dum  esse  ne  quisquam   Deo  tribu-  .  .  sive  intresecus,  ubinemohabetin 

endum  putet  peccatum,  quod  admit-  potestate  quid  ei  veniat,  in  mentem, 

titur  per  liberum  arbitrium,  si  in  eo  sed  consentire  vel  dissentlre  propriee 

quod  dicitur,  "  Quid  habes  quod  non  voluntatisest.  His  ergo  modi squando 

accepisti  ?  "  propterea  etiam  voluntas  Deus  agit  cum  anima  rationali,  ut  ei 

qua  credimus    dono  Dei   tribuitur,  credat  (neque  enim  credere  potest 

quia  de  libero  existit  arbitrio,  quod  quodlibet  libero  arbitrio  si  nulla  sit 

cum  crearemur  accepimus  ;  attendat  suasio  vel  vocatio  cui  credat)  profecto 

et  yideat,  non  ideo,  quia  ex  libero  et  ipsum  velle  credere  Deus   ope- 

arbitrio  est,  quod  nobis  naturaliter  ratur  inhomine,  etin  omnibus  mise- 

concreatum  est ;  verum  etiam  quod  ricordia  ejus  prsevenit  nos :  consen- 

visorum  suasionibus   agit  Deus,   ut  tire  autem  vocationi  Dei,  vel  ab  ea 

velimus  et  ut  credamus,  sive  extrin-  dissentire,  sicut  dixi,  proprice  volun- 


CHAP.  vni.  of  Freewill.  225 

We  have,  then,  in  this  passage  the  expression,  <  assentire 
vel  dissentire  proprice  voluntatis  est ; '  and  this  expres 
sion  seems  at  first  sight  to  involve  a  self-determining  will. 
But  it  will  be  seen,  that  in  the  course  of  the  statement  it 
receives  a  different  explanation.  In  this  passage  S.  Augus 
tine  is  discussing  the  question,  whether  the  will  to  believe 
is  given  by  Grod ;  and  he  answers,  first,  that  it  is  given  by 
God  because  it  arises  out  of  that  freewill  which  was  given 
to  man  at  his  creation.  But  then  he  remarks,  that  this 
answer  is  not  enough,  because  sin  also  arises  out  of  free 
will,  and  sin  is  not  the  gift  of  (rod.  What  is  the  difference, 
then,  he  asks,  in  the  mode  in  which  they  respectively  arise, 
which  makes  one  the  gift  of  God,  and  the  other  not  ?  He 
decides  that  this  difference  lies  in  a  certain  calling  or  per 
suading  on  the  part  of  God,  which  is  necessary  in  order  to 
produce  the  believing  will — neque  enim  credere  potest 
quodlibet  libero  arbitrio,  si  nulla  sit  suasio  vel  vocatio 
cui  credat.  And  to  this  calling  and  persuasion  the  natural 
will  has  to  consent,  in  order  for  it  to  be  effectual ;  for  that 
'assenting  or  dissenting  belongs  to  the  natural  will — 
consentire  vocationi  Dei  vel  ab  ea  dissentire  proprice 
voluntatis  est.'  The  believing  will,  then,  is  a  Divine  gift, 
inasmuch  as  it  is  the  result  of  a  Divine  calling  with  which 
the  human  will  agrees.  But  then  the  question  imme 
diately  arises,  whether  this  is  not  a  compromise  which 
really  gives  up  the  whole  point,  and  makes  the  believing 
will  not  a  gift  which  man  receives  simply,  but  something 
which  he  acquires  by  an  act  of  his  own.  And  to  that  he 
replies,  that  it  is  not,  because  consent  is  only  the  necessary 
mode  in  which  the  will  receives  a  gift :  consent  being,  in 
fact,  nothing  but  the  act  itself  of  receiving ;  so  that  to 
say  that  the  will  must  consent  in  order  to  receive,  is 

tatis  est.     Quae  res  non  solum  non  tis  est.    Jam  si  ad  illam  profundi- 

infirmat  quod   dictum  est,     "  Quid  tatem    scrutandam    quisquam   nos 

habes  quod  non  accepisti  ?  "  verum  coarctet,  cur  illi  ita  suadeatur    ut 

etiam  confirmat.     Accipere  quidem  persuadeatur  illi  autem    non    ita: 

et  habere  anima  non  potest  dona,  duo   sola    occurrunt   interim     quae 

de  quibus  hoc  audit,  nisi  consenti-  respondere  mihi  placeat  "  0  altitude 

endo  :  ac  per   hoc  quid  habeat   et  divitiarum  "  et  "  Numquid  iniquitas 

quid  accipiat,  Dei  est ;  accipere  au-  apud    Deum  ?  "  '  —  De    Spiritu    et 

tern  et  habere,  accipientis  et  haben-  Litera,  1.  1.  n.  60. 


226  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  Yin. 

nothing  more  than  to  say  that  the  will  must  receive  when 
it  receives — accipere  et  habere  utique  accipientis  et  haben- 
tis  est.  The  believing  will  thus  comes  out,  after  due  ex 
planation,  a  simple  gift,  to  which  the  only  consent  is  one 
which  is  involved  in  the  "mere  fact  of  it  being  given;  viz. 
reception  and  possession.  And,  lastly,  why  one  man  has 
this  gift,  and  another  not,  is  explained  by  a  simple  appeal 
to  mystery. 

Any  one  who  carefully  examines  this  passage  will  see 
that  the  explanation  here  given  of  it  is  the  only  one  by 
which  a  consistent  meaning  is  secured  for  it  throughout. 
A  phrase  apparently  owning  an  original  power  in  the 
human  will  to  accept  or  reject  the  Divine  operation  upon 
it,  is  admitted  ;  but  as  soon  as  it  has  been  admitted  it  is 
explained  in  a  particular  way,  and  reduced  into  entire 
harmony  with  a  theory  of  omnipotent  grace,  resting  upon 
a  basis  of  mystery.1 

To  sum  up  in  one  distinction  the  general  argument  of 
this  chapter,  the  Augustinian  doctrine  of  freewill  may  be 
said  in  a  word  to  describe  the  nature  of  freewill  as  being 
a  mode  of  action,  not  a  source  of  action — taking  source  in 
its  proper  sense  as  an  original  source.  The  mode  of  human 

1  Jansen  (De  Gratia  Christi,  pp.  of  Augustinian  election  as  ex  prce- 
220,225,  908,  936,955,980,  989)  visis  operibus  (p.  989) :  and  his  and 
properly  explains  various  passages  Molini's  explanation  of  gratia  effi- 
of  Augustine  from  which  the  Jesuits  cax,  as  efficacious  si  voluntas  cum  ca 
Bellarmine.Suarez,  Molina,  Lessius,  co-operari  velit  (p.  936),  omitting 
and  others  had  extracted  a  freewill  the  whole  consideration  that  this 
meaning,  as  applying  to  the  will  of  consent  of  the  will  is  itself,  accord- 
man  as  created,  or  simply  to  will  as  ing  to  Augustine  the  effect  of  grace, 
such.  But  while  such  explanation  Having  excluded  Augustinianism 
is  sometimes  required  on  his  own  from  the  pale  of  tolerated  opinion, 
side,  nothing  can  be  more  far-fetched  the  Church  of  Kome  is  obliged  to 
arid  artificial  than  the  Jesuit  inter-  prove  that  S.  Augustine  was  not 
pretations  of  the  great  pervading  Augustinian.  But  the  plain  language 
dicta  and  fundamental  positions  of  of  S.  Augustine  refutes  such  inter- 
Augustine  ;  if  interpretations  de-  preters,  and  forces  one  of  two  alter- 
serve  that  name  which  are  obvious  natives  upon  them,  either  that  they 
and  barefaced  contradictions  to,  tolerate  his  doctrines,  and  so  keep 
rather  than  explanations  of,  S.  him  in  communion  with  their 
Augustine's  meaning,  as  Lessius'  Church,  or  anathematise  his  doc- 
interpretation  of  the  Augustinian  trines,  and  confess  that  S.  Augustine 
predestination  as  conditional  and  does  not  belong  to  their  commu- 
incomplete  (pp.  955,  981)  his  view  nion. 


CHAP.  viir.  of  Freewill.  227 

action  is  free.  We  act  willingly  and  without  compulsion 
whenever  we  truly  act  at  all ;  for  action  forced  upon  us  is 
not  our  own,  but  another's,  and  to  act  willingly  is  to  act 
freely.  We  act  with  deliberation,  choice,  preference,  on 
certain  principles,  and  to  certain  ends.  But  it  does  not 
follow,  it  is  argued,  that  our  mode  of  action  decides  any 
thing  as  to  the  source  of  action  :  we  act  as  we  will ;  but 
the  question  still  remains  how  we  come  to  will.  Under 
neath  all  our  sensations  of  original  agency,  it  is  maintained, 
a  deeper  cause  operates,  and  that  which  is  not  the  will  pro 
duces  the  movements  and  acts  of  the  will.  '  Men  are 
acted  upon,  that  they  may  act,  not  that  they  may  not  act 
— aguntur  ut  agant  non  ut  ipsi  nikil  agant.'  A  transla 
tion  cannot  give  the  point  of  the  original,  which  is  literally 
that  '  men  are  acted  that  they  may  act ; '  the  passive  and 
the  active  of  the  same  verb  being  used  to  express  the  more 
pointedly  the  entire  sequency  of  an  effect  from  a  cause. 
Men  act — agunt,  that  is  the  effect ;  they  are  acted  upon 
— aguntur,  that  is  the  cause  which  accounts  for  the  whole 
of  the  effect.  The  whole  cause  then,  of  human  acts  is 
beyond  the  agent  himself.  But  the  agent  is  not  never 
theless  inert,  because  he  is  not  a  cause ;  on  the  contrary, 
he  is  an  agent,  he  acts.  He  is  not  caused  to  do  nothing  ; 
caused  to  be  idle,  passive,  motionless;  an  actor  is  the  very 
thing  he  is  caused  to  be.  That  is  to  say,  his  mode  of  act 
ing,  which  is  wholly  free,  coexists  with  a  source  of  action 
which  is  external. — '  When  we  will  we  will,  but  He  makes 
us  to  will — cerium  est  nos  velle  cum  volumus,  sed  ille 
facit  ut  velimus  bonum.'  An  objector  is  supposed  to  say 
that  he  must  be  the  cause  of  his  own  acts  because  he  wills 
them.  But  he  is  told  that  his  mode  of  action,  which  is 
free,  decides  nothing  as  to  its  source.  That  a  man  should 
be  'forced  to  will — cogatur  velle,'  would  be  a  contradiction; 
for,  '  if  he  is  forced  he  does  not  will,  he  cannot  will  unwill 
ingly — cum  enim  cogitur  non  vult,  et  quid  absurdius 
quam  ut  dicatur  nolens  velle.''1  But  there  is  no  contra 
diction  in  his  being  made  to  will,  because  the  will  cannot 
resist  before  it  exists,  and  therefore  cannot  be  opposed  to 
1  Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  134. 
Q  2 


228  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  YIH. 

its  own  formation.  It  is  the  same  distinction  of  mode  and 
source.  "  You  do  not  understand,"  Augustine  tells  the 
Pelagian  who  brings  against  him  the  text  2  Tim.  ii.  21  : 
"  If  a  man,  therefore,  purge  himself,'  &c.,  as  proving  man 
to  be  the  proper  source  of  his  own  acts,  '  you  do  not  under 
stand  that  both  assertions  are  true,  that  the  vessels  of  glory 
prepare  themselves,  and  that  God  prepares  them.  For 
God  makes  that  man  does  —  ut  facial  homo  facit  Deus.'  — 
'  What  can  be  more  absurd  than  your  idea  that  because  the 
motives  of  the  will  are  unforced,  we  are  not  to  inquire 
whence  they  are,  as  if  a  cause  were  contradictory  to  their 
freedom,  as  forcing  them  to  be?  Is  a  man  forced  to  exist, 
because  he  has  an  origin  ?  Before  he  existed,  was  there 
anything  to  be  forced  ?  The  will  has  an  origin,  and  yet  is 
not  forced  to  be  ;  and  if  this  origin  is  not  to  be  sought 
for,  the  reason  is  not  that  it  should  not  be,  but  that  it 
need  not,  —  that  it  is  too  manifest.  The  will  is  from  him 
whose  the  will  is  ;  the  angel's  will  from  the  angel,  the 
man's  from  the  man,  (rod's  from  God.  God,  in  working  a 
good  will  in  man,  causes  a  good  will  to  arise  in  him  whose 
the  will  is  —  agit  ut  oriatur  ab  illo  bona  voluntas  cujus 
est  voluntas  ;  just  as  He  causes  man  to  spring  from  man.'1 
No  language  could  indicate  more  fully  the  nature  of  the 
will,  as  an  active,  living,  willing  will,  internal  and  truly 
our  own,  than  this  which  goes  even  the  length  of  claiming 
an  originality  of  the  will  within,  and  making  it  arise  out 
of  ourselves.  But,  on  the  other  hand,  this  very  originality 


1  Op. 
Quid 


Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  101.  cogitur;  et  si  ejus  origo  quaerenda 

autem  vauius  definitionibus  non  est,  non  ideo  quaerenda  non  est 

tuis,  qui  propterea  putas   non  esse  quod  voluntas  alicunde  non  sit,  sed 

quserendum  unde  sit  voluntas,  quia  quia  manifestum  est  unde  sit.     Ab 

motus  est  animi  cogente  nullo  ?     Si  illo   est    enim    voluntas   cujus  est 

enim  dicatur,    ut   putas,   unde  sit  ;  voluntas  ;  ab  angelo  scilicet  volun- 

non   erit   verum  quod   dictum    est,  tas  angeli,   ab  homine   hominis,    a 

cogente  nullo  :    quia  illud  unde  est  Deo  Dei,  et  si  operatur  Deus  in  ho- 

eam   cogit    esse  ;    et   ideo  non    est  mine   voluntatem  bonam,  id  utique 

alicunde,  ne  cogatur  esse.     0  stul-  agit,  ut  oriatur  ab  illo  bona  voluntas, 

titiam  singularem  !     Non    est   ergo  cujus  est    voluntas  ;    sicut  agit  ut 

alicunde  ipse    homo,   qui    non    est  homo  oriatur  ab  homine  ;  non  enim 

coactus  esse,  quia  non  erat  qui  co-  quia  Deus  creat  hominem,  ideo  non 

geretur  antequam  esset.     Prorsuset  homo    ex     homine     nascitur.  —  Op. 

alicunds  est  voluntas,  et  esse  non  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  42. 


CHAP.  viir.  of  Freewill.  229 

of  the  will  is  not  original ;  this  very  source  within  us  is 
derived  from  a  source  without  us.  This  rise  of  the  will 
out  of  ourselves  is  no  more  opposed  to  its  true  causation 
by  Divine  grace,  than  the  birth  of  man  from  man  is 
opposed  to  man's  creation  by  Divine  power.  The  will  is  a 
middle  cause  between  (rod  and  the  act,  as  man  is  a  middle 
cause  between  God  and  the  human  birth.  It  is  a  cause, 
but  that  very  cause  is  caused ;  i.e.  the  will  is  an  absolutely 
free  mode  of  action,  but  not  a  true  original  source  of  action. 
Such  a  doctrine  is  not  fairly  open  to  the  charge  commonly 
brought  against  it,  that  it  converts  man  into  a  machine, 
and  degrades  him  to  the  level  of  matter;  for  it  does  not 
do  so.  A  machine  has  no  will ;  but  this  doctrine  expressly 
admits  in  man  a  will.  But  it  allows  a  will  as  a  mediate, 
and  not  a  first  cause,  of  action. 

The  Augustinian  doctrine  of  freewill  having  been  thus 
stated,  it  only  remains  to  point  out  wherein  lies  its  pecu 
liarity,  in  what  the  true  difference  between  it  and  the 
ordinary  doctrine  of  freewill  consists. 

The  first  characteristic,  then,  that  we  observe  in  the 
doctrine  which  we  have  been  considering,  is,  that  it  com 
bines  freewill  with  necessity.  The  terms  themselves  neces 
sity  and  necessary  are  not  indeed  in  constant  use  in  Augus 
tine  though  he  does  use  them  ;  maintaining  man  in  a  state 
of  nature  to  be  under  '  a  necessity  to  sin—  peccati  neces- 
sitas^  and  under  grace  to  be  recalled  by  necessity  to  a 
spiritual  life — necessitate  revocari.*  Not  selecting  them 
for  his  own  use — conveying  as  they  do  to  ordinary  minds 
the  idea  of  force — when  challenged  by  his  Pelagian 
opponent  to  admit  them,  he  does  not  refuse ;  only  securing 
a  distinction  between  a  co-active  and  a  creative  necessity. 
But  though  the  word  itself  is  not  in  constant  use,  other 
words  which  signify  the  same  thing  are  ;  and  therefore 


1  Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  61.  cuta  est  peccantem  peccavit  habendi 

2  Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  93.     'Necessi-  dura  necessitas,  donee  tota  sanetur 
tatis  inerat  plenitude.' — L.  5.  c.  59.  infirmitas   .    .    .   ita  ut  sit    etiam 
'  Attende  eum  qui  dicit,   Quod  nolo  bene  vivendi,  et  nunquam  peccandi 
malum  hoc  ago,   et   responde  utrum  voluntaria      felixque      necessitas." 
necessitatem  non  habeat.'— L.  5.  c.  — De  Perfectione  Justitise,  c.  4. 

50.  '  Quia  vero  peccavit  voluntas  se- 


230  Augustinian  Doctrine  CHAP.  vni. 

this  doctrine  may  be  called,  in  the  first  place,  a  combination 
of  freewill  with  necessity. 

The  peculiarity,  however,  of  the  Augustinian  doctrine 
does  not  lie  in  this  combination  ;  for  the  combination  itself 
is  not,  when  we  examine  the  matter,  open  to  any  substan 
tial  objection.  We  are  apt,  indeed,  at  first  to  think  that 
no  will  can  be  in  any  sense  free  that  acts  necessarily ;  but 
a  little  reflection  will  show  us  that  this  is  a  first  thought 
resulting  from  not  properly  knowing  our  own  admissions 
on  this  subject.  We  attribute  to  the  Supreme  Being,  the 
angels,  and  saints  in  their  state  of  reward,  a  necessity  on 
the  side  of  goodness  ;  but  we  attribute  to  God,  the  angels, 
and  the  saints  the  operation  of  a  genuine  will.  We  attri 
bute  to  the  evil  spirits  and  the  wicked,  in  their  state  of 
punishment,  a  necessity  on  the  side  of  evil,  and  together 
with  it  the  same  genuine  will.  Necessity  indeed  only  ope 
rates  in  matter  in  this  lower  world ;  inevitable  growth, 
inevitable  decay,  organisation,  and  disorganisation,  are  only 
seen  in  the  animal,  vegetable  and  mineral  bodies  ;  but  in 
the  eternal  world,  the  intelligent  substance  acts  necessarily, 
and  that  which  moves  with  certainty  in  the  direction  of 
good  or  evil  is  will.  The  Supreme  Will,  being  essentially 
good,  cannot  contradict  itself ;  the  will  of  the  wicked  can 
not  agree  with,  the  will  of  the  righteous  cannot  recede 
from,  the  Will  Supreme.  Indeed,  we  are  conversant  with 
certain  approaches  to  necessity  in  human  conduct  in  this 
life.  It  is  the  essential  characteristic  of  habit,  that  it 
makes  acts  to  be  performed  by  us  as  a  matter  of  course, 
implants  a  kind  of  law  in  our  minds,  by  which  we  act  in 
this  or  that  way ;  and  therefore  habit  is  called  a  second 
nature.  But  we  do  not  consider  that  men  who  have 
formed  habits,  virtuous  or  the  contrary,  do  not  act  with 
freewill. 

Nor,  again,  does  the  peculiarity  of  S.  Augustine's  doc 
trine,  as  it  does  not  lie  in  the  combination  of  freewill  with 
necessity,  lie  either  in  the  source  which  he  assigns  to  such 
necessity,  which  is  one  external  to  the  agent.  The  doctrine 
of  an  eternal  state  of  reward  and  punishment,  which  all 
Christians  admit,  asserts  the  transference  of  human  wills 


CHAP.  vin.  of  Freewill.  231 

into  a  state  of  necessity,  both  for  evil  and  good,  by  an  act 
of  Almighty  Power  ;  that  the  wills  of  wicked  men  are,  on 
their  departure  from  this  life,  put  by  this  act  into  a  state 
in  which  they  are  beyond  recovery ;  those  of  the  good  into 
a  state  in  which  they  are  beyond  lapse.  The  power  of 
choice  being,  according  to  the  doctrine  of  freewill,  retained 
by  man  so  long  as  he  remains  in  this  world,  its  determina 
tion,  on  his  departure  to  another,  is  caused  not  by  an  act 
of  his  own,  but  by  a  Divine  act  of  judgment  or  of  reward, 
as  it  may  be.  Thus  all  (rod's  moral  creatures  pass,  at  a 
particular  stage  of  their  being,  by  an  act  of  Divine  Power, 
from  a  state  in  which  their  wills  are  indeterminate  and 
may  choose  either  good  or  evil,  to  a  state  in  which  they 
necessarily  choose  one  or  the  other.  While  there  is  life 
there  is  hope,  and  there  is  fear.  The  most  inveterate 
habits  of  vice  still  leave  a  power  of  self-recovery  in  the 
man  if  he  will  but  exert  it ;  the  most  confirmed  habits  of 
virtue  still  leave  the  liability  to  a  fall.  The  resources  for 
a  struggle  between  good  and  evil  remain  up  to  the  time  of 
departure  from  life,  when  a  change  takes  place  which  no 
thought  can  reach,  and  by  a  Divine  act  the  will,  remaining 
the  same  in  substance,  is  changed  fundamentally  in  con 
dition,  and  put  out  of  a  state  of  suspense  and,  in  ordinary 
language,  freedom,  into  one  of  necessity. 

But  the  combination  of  necessity,  and  that  a  necessity 
communicated  to  the  will  from  without,  with  freewill,  being 
admitted  on  both  sides,  the  peculiarity  of  Augustine's  doc 
trine  lies  in  the  application  of  this  principle  ;  in  the  reason, 
the  time,  and  the  manner  he  assigns  to  its  operation.  That 
state  of  the  will  to  which  an  original  power  of  choice 
attaches  is  upon  the  doctrine  of  freewill  identical  with  a 
state  of  trial ;  and  this  consideration  gives  us  the  reason 
and  time  of  the  introduction  of  necessity,  as  well  as  the 
manner  of  its  operation  according  to  the  doctrine  of  free 
will.  The  ground  of  its  introduction  is  final  reward  and 
punishment ;  the  time  of  its  introduction  is  after  a  state  of 
trial;  and  the  manner  of  its  operation  consists  in  the 
absence  of  struggle,  effort,  or  interruption  ;  in  the  entire, 
continuous,  and  natural  yielding  of  the  will  to  the  impulses 


232  Augustinian  Doctrine          CHAP.  vni. 

of  good  or  evil.  The  strife  is  over  in  the  mind  of  man ; 
and  the  will,  finally  rooted,  goes  on  producing  good  or  evil 
acts  and  motions  with  the  ease  and  uniformity  of  physical 
law.  But  in  S.  Augustine's  application  of  the  principle, 
the  reason,  and  time  of  its  introduction,  and  mode  of  ope 
ration,  are  all  different.  Necessity  is  not  the  reward  or 
punishment  of  a  previous  exercise  of  liberty  of  choice,  but 
the  effect  of  original  sin  on  the  one  hand,  and  an  eternal 
Divine  decree  of  mercy  on  the  other.  And  with  the  diffe 
rence  of  reason  for,  the  time  of  its  introduction  is  also 
different.  It  does  not  succeed  and  come  after  a  state  of 
trial,  but  is  simultaneous  with  it,  and  is  in  full  operation 
in  this  life,  instead  of  being  reserved  for  the  next.  And 
the  manner  of  its  operation  is  for  the  same  reason  different, 
exhibiting  the  struggle,  the  variableness,  and  interruption 
incident  to  this  present  state  of  existence.  The  difference 
between  the  trial,  effort,  and  alternation  of  the  present,  and 
the  peace  and  serenity  of  the  future  life,  which  is  upon  the 
doctrine  of  freewill  a  difference  between  a  state  of  liberty 
and  a  state  of  necessity,  is,  according  to  the  predestinarian, 
only  a  difference  between  two  modes  of  operation  on  the 
part  of  the  same  necessity.  That  grace  from  which  good 
action  necessarily  follows  is  not  given  with  uniformity  in 
this  life,  sometimes  being  given  and  sometimes  not,  to  the 
same  individual ;  whereas,  in  the  eternal  world  it  is  either 
given  wholly  or  taken  away  wholly,  always  given  or  never  ; 
so  that  there  the  determination  of  the  will  is  constant  for 
good  or  for  evil.  Its  mode  of  operation,  then,  in  this  life 
is  variable,  in  the  next  uniform  ;  here,  with  pain  and  effort 
to  the  man,  with  trouble  and  anxiety,  the  feeling  of  uncer 
tainty,  and  other  feelings  exactly  like  what  we  should  have, 
supposing  our  wills  were  free  and  our  acts  contingent ; 
there  with  ease,  security,  and  bliss ;  here  preparatory,  there 
final ;  here  after  the  mode  of  trial,  there  after  the  mode  of 
reward. 

Such  a  difference  between  two  doctrines  of  necessity,  it 
will  be  seen,  involves  all  the  difference  between  a  doctrine 
of  necessity  and  a  doctrine  of  freewill.  The  former  gives 
to  freewill  that  period  which  is  the  turning  part  of  man's 


CHIP.  vm.  of  Freewill.  233 

existence,  this  life  ;  to  necessity  only  that  future  state  which 
is  here  decided.  The  latter  gives  to  necessity  both  the 
future  state  itself  and  the  decision  of  it. 


CHAPTER    IX. 

SCHOLASTIC   THEORY   OF   NECESSITY. 

THE  teaching  of  S.  Augustine  had  that  result  which  natu 
rally  follows  from  the  keen  perception  and  mastery  of  a 
particular  truth  by  a  vigorous,  powerful,  and  fertile  mind ; 
endowed  with  an  inexhaustible  command  and  perfect 
management  of  language,  which  seconded  and  acted  as 
the  simple  instrument  of  the  highest  religious  ardour  and 
enthusiasm.  Copious  and  exuberant,  and  concise  and 
pointed,  at  the  same  time  ;  bold,  ingenious,  and  brilliant, 
yet  always  earnest  and  natural,  he  did  not  write  so  much 
in  vain.  As  the  production  of  a  single  mind,  the  quantity 
of  the  writing  had  a  unity,  force,  and  wholeness  which  told 
with  surprising  effect  upon  the  Church.  The  large  aggre 
gate  of  thought  and  statement  came  in  one  effective  mass 
and  body.  One  such  writer  is  in  himself  a  whole  age,  and 
more  than  an  age  of  authorship  ;  a  complete  school,  and 
more  than  a  school  of  divinity.  He  had,  moreover,  the 
advantage  of  an  undoubted  and  solid  ground  of  Scripture ; 
an  advantage  which  his  deep  and  full  knowledge  of  the 
sacred  text,  and  wonderful  skill  and  readiness  in  the  appli 
cation  of  it,  enabled  him  to  use  with  the  greatest  etfect. 
He  erected  on  this  ground,  indeed,  more  than  it  could 
legitimately  bear,  and  was  a  one-sided  interpreter.  Still 
he  brought  out  a  side  of  Scripture  which  had  as  yet  been 
much  in  the  shade,  and  called  attention  to  deep  truths 
which  had  comparatively  escaped  notice  in  the  Church. 
He  brought  to  light  the  full  meaning  of  S.  Paul,  and  did 
that  which  the  true  interpreter  does  for  his  teacher  and 
master, — fastened  the  great  doctrine  of  the  Apostle,  in  its 
full  and  complete  sense,  upon  the  Church. 


234  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  ix. 

Such  an  exposition  had  as  great  and  as  permanent 
success  as  could  have  been  anticipated.  The  doctrine  of 
S.  Augustine  reigned  in  the  mediaeval  Church,  and  moulded 
its  authoritative  teaching,  till  the  Reformation  produced 
a  reaction  ;  and  the  Eoman  Church,  apprehensive  of  the 
countenance  which  it  gave  to  some  prominent  doctrines  of 
the  Reformers,  and  repelled  by  the  use — sometimes  unfair 
and  fanatical — made  of  it,  fell  back  upon  a  strong  doctrine 
of  freewill.  The  Thomists  took  an  important  part,  indeed, 
in  the  Council  of  Trent,  and  had  sufficient  influence  to 
guard  its  decrees  from  any  turn  unfavourable  to  themselves. 
But  they  ceased  after  the  Reformation  to  be  a  prominent 
and  ruling  school,  and  gave  place  to  the  Jesuits,  who,  as 
the  antagonists  by  position  and  calling  of  the  Reformation, 
formed  their  theology  in  express  opposition  to  it,  and 
abandoned  the  Augustinian  ground.  The  Jansenists  at 
tempted  a  revival  of  it,  to  which  their  enthusiasm  and 
devotion  gave  a  temporary  success,  sufficient  to  alarm  the 
dominant  school :  but  authority  finally  suppressed  it,  and 
ejected  them,  and  practically  with  them  the  Augustinian 
doctrine,  from  the  Roman  Church. 

The  mediaeval  Augustinian  school  presents  us  with  the 
names  of  Peter  Lombard,  S.  Bernard,  S.  Anselm,  Thomas 
Aquinas,  Bradwardine,1  and  others.2  Among  these  Lombard 
and  Aquinas  occupy  the  first  place  as  formal  and  systematic 
theologians.  The  former  of  these,  however,  is  more  of  a 
compiler  and  collector  of  extracts  and  references,  than  an 
exponent  and  a  constructor.  His  collection  of  statements, 
indeed,  arranged  on  a  plan,  and  extending  over  a  large 
ground,  is  in  itself  an  exposition,  and  an  able  one ;  and  it 

1  I  cannot  wholly  understand,  ex-  are    more    like    the   shadows   and 

cept  as  unfavourably  characteristic  ghosts  of  reasonings  than  the  reali- 

of  that  age,  the  great  mediaeval  re-  ties. 

putation  of  Bradwardine,  called  the  2  The  predestinarian  controversy 
1  profound  doctor.'  A  dull  monotony  in  the  Gallican  Church,  which 
characterises  his  speculations,  which  arose  out  of  the  statements  of  Grot- 
are  all  spun  out  of  the  idea  of  the  Di-  teschalcus,  in  the  ninth  century, 
vine  Power,  or  of  Grod  as  the  Univer-  does  not  offer  much  valuable  mate- 
sal  Cause  ;  but  spun  into  airy  subtle-  rial  to  the  theological  student.  I 
ties,  which  want  the  substance  of  give  the  principal  points  of  it  in 
solid  thought  and  argument,  and  NOTE  XX. 


CHAP.  ix.  of  Necessity.  235 

formed  the  great  text  book  of  the  Church  for  centuries. 
But  it  is  not  an  argumentative  exposition ;  it  does  not  ex 
pand  and  develop  by  statement  and  reasoning  theological 
ideas.     Aquinas,  however,  supplies  the  deficiencies  of  Lom 
bard,  and,  taking  up  the  scheme  and  ground-plan  which  the 
older  commentator   furnishes,  applies  the  argumentative 
and  philosophical  talent  to  it,  and  fills  it  out  with  thought ; 
enriching  it  at  the  same  time  with  large  additions  from 
the  stores  of  heathen  philosophy.     Aquinas  is  accordingly 
the  great  representative   of  mediaeval  August inianism — I 
might  say,  of  mediaeval  theology.     He  reflects  the  mind — 
he  embodies   the  ideas  and  sentiments  of  the  mediaeval 
Church.     In  him,  as  in  a  mirror,  we  see  the  great  assump 
tions,  the  ruling  arguments  of  the  theological  world  ;  the 
mode  of  inference  which  was  considered  legitimate ;  the 
way  of  solving  difficulties  which  was  thought  satisfactory. 
In  his  large  and  capacious  mind  we   see  the  collective 
theological  thought  and  philosophy  of  the  middle  ages. 
He  fails,  indeed,  in  a  power  which  it  was  reserved  for  a 
modern   age  to  call  forth   from   the  human  mind — the 
analytical  one.     He  does  not  turn  his  mind  inward  upon 
itself  to  examine  its  own  thoughts  and  ideas,  and  compare 
received  and  current  truths  with  the  original  type  from 
which  they  are  copied.     In  this  sense  he  does  not  appre 
hend  and  realise  truths :  because  he  does  not  put  his  mind 
into  that  attitude  in  which  it  has  alone  the  power  of  seeing 
its  own  processes,  ideas,  and  modes  of  entertaining  truth 
— the  attitude   of  reflection  and  turning   inward   of  the 
mind  upon  itself.     No  one  can  see  a  thing  but  by  looking 
at  it ;  the  mediaeval  mind  did  not  look  within,  or  examine 
itself  ;   it  could  not,  therefore,  see   itself — i.e.   get  such 
knowledge  as  has  been  since  proved  to  be  attainable  of  its 
own  operations  and  ideas.     It  was  left  for  a  later  age  to 
call  attention  to  this  world  of  internal  discovery,  and  force 
the  human  mind  back  upon  itself ;  changing  that  progres 
sive  habit,  in  which  it  had  so  long  exclusively  indulged, 
of  following  up  and  arguing   interminably  upon  truths, 
into  the  stationary  one   of  examining  the  truths   them 
selves.     Aquinas  accepts  the  received  statements  and  posi- 


236  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  ix. 

tions,  and  expands  them  with  argumentative  subtlety  and 
power.  And  the  vast  amount  of  statements  and  positions 
which  his  mind  includes  and  thus  expands  and  treats  argu- 
mentatively  is  surprising ;  showing  a  truly  enormous  grasp 
and  capacity,  somewhat  analogous  to  that  of  a  great  states 
man,  who,  without  penetrating  far  below  or  aiming  at  a 
deeper  understanding  of  the  particular  subjects  and  ques 
tions  presented  to  his  consideration  than  he  practically 
wants,  embraces  an  immense  quantity  of  such  particulars ; 
all  of  which  he  treats  argumentatively  and  is  ready  to 
discuss,  and  come  to  a  conclusion  and  decision  upon  them. 
The  argumentative  edifice,  however,  of  Aquinas,  for  want 
of  this  later  and  inward  attitude  of  mind,  shows  deep 
deficiencies  ;  and  especially  that  great  vice  of  the  scholastic 
intellect — distinguishing  without  a  difference ;  a  fault  which 
arises  from  accepting  the  superficial  meaning  of  statements, 
or  the  words  themselves,  without  going  into  their  real 
meaning,  which  would  often  show  that  different  words  really 
meant  the  same  thing. 

Taking  Aquinas,  therefore,  as  the  representative  of 
medieval  Augustinianism,  I  shall  endeavour  in  this  and 
the  following  chapter  to  give  an  account  of  his  system  so 
far  as  it  touches  on  the  particular  subject  of  the  present 
treatise.  aThe  examination  will  disclose  some  forms  of 
thought  and  modes  of  arguing  with  which  a  modern  mind 
will  not  sympathise,  but  to  which  it  will  rather  appeal  as 
showing  how  differently  the  intellect  of  man  reasons  in 
different  ages,  and  how  the  received  thought  of  one  period 
becomes  quaint  and  obsolete  in  another.  The  system, 
however,  will  be  found  as  a  whole  to  rest  upon  some  broad 
and  common  assumptions,  which  have  always  formed,  and 
always  will  form,  an  important  portion  of  the  basis  of 
human  opinion. 

The  doctrine  of  predestination,  then,  in  the  system  of 
Aquinas,  rests  mainly  on  philosophy,  and  rises  upon  the 
idea  of  the  Divine  Power.  This  fundamental  position  was 
laid  down,  this  religious  axiom  stated  with  jealous  exactness 
and  the  most  scientific  strength  of  language,  and  the  rest 
was  deduced  by  way  of  logical  consequence  from  it.  God 


CHAP.  rx.  of  Necessity.  237 

was  the  First  Great  Cause:  His  will  the  source  of  all 
things,  the  spring  of  all  motions,  all  events :  it  could  not 
be  frustrated,  it  must  always  be  fulfilled  :  «  God  hath  done 
whatsoever  He  would — omnia  qucecunque  voluit  fecit,  in 
codo  et  in  terra.'  This  was  contained  in  the  very  idea  of 
Omnipotence ;  for  no  agency  can  be  impeded  but  by 
stronger  agency,  and  none  can  be  stronger  than  Omnipo 
tence  :  it  was  contained  in  the  very  idea  of  the  Divine 
Felicity  ;  for  no  one  can  be  perfectly  happy  whose  will  is 
not  fulfilled,  and  the  Supreme  Being  is  perfectly  happy.1 
Though  the  Divine  Will,  then,  acted  by  mediate  and 
secondary  causes,  both  in  the  physical  and  moral  world, 
these  causes  were  no  more  than  mediate  ones,  and  fell  back 
upon  the  First  Great  Cause,  from  which  they  derived  all 
their  efficacy.  Nor,  because  a  secondary  cause  failed  of  its 
effect,  was  there,  therefore,  any  failure  of  the  power  of  the 
First  Cause.  One  particular  cause  was  impeded  in  its 
operation  by  another ;  the  action  of  fire  by  that  of  water, 
the  digestive  functions  of  the  stomach  by  the  coarseness 
of  the  food :  but  the  qualities  of  the  water  and  the  food 
were  also  particular  causes,  acting  under  the  Universal 
Cause  as  much  as  those  which  they  impeded.  Thus  what 
seemed  to  recede  from  the  Divine  Will  according  to  one 
order,  returned  to  it  under  another ;  and  the  failure  of  the 
particular  cause  was  the  success  of  the  universal.2 

1  '  Voluntas  Dei  causa  est  omnium  speciei,  sed  etiam  quantum  ad  indi- 
quse  naturaliter  fiunt,  vel  facta  sive  vidua  principia.' — Summa  Theolo- 
futura  sunt.  .  .  .  prima  et  summa  gica,  P.  1.  Quaest.  22.  Art.  2. 
causa  omnium  specierum  et  moti-  '  In  hujusmodi  autem  causis  non 
©num.' — Lombard.  1.  1.  Distinct.  45.  est  infinitus  processus,  est  ergo 
4  Cassari  non  potest,  quia  ilia  volun-  aliqua  omnium  una  prima  quse  est 
tate  fecit  quaecunque  voluit,  in  ccelo  Deus.' — Bradwardine,p.l90.  '  Omne 
et  in  terra,  cui,  teste  Apostolo,  nihil  movens  posterius  est  instrumentum 
resistit.' — Distinct.  46.  '  Nulla  causa  primi  moventis,  alias  enim  non  est 
impeditur  nisi  ab  aliquo  fortiori  posterius  naturaliter  eo,  sed  prius 
agente,  sed  nihil  est  fortius  Divina  vel  etiam  coaequum.' — p.  173. 
voluntate.  .  .  .  Prseterea,  diminutio  2  '  Quod  si  aliqua  causa  particu- 
gaudii  si  voluntas  non  impleatur,  laris  deficiat  a  suo  effectu,  hoc  est 
sed  Deus  felicissimus.' — Aquinas  in  propter  aliquam  aliam  causam  par- 
Lombard.  Distinct.  47.  '  Causali-  ticularem  immediantem,  quae  conti- 
tas  autem  Dei  qui  estprimum  agens,  netur  sub  ordine  causae  universalis. 
se  extendit  usque  ad  omnia  entia,  Unde  effectus  ordinem  causae  uni- 
non  solum  quantum  ad  principia  versalis  nullo  modo  potest  exire.' 


238  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  rx. 

To  the  position  that  the  Divine  Will  was  the  cause  of 
things  that  were,  succeeded  the  further  one,  that  it  could 
have  caused  everything  that  was,  without  a  contradiction 
in  terms,  possible.1  And  stated  thus  indefinitely,  this 
position  also  was  only  a  legitimate  expansion  of  the  idea 
of  the  Divine  Power.  We  evidently  cannot  restrict  the 
Divine  Power  to  the  simple  causation  of  the  existing  world, 
without  reducing  it  to  a  cause  acting  itself  under  a  neces 
sity,  or  to  a  kind  of  fate.  If  we  liberate  the  First  Cause, 
however,  from  this  tie,  and  suppose  it  to  act  freely,  causing 
some  effects  and  not  others,  according  to  its  own  sovereign 
will  and  pleasure,  we  cannot  state  its  Power  less  narrowly 
than  as  a  Power  of  causing  anything  which  is,  in  the 
nature  of  things,  possible.  But  while  the  scholastic  posi 
tion  was  in  itself  legitimate,  it  was  carried  out  unsoundly 
and  hastily.  Its  maintainers  advanced  beyond  the  inde 
finite  ground  that  God  could  cause  every  thing  that  was 
possible,  to  state  what  was  possible  ;  and  they  determined 
that  the  Supreme  Being  could,  had  it  pleased  Him,  have 
made  the  whole  universe  more  perfect  than  it  was,  both 
by  adding  to  its  parts  and  species,  and  by  making  the 
existing  ones  better,  and  not  only  better  but  faultless.  The 
universe  was  finite,  and  what  was  finite  could  be  added  to; 
and  the  scale  which  ascended  from  this  created  world  to 
infinity  had  numberless  places  unoccupied,  which  the 
Creator  could  have  filled  up,  and  successive  types  of  being 
which  He  could  have  embodied  and  expressed,  had  He  so 
willed,  and  so  increased  the  ranks  and  orders  of  the  exist 
ing  universe.  The  existing  species,  too,  could  have  been 

— Sum.  Theol.  P.   1.  Q.  19,  Art.  6.  aliquid   contingat    prseter    ordinem 

'  Sicut   lignum   impeditur    a    com-  divinse  gubernationis ;  sed   ex   hoc 

bustione    per     actionem     aquae.' —  ipso  quod   aliquid  ex  una  parte  vi- 

Q.   22.  Art.    2.      '  Sicut    indigestio  detur  exire  ab  ordine  Divinae  provi- 

contingit    prseter   ordinem    virtutis  dentise,  quo  consideratur  secundum 

nutritivse    ex   aliquo    impedimento,  aliquam  particularem   causam,  ne- 

puta  ex  grossitie  cibi,  quam  necesse  cesse  est  quod  in  eundem  ordinem 

est  reducere   in   aliam  causam,    et  relabatur  secundum  aliam  causam.' 

sic  usque  ad  causam  primamj  uni-  — Sum.  Theol.  P.  1.  Q,.  103.  Art.  7. 

versalem.      Cum   igitur   Deus     sit  *  Cum  Deus  omnia  posse  dicitur, 

prima  causa  universalis  non  unius  nihil  rectius  intelligitur  quam  quod 

generis  tantum,    sed    universaliter  possit     omnia     possibilia.  —  Sum. 

totius  entis,    impossible   est  quod  Theol.  P.  1.  Q.  25.  Art.  3. 


CHAP.  ix.  of  Necessity.  239 

made  better,  and  even  without  fault,  for  God  could,  had  it 
pleased  Him,  have  created  a  universe  in  which  there  was 
no  evil ;  and  man  himself  could  have  been  made  so  that  he 
neither  could  nor  would  even  wish  to  sin.1 

The  fundamental  idea  of  the  Divine  power  thus  laid 
down  was  applied  strictly  to  the  motions  of  the  human 
will,  or  to  human  actions.  God  was  the  cause  of  all  the 
motions  of  the  human  will,  but  He  caused  them  by  means 
of  the  will  itself,  as  a  mediate  and  secondary  cause.  The 
great  scheme  of  Divine  Providence  contained  two  great 
classes  of  secondary  causes,2  one  necessary,  the  other  con 
tingent.  The  course  of  nature  was  conducted  by  means 
of  necessary  causes,  or  causes  acting  necessarily ;  which 
class,  again,  had  two  different  operations  and  effects, 
according  to  the  difference  of  the  natures  to  which  it  was 
applied.  In  fixed  and  permanent  natures,  the  operation 
of  necessary  causes  was  unfailing,  and  they  could  not  by 
possibility  fall  short  of  their  effects  ;  such  was  the  opera 
tion  of  fixed  and  unalterable  law  in  the  motions  of  the 
heavenly  bodies,  presenting  to  us  an  instance  of  a  world 
which  was  without  change,  and  of  which  it  was  said,  that 
above  the  sphere  of  the  moon  was  no  evil.  In  generable 

1  'Potest  Deus  meliorem  rem  fa-  bilis.' — Aquinas,    in   Lomb.   L.     1. 

cere.sive  etiam  rerum  universitatem,  Dist.  44. 

quam  fecit.' — Lombard,  L.  1.  Dist.  '  Utrum  Deus  potuerit  facere  hu- 

44.    '  Secundum  philosophum  albius  manitatem  Christi  meliorem  quam 

est   quod  est    nigro    impermistius:  fit.' — '  Quamvis  humana  natura  sit 

ergo    etiam    melius    est    quod   est  Divinitati  unita  in  persona,  tamen 

impermistius  malo  :    sed   Deus   po-  naturae   rernanent   distantes  infini- 

tuit  facere  universum  in  quo  nihil  turn,  et  ex  hoc  potest  esse  aliquid 

mali   esset.      .     .     .    Quantum    ad  melius  humana  natura  in  Christo.' 

partes   ipsas     potest    intelligi  uni-  — Aquinas,inLomb.  Dist.  44.  Art.  3. 

versum  fieri  melius.     Sive  per  ad-  '  Talem    potuit    Deus    hominem 

ditionempluriumpartium.ut  scilicet  fecisse  qui  nee  peccare  posset  nee 

crearentur  multse   aliae   species,    et  vellet ;    et  si    talem    fecisset    quis 

implerentur  multi  gradus  bonitatis  dubitet    eum   meliorem    fecisse.' — 

qui  possunt  esse,  cum   etiam  inter  Aug.  sup.  Gen.  ad  Lit.  xi.  7.  Quoted 

summam   creaturam  et  Deum  infi-  by  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  44. 

nita  distantia  sit;  et  sic  Deus  melius  2  Causse  mediae  —  proximae — se- 

universum  facere  potuisset.  .  .  Vel  cundae. — '  Omnium  quse  sunt  causa 

potest  intelligi  fieri   melius    quasi  est  Dei  voluntas  .  .  .  mediantibus 

intensive,  quasi   mutatis    omnibus  aliis  causis,  ut  sic  etiam  causandi 

partibus  ejus  in  melius  .  .  .  et  sic  dignitas  creaturis  communicaretur.' 

etiam  esset  (melioratio)  Deo  possi-  — Aquinas,  in  Lomb.  Dist.  45. 


240 


Scholastic  Theory 


CHAP.  IX. 


and  corruptible  natures  they  had  a  failing  operation,  and 
alternately  attained  and  fell  short  of  their  effects:  the 
Universal  Cause,  however,  being  alike  effective  in  either 
case,  and  good  alike  the  result ;  for  the  corruption  of  one 
thing  was  the  generation  of  another.1  The  second  class 
of  causes  was  contingent  or  voluntary,  operating  in  those 
creatures  which  had  in  addition  to  nature  the  principle  of 
will.  The  effects,  then,  which  took  place  in  the  world 
took  place  necessarily,  or  contingently,  according  to  the 
character  of  those  mediate  and  secondary  causes  which 
were  respectively  in  operation ;  but  in  either  case  these 
causes  were  but  mediate,  and  fell  back  upon  the  First 
Great  Cause,  from  which  they  derived  all  their  virtue  as 
secondary  ones.  The  Supreme  Being  fitted  like  causes  to 
like  effects,  necessary  to  necessary,  contingent  to  contin 
gent;2  but  His  will  it  was  which  gave  to  these  causes  their 
respective  natures,  and  made  one  necessary  and  the  other 
contingent.3  He  moved  matter,  and  He  moved  will  by 


1  '  In  his  autem  qui  consequuntur 
finem  per   principium  quod  est  na- 
tura  inyenitur   quidam  gradus,    eo 
quod     quarundam    rerum     natura 
impediri  non  potest  a  consecutions 
effectus  sui,  et  iste  est  gradus  altior 
sicut  est  in   corporibus   caelestibus. 
Unde   in    his   nihil    contingit   non 
intentum  a  Deo  ex  defectu  ipsorum  ; 
et  propter  hoc  Avicenna  dicit  quod 
supra  orbem  lunse  non   est  malum. 
Alius  autem  gradus  naturae  est  quae 
impediri    potest    et    deficere,  sicut 
natura  generabilium  et  corruptibi- 
lium ;    et  quamvis    ista   natura  sit 
inferior  in  bonitate,  tamen  bona  est.' 
— Aquinas,  in  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  39. 

2  Quibusdam    effectibus    praepa- 
ravit  causas  necessarias  ut  necessario 
evenirent;  quibusdam  vero    causas 
contingentes,  ut   evenirent    cont  n- 
genter,  secundum  conditionem  proxi- 
marum  causarum.' — Sum.*  Theol.  P. 
1.  Q.  23.  Art.  4. 

'  Ita  omnia  movet  secundum  eorum 
conditionem ;    ita   quod  ex    causis 


necessariis  per  motionem  divinam 
sequuntur  effectus  ex  necessitate ; 
ex  causis  autem  contingentibus  se 
quuntur  effectus  contingentes.' — 
lm»  2dae  Q.  49.  Art.  4. 

'  Effectus  consequitur  conditionem 
causae  suse  proximse.' — Aquinas,  in 
Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist,  39. 

3  Dicendum  est  quod  hoc  contingit 
propter  efficaciam  Divinae  voluntatis 
.  .  .  Vult  enim  quaedamDeus  neces 
sario,  qusedam  contingenter,  ut  sit 
ordo  in  rebus  ad  complementum 
universi.  Et  ideo  quibusdam  effec 
tibus  aptavit  causas  necessarias,  ex 
quibus  effectus  ex  necessitate  pro- 
veniant ;  quibusdam  autem  causas 
defectibiles,  ex  quibus  effectus  con 
tingenter  proveniant.  Non  igitur 
propterea  effectus  voliti  a  Deo  eve- 
niunt  contingenter,  quia  causae 
proximae  sunt  contingentes ;  sed 
propterea  quia  Deus  voluit  eos 
contingenter  evenire,  contingentes 
causas  ad  eos  praeparavit.' — Sum. 
Theol.  lma  Q.  19.  Art.  8. 


CHAP.  ix.  of  Necessity.  241 

causes  alike  of  His  own  arbitrary  arid  sovereign  creation. 
He  produced  the  motions  of  the  physical  world  by  neces 
sary,  the  motions  of  the  human  will  by  voluntary  causes  ; 
but  these  voluntary  causes  were  set  in  motion  by  Himself; 
(rod  was  the  cause  of  the  will.1  The  aims,  the  designs, 
the  deliberations,  and  the  acts  of  man  were  subjected  to 
the  Divine  Will,  as  being  derived  ultimately  from  it ;  and 
man's  providence  was  contained  under  the  Divine,  as  the 
particular  cause  under  the  universal.2 

Such  was  the  logical  consequence  of  the  idea  of  the 
Divine  power,  as  regards  the  human  will.  Under  the  no 
tion  of  the  will,  as  a  mediate  cause,  the  Augustinian 
schoolmen  left  out  no  function,  action,  or  characteristic  of 
will  of  which  the  human  soul  is  conscious.  They  acknow 
ledged  every  internal  act  and  sensation  which  belongs  to 
us  as  having  and  exercising  will ;  that  which  every  reason 
able  man  who  does  not  deny  the  plainest  facts  must  admit. 
They  brought  all  these  characteristics  to  a  point,  and  ex 
pressed  them  in  one  term — self-motion.  The  will  moved 
itself,  was  the  cause  of  its  own  motion,  the  mistress  of  its 
own  acts  ;  it  was  in  its  power  to  will  or  not  to  will.  Man 
moved  himself  to  action  by  his  freewill.  But  this  self- 
motion  was  only  admitted  as  an  internal  impression,  and 
was  not  allowed  to  counteract  or  modify  the  dominant 
position  of  one  absolute  causality.  The  will  was  a  prin 
ciple  of  motion  to  itself;  but  it  was  not,  therefore,  the 
first  principle  of  such  motion, — it  did  not  follow  that  this 
principle  of  motion  was  not  itself  set  in  motion  by  some 
thing  else.  The  will  was  the  internal  principle  of  its  own 
motion  ;  but  this  self-determining  power  moved  the  will 
as  causa  proxima,  not  as  causa  prima  ;  the  internal 
principle  was  only  a  secondary  one,  succeeding  to  a  first 
principle,  which  was  external  to  the  will.  The  will,  though 
it  moved  itself,  was  moved  ab  alio  to  this  motion.  Nor 

1  '  Voluntatis   causa  nihil    aliud  2  '  Providentia     hominis     conti- 

esse    potest    quam    Deus.'  —  Sum.  netur    sub    providentia    Dei   sicut 

Theol.  I™*  2dae  Q.  10.  Art.  6.  'Deus  particularis   causa    sub  causa   uni- 

est  causa  prima  movens  et  naturales  versali.' — Sum.  Theol.     I"*  Q.   23. 

causas  et  voluntarias.' — lma  Q.  83.  Art.  2. 
Art.  1. 


242  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  rx. 

was  the  true  and  genuine  voluntariness  of  its  motions  at  all 
effected  by  their  source  being  external.  For  the  Supreme 
Mover  did  not,  by  setting  natural  causes  in  motion,  hinder 
the  acts  in  which  such  causes  issued  from  being  natural ; 
no  more,  when  He  set  in  motion  the  voluntary  causes,  did 
He  hinder  the  acts  in  which  they  issued  from  being  volun 
tary.  Rather  He  Himself  caused  in  these  acts  their 
voluntariness,  and  their  naturalness  respectively,  working 
in  each  nature  according  to  its  peculiarity — inunoquoque 
operans  secundum  ejus  proprietatem.1 

And  this  consideration  supplied  the  answer  to  the  ques 
tion  how  our  wills  could  be  moved  from  without,  and  yet 
feel  no  force,  no  constraint,  but  all  its  motions  go  on  ex 
actly  as  if  they  originated  in  ourselves.  There  were  two 
kinds  of  necessity,  the  necessity  of  force,  and  the  necessity 
of  nature  or  inclination.  The  necessity  of  force  was  vi 
termini  opposed  to  inclination,  and  if  it  prevailed,  pre 
vailed  in  spite  of  it.  and  was  attended  with  the  sensation 
to  the  man  of  being  forced  or  obliged  to  do  a  thing.  But 
the  necessitv  of  inclination,  or  that  which  made  the  incli 
nation  to  be  what  it  was,  could  only  be  felt  as  inclination, 
not  as  force.  For  the  inclination  itself  was  to  begin  with 
that  which  such  necessity  had  made  it  to  be ;  it  could 
have  felt  nothing  contrary  to  it,  nothing  violating  it,  in 

1  '  Voluntas  domina  est  sui  actus,  quin  actiones  earum  sint  voluntariae, 

et  in  ipsa  est  velle  et  non  velle  ;  sed  potius  hoc  in  eis  facit ;  operatur 

quod  non  esset  si   non    haberet  in  enim  in  unoquoque  secundum  ejus 

potestate    movere   seipsam   ad   vo-  proprietatem.' — Sum.  Theol.  lm'  Q,. 

Jendum.'—  1™  2d»e  Q.  9.  Art.  3.  83.  Art.  1. 

'  Liberum  arbitrium  est  causa  sui  '  De  ratione  voluntarii  est   quod 

motus  :  quia  homo  per  liberum  ar-  principium  ejus  sit  intra  ;  sed  non 

bitrium  seipsum  movet  ad  agendum.  oportet  quod  hoc  principium  intrin- 

Non  tamen  hoc  est  necessitate  liber-  secum    sit  primum  principium  non 

tatis  quod  sit  prima  causa   sui  id  motum  ab  alio.     Unde  motus  volun- 

quod  liberum  est;  sicut  nee  ad  hoc  tarius,  etsi  habeat  principium  proxi- 

quod   aliquid    sit    causa     alterius,  mum  intrinsecum,  tamen  principium 

requiritur    quod    sit    prima   causa  primum  est  ab  extra;  sicut  et  pri- 

ejus.     Deus  igitur  est  prima  causa  mum  principium  motus  naturalis  est 

movens  et  naturales  causas  et  vo-  ab  extra,  quod  scilicet  movet  natu- 

juntarias.      Et    sicut     naturalibus  ram.' — lm»  2lae  Q.  9.  Art.  3. 
causis,  movendo  eas,  non  aufert  quin  '  Ipse  actus  liberi  arbitrii  reduci- 

actus  earum  sint  naturales,  ita  mo-  tur  in  Deum  sicut  in  causam.' — lm* 

\endo  causas  voluntarias,  non  aufert  Q.  23.  Art.  2. 


CHAP.  rx.  of  Necessity.  243 

that  which  was  not  its  combatant,  or  its  coercer,  but  its 
cause.1 

Now  it  is  evident  that  such  a  scheme  as  this  is  necessi 
tarian,  and  is  inconsistent  with  the  ordinary  doctrine  of 
freewill;  because  freewill  is  here  not  truly  self-moving, 
and  an  original  spring  of  action.  It  is  not  a  first  cause, 
but  a  second  cause,  subordinated  to  another  above  it,  which 
sets  it  in  motion.  But  the  will,  as  a  link  in  a  chain  of 
causes  and  effects,  is  not  freewill,  in  the  common  and  true 
understanding  of  that  term,  according  to  which  it  means 
an  original  source  of  action.  Freewill  is  here  reconciled 
and  made  consistent  with  the  Divine  Power ;  brought  into 
the  same  scheme  and  theory.  But  it  is  of  itself  a  sufficient 
test  that  a  system  is  necessitarian,  that  it  maintains  the 
Divine  Power  in  harmony  with  freewill.  The  will  as  an 
original  spring  of  action  is  irreconcilable  with  the  Divine 
Power,  a  second  first  cause  in  nature  being  inconsistent 
with  there  being  only  one  First  Cause.  To  reconcile  free 
will,  then,  with  the  Divine  Power  is  to  destroy  it ;  because 
such  a  reconciliation  can  only  be  effected  by  subordinating 
one  to  the  other,  in  the  way  just  described,  as  second  cause 
to  first  cause,  and  so  depriving  the  will  of  that  which  con 
stitutes  its  freedom,  in  the  common  acceptation  of  the 
word,  viz.  its  originality.  Freewill  to  be  true  freewill 
must  be  inconsistent  with  the  other  great  truth  ;  it  must 
be  held  as  something  existing  side  by  side  with  the  Divine 
Attribute,  but  never  uniting  to  our  understanding  with  it. 
This  inconsistency,  this  absence  of  relation,  is  the  only 
security  for  its  genuineness  ;  the  removal  of  which  is,  there 
fore,  fatal  to  it.  When,  in  the  place  of  philosophical  dis 
agreement,  we  have  philosophical  unity,  one  consistent 
scheme  and  theory,  one  connection  of  part  with  part,  one 

1  '  Hsecigitur  coactionis  necessitas  dum  inclinationem  voluntatis.  Sicut 

omnino  repugnat   voltmtati.     Nam  ergo  impossibile  est    quod   aliquid 

hoc  dicimus  esse  violentum  quod  est  simul  sit  violentum  et  naturale ;  ita 

contra  inclinationem  rei.  Ipseautem  impossibile  est  quod  aliquid  simpli- 

motus  voluntatis  est  inclinatio  quae-  citer  sit  coactum,  sive  vioientum,  et 

dam  in  aliquid :  et  ideo,  sicut  dicitur  voluntarium.  Necessitas  autem  na- 

aliquid  naturale,  quia  est  secundum  turalis   non   repugnat  voluntati.' — 

inclinationem   naturae  ;    ita  dicitur  lm"  Q.  82.  A.  4. 
aliquid  voluntarium,  quia  est  secun- 

B  2 


244.  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  ix. 

harmony  of  cause  with  cause,  we  have,  in  the  place  of  two 
truths,  one  truth,  and  the  Divine  Power  is  maintained,  but 
freewill  is  abandoned. 

Such  a  compact  and  harmonious  theory,  however,  en 
countered  in  limine  one  great  difficulty.  Upon  the  idea 
of  the  Divine  Power,  thus  singly  and  determinately  carried 
out,  and  made  the  exclusive  rationale  of  all  the  facts  in 
the  universe,  how  were  we  to  account  for  the  origin  of 
evil  ?  The  existence  of  evil  was  a  plain  fact.  Was  Grod 
the  cause  of  it  ?  That  could  not  be ;  for  Grod  could  not 
possibly  will  evil.  Did  it  exist  in  spite  of  Him,  and  against 
His  will  ?  That  could  not  be  ;  for  God  could  not  possibly 
be  deficient  in  power.  Then  how  was  its  existence  to  be 
accounted  for  ? 

Now,  evil  is  sometimes  understood  in  a  negative  rather 
than  in  a  positive  sense, — in  the  sense  of  a  defect  and  fall 
ing  short,  of  lesser  as  contrasted  with  greater  good ;  and 
in  this  sense  it  was  not  difficult  to  account  for  the  existence 
of  evil  in  the  universe.  For  if  we  considered  it  inconsistent 
with  the  justice  and  benevolence  of  Grod,  that  He  should 
not  make  everything  the  very  best,  where  were  we  to  stop 
in  our  demand  ?  We  could  not  pause  till  we  reached  in 
our  wishes  the  very  highest  point  of  all,  and  arrived  at  the 
Uncreated  Perfection  itself.  Wherever  we  stopped  below 
this  culminating  point,  the  same  charge  could  be  urged  as 
now,  that  things  were  not  made  so  good  as  they  could  be 
made.  But  a  desire  that  tended  straight  to  the  confusion 
of  the  distinction  between  the  creature  and  Grod,  and  could 
not  be  satisfied  but  by  a  contradiction,  was  absurd ;  and  a 
charge  which  would  always  be  made,  whatever  the  Creator 
might  do,  was  untenable.  The  possibility,  then,  of  things 
being  made  better  argued  no  envy  in  Grod  who  made  them 
worse,  and  the  existence  of  evil,  in  the  sense  of  lesser  good, 
was  no  real  difficulty  at  all.1 

1  '  Cuilibet  finite  possibilis  est  ad-  sibi  debetur  quam  secundum  deter- 

ditio  ;  sed  cujuslibet  creaturae  boni-  urination  em    divinse    voluntatis,  et 

tas  finita  est.     Ergo  potest  sibi  fieri  ideo  nulla  invidia  in  Deo  resultat, 

additio,  sed  creatura  nunquam  po-  si  rem  meliorem  facere  potuit  quam 

test  attingere  ad  sequalitatem  Dei.  fecerit.' — Aquinas,   in  Lomb.  Dist. 

Nee  alia  mensura  divinae  bonitatis  43.  Q.  1.  A.  1. 


CHAP.  ix.  of  Necessity.  245 

But  evil  existed  in  the  world,  not  only  in  the  sense  of 
lesser  good,  but  in  that  of  positive  evil ;  and  this  was  a 
more  difficult  fact  to  account  for.  The  explanations  of  this 
fundamental  difficulty,  then,  by  the  Augustinian  school 
men  may  be  placed  under  two  heads :  under  the  first 
of  which  the  explanation  is  almost  purely  verbal,  and  can 
hardly  be  said  to  come  into  contact  even  with  the  real 
difficulty ;  while  under  the  second  the  difficulty  is  really 
confronted,  and  an  effort  of  a  philosophical  kind  made  to 
solve  it. 

I.  The  first  of  these  verbal  explanations  which  I  will 
instance,  and  which  is  a  rather  extreme  specimen  of  its 
class,  is  an  attempt  to  pare  down  by  simple  artifices  of 
language  the  opposition  of  the  Divine  Will  to  evil,  till  it 
reaches  a  point  at  which  it  substantially  ceases,  and  becomes 
a  manageable  truth  to  the  metaphysician.  It  is  evident 
that,  so  long  as  the  opposition  of  the  Divine  Will  to  evil 
remains  decided  and  absolute,  there  being  this  evil  as  a 
plain  fact  in  the  world,  such  opposition  affects  the  attri 
bute  of  the  Divine  Power ;  because  if  (rod  does  not  will 
evil,  it  would  appear  that  evil  takes  place  only  because 
He  has  not  the  power  to  prevent  it.  The  aim,  therefore, 
was  to  reduce  by  niceties  of  expression  this  opposition  of 
the  Divine  Will,  until  that  will  ceased  to  disagree  with 
evil,  and,  as  a  consequence,  its  frustration  ceased  ;  and 
with  it  the  danger  to  the  attribute  of  Power.  A  distinc 
tion  was  accordingly  drawn  between  '  God  not  willing  evil 
— mala  velle '  and  God  not  willing  that  evil  should  take 
place — velle  mala  non  fieri ;  and,  allowing  that  God  did 
not  will  evil,  it  was  determined  that  He  did  will  that  evil 
should  take  place.  Again,  those  who  objected  to  this  posi 
tion  as  being  opposed  to  the  goodness  of  the  Divine  Will, 
made  a  distinction  between  '  God  not  willing  that  evil 
should  take  place '  and  '  God  willing  that  evil  should  not 
take  place ; '  accepting  the  former,  but  rejecting  the  latter 
formula,  the  difference  being  in  the  situation  of  the  nega 
tive  adverb  in  the  two  statements  ;  which  in  the  one  is 
next  to  « willing,'  in  the  other  to  '  taking  place ;'  and  these 


Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  IK. 


denied  accordingly  that  '  God  willed  that  evil  should  not 
take  place.'  *  Here,  then,  are  two  modifications  of  the 
opposition  of  the  Divine  will  to  evil,  one  professing  to  be 
an  improvement  on  the  other.  But  it  is  obvious  that  such 
modifications  are  no  more  than  plays  on  words,  and  can 
lead  to  no  result  ;  because  in  proportion  as  these  state 
ments  reduce  the  opposition  of  the  Divine  Will  to  evil, 
they  cease  to  be,  in  their  natural  meaning,  true  ;  while  in 
proportion  as  an  artificial  interpretation  relieves  them  of 
falsehood,  it  divests  them  also  of  use  for  the  purpose  for 
which  they  are  wanted.  They  either  deny  a  characteristic 
of  the  Divine  Will,  and  in  that  case  they  are  false  ;  or  they 
admit  it,  and  in  that  case  they  fail  of  their  object  of  re 
lieving  the  attribute  of  the  Divine  Power. 

Again,  a  distinction  was  made  between  the  Divine 
Will  and  the  signs  of  it,  —  voluntas  and  signa  voluntatis  ; 
between  the  will  itself  of  God,  and  those  outward  expres 
sions  of  it  which  were  given  in  accommodation  to  our 
understandings  and  for  the  practical  purposes  of  life  and 

1  'Alii  dicunt  quod  Deus  vult  mala  malum  fieri,  cum  scriptum  est,  Kom. 

esse   vel  fieri,  non  tamen  vult  mala.  9.,  voluntatiejus  quis  resistit  ?  Supra 

Alii  vero  quod  nee  vult  mala  esse  nee  etiam  dixit  Augustinus  quia  necesse 

fieri.     In  hoc  tamen  conveniunt  et  est  fieri  si  voluerit.     Sed  vult  mala 

hi    et   illi    quod    utrique    fatentur  fieri  aut  non  fieri.    Si  vult  non  fieri 

Deum  mala  non  velle.     Utrique  vero  non    fiunt  ;  fiunt  autem,  vult  ergo 

rationibus  et  auctoritatibus  utuntur  fieri. 

ad  muniendam   suam    assertionem.  '  Illi  vero  qui  dicunt  Dei  voluntate 

Qui  enim  dicunt  Deum  mala  velle  mala  non  fieri  vel  non  esse,  inductio- 

esse  vel  fieri   suam  his  modis  mu-  nibus  prsemissis  ita  respondent,  di- 

niunt  intentionem.      Si  enim,    in-  centes  Deum   nee   velle    mala  fieri, 

quiunt,  mala  non   esse  vel  non  fieri  nee  velle  non  fieri,  vel  nolle  fieri,  sed 

vellet,  nullo  modo  essent  vel  fierent,  tantum  non  velle  fieri.  Sienim  vellet 

quia  si  vult  ea  non  esse   vel  non  ea  fieri  vel  esse,  faceret  utique  ea 

fieri,  et  non  potest  id  efficere,  scilicet  fieri   vel   esse,    et  ita    esset   auctor 

ut  non  sint  vel  non  fiant,  voluntati  malorum.  .  .  .  Item  si  nollet  mala 

ejus  et  potentise  aliquid  resistit,  et  fieri,  vel  vellet  non  fieri,  et  tamen 

non  est  omnipotens,  quia  non  potest  fierent,  omnipotens  non  esset.  .  .  . 

quod  vult,  sed  impotens  est  sicut  et  Ideoque  non  concedunt  Deum  velle 

nos  sumus,  qui  quod  volumus  quan-  mala  fieri   ne   malorum   auctor  in- 

doque    non   possumus.      Sed    quia  telligatur,  nee  concedunt  eum  velle 

omnipotens  est  et  in  nullo  impotens,  mala  non   fieri,   ne   impotens  esse 

certum  est  non  posse  fieri  mala  vel  videatur,   sed   tantum    dicunt   eum 

esse  nisi  eo  volente.  Quomodo  enim  non  velle  mala  fieri'  —  Lombard,  1.  1. 

invito  eo  et  uolente  posset  ab  aliquo  Dist.  46. 


CHAP.    IX. 


of  Necessity. 


247 


conduct, — precept,  prohibition,  permission,  and  the  like — 
praceptio,  prohibitio^  permissio ;  between  a  real  and  a 
metaphorical  will  of  Grod, — the  one  being  called  voluntas 
beneplaciti,  the  other  voluntas  signi.1  And  the  object  of 
this  distinction  is  the  same  with  that  of  the  preceding 
ones ;  viz.  to  enable  the  theologian  to  refer  to  a  Divine 
Will,  which  was  in  some  way  not  opposed  to  evil,  and  with 
which,  therefore,  evil  could  co-exist  without  risk  to  the 
attribute  of  the  Divine  Power.  That  will  of  Grod  which 
came  into  contact  with  our  understandings,  which  com 
manded  and  which  prohibited,  was  opposed  to  evil ;  and 
this  will  could  be  violated,  neglected,  and  trodden  under 
foot  by  the  passion  and  the  pride  of  man.  But  that  secret 
and  ulterior  will  which  lay  behind  this  external  and  ex- 


1  '  Aliquando  vero  secundum  quan- 
dam  figuram  dicendi  voluntas  Dei 
vocatur,  quod  seeundum  proprieta- 
tem  non  est  voluntas  ejus  :  ut  prae- 
ceptio,  prohibitio,  consilium,  ideoque 
pluraliter  aliquando  Scriptura  vo- 
luntates  Dei  pronuntiat.  Unde 
Propheta  psalm  1 1 0.  Magna  opera 
Domini,  exquisita  in  omnes  volun- 
tates  ejus,  cum  non  sit  nisi  una  vo 
luntas  Dei  quae  ipse  est.  .  .  .  Ideo 
autem  praeceptio  et  prohibitio  atque 
consilium,  cum  sint  tria,  dicitur 
tamen  unumquodque  eorum  Dei  vo 
luntas,  quia  ista  sunt  signa  divinae 
voluntatis  :  quemadmodum  et  signa 
irae  dicuntur  ira,  et  dilectionis  signa 
dilectioappellantur;  et  dicitur  iratus 
Deus,  et  tamen  non  est  ira  in  eo 
flliqua,  sed  signa  tan  turn  quae  foris 
fiunt,  quibus  iratus  ostenditur,  ira 
ipsius  nominantur.  Et  est  figura 
dicendi,  secundum  quam  non  est 
falsum  quod  dicitur,  sedverum  quod 
dicitur  sub  tropi  nubilo  obumbratur. 
Et  secundum  hos  tropos  diversae 
voluutates  Dei  dicuntur,  quia  di- 
versa  sunt  ilia  quae  per  tropum  vo 
luntas  Dei  dicuntur. 

'  Magna  est  adhibenda  discretio 
in  cognitione  Divinae  voluntatis,  quia 
et  beneplacitum  Dei  est  volumas 


ejus,  et  signum  beneplaciti  ejus  dici 
tur  voluntas  ejus.  Sed  beneplaci- 
tum  ejus  aeternum  est,  signum  vero 
beneplaciti  ejus  non.'— Lombard,  1. 
1.  Dist.  45. 

'Voluntas  Dei  distinguitur  in 
voluntatem  beneplaciti  et  voluntatem 
signi.  .  .  De  Deo  quaedam  dicuntur 
proprie,  quaedam  metaphorice.  Ea 
quae  proprie  de  ipso  dicuntur,  vere 
in  eo  sunt ;  sed  ea,  quae  metaphorice 
dicuntur  de  eo,  per  similitiidinem 
proportionabilitatis  ad  effectum  ali- 
quem,  sicut  dicitur  ignis  Deutero. 
4.,  eo  quod  sicut  ignis  se  habet  ad 
consumptionem  contrarii,  ita  Deus 
ad  consumendam  nequitiam.  .  .  . 
Deus  potest  did  aliquid  velle  dupli- 
citer ;  vel  proprie,  et  sic  dicitur  velle 
Uhid,  cujus  voluntas  vere  in  eo  est, 
et  hcec  est  voluntas  beneplaciti.  Dici 
tur  etiam  aliquid  velle  metaphorice, 
eo  quod  ad  modum  volentis  se  habet, 
in  quantum  prcecipit,  vel  consulit, 
vel  aliquid  hujusmodi  facit.  Unde 
ea,  in  qiiibus  attenditur  similitudo 
istius  rei  ad  voluntatem  Dei,  volun- 
tates  ejus  metaphorice  dicuntur,  et 
quia  talia  sunt  effectus,  dicuntur 
signa! — Aquinas,  in  Lomb.  1.  1. 
Dist.  45.  A.  4. 


248  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  ix. 

pressed  one,  was  not  opposed  to  any,  but  harmonised  with 
all  facts  ;  and  evil  was  no  rebel  against  it,  but  its  subject ; 
nothing  impeded,  then,  but  everything  in  heaven  and  earth 
fulfilled  this  eternal,  incomprehensible  Will,  which  was  of 
the  essence  of  God,  and  which  was  God. 

Now,  this  distinction  is  drawn  with  greater  breadth, 
boldness,  and  strength  than  the  preceding  ones  ;  but  it  is 
open  to  the  same  answer,  viz.  that  so  far  as  it  denies  the 
disagreement  of  the  Divine  Will  with  evil  it  is  false,  so 
far  as  it  admits  it  it  is  useless  for  its  purpose.  This  posi 
tion  of  a  real  will  of  God  which  is  different  from  His 
expressed  will  may  be  interpreted  in  two  ways.  It  may 
be  understood  as  meaning  that  the  real  will  of  God  is  in 
true  and  actual  harmony  with  evil,  the  expressed  being 
only  an  outside  show,  which  is  useful  in  some  way  for  the 
Divine  government  of  mankind  in  this  present  state,  and 
the  maintenance  of  this  existing  system.  And  a  theory 
like  this  has  been  put  forward  in  modern  times,  represent 
ing  the  Divine  Will,  as  expressed  in  the  distinction  of  good 
and  evil,  as  a  mere  mask,  concealing  a  deeper  truth  behind 
it ;  a  truth  of  pure  fact,  in  which  good  and  evil  meet  and 
are  united,  and  each  is  good.  The  commands  and  prohibi 
tions,  the  promises  and  the  terrors  of  the  moral  law,  are 
according  to  such  a  theory  but  a  display,  which  deludes 
the  mass,  but  is  penetrated  by  the  philosopher.  And 
understood  in  such  a  way  this  position  does  indeed  get  rid 
most  effectually  of  the  difficulty  of  the  existence  of  evil 
as  being  against  the  will  of  God,  and  so  a  sign  against 
His  Power.  But  then,  understood  in  such  a  way,  this 
position  is  false  and  impious.  We  cannot  suppose  any 
difference  between  the  real  and  the  expressed  will  of  God,1 
without  destroying  the  basis  of  all  morals  and  religion. 

1  '  Et  si  ilia  dicantur  Dei  voluntas,  fieret,   sed  ut   Abrahse   probaretur 

ideo  quia  signa  sunt  Divinse  volun-  fides ;  et  in  evangelic  prsecepit  sa- 

tatis,  non  est  tamen  intelligendum  nato    ne    cui    diceret ;    ille  autem 

Deum  omne  illud  fieri   velle  quod  prsedicavit  ubique,  intelligens  Deum 

cuicunque   prsecipit,  vel    non    fieri  non   ideo   prohibuisse,    quin  vellet 

quod     prohibuit.      Prsecepit    enim  opus  suum  prsedicari,  sed  ut  daret 

Abrahse  immolare  filium,  nee  tamen  formam   homini,  laudem  humanam 

voluit;    nee   ideo    prsecepit    ut    id  declinandi.' — Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  45. 


CHAP.  ix.  of  Necessity.  249 

But  if  tins  position  does  not  mean  this,  as  in  the  minds  of 
those  who  maintained  it  it  did  not,  it  is  not  available  for 
the  object  for  which  it  is  designed.  For  all  it  means  to 
assert  in  that  case  is  the  incomprehensibility  of  the  Divine 
Will,  and  that  there  is  some  mysterious  sense  in  which 
everything  which  takes  place  agrees  with  this  will ;  bub 
this  is  not  to  explain  the  difficulty  of  the  co-existence  of 
evil  with  that  will,  but  only  to  state  it. 

A  distinction,  again,  was  drawn  between  an  antecedent 
will  of  Grod — voluntas  antecedens,  and  a  posterior  will — 
voluntas  consequens  ;  the  former  of  which  willed  a  thing 
absolutely — simpliciter,  the  latter  conditionally — secun- 
dum  quid1-,  and  the  former  of  which  was  opposed  to  evil, 
the  latter  not.  Thus  God  willed  the  salvation  of  all  men 
on  the  one  hand  absolutely  ;  and  that  will,  which  was 
opposed  to  all  evil,  to  sin  and  punishment  alike,  could  be 
frustrated — imperfectio  antecedentis  voluntatis.  But,  on 
the  other  hand,  He  willed  this  salvation  conditionally — i.e. 
on  the  supposition  that  men  were  good  ;  and  this  will, 
which  was  not  opposed  to  the  evil  of  punishment  if  men 
were  bad,  could  not  be  frustrated,  being  as  much  fulfilled 
in  the  damnation  of  men  as  in  their  salvation.  This  dis 
tinction,  then,  had  the  same  aim  as  the  former ;  viz.,  to 
establish  a  Divine  Will  which  was  not  opposed  to  evil,  and 
which  therefore  the  existence  of  evil  did  not  frustrate,  and 
so  interfere  with  the  Divine  Power.  But  while  the  diffi 
culty  which  this  distinction  professes  to  meet  is  in  the  case 
of  the  will  antecedent  simply  confessed  instead  of  solved, 
it  is  only  evaded  instead  of  solved  in  the  case  of  the  will 
consequent.  Grod  wills  the  salvation  of  men  on  the  con 
dition  that  they  are  good ;  which  will,  if  they  are  bad,  is 

1  '  Voluntas  Dei  duplex,    antece-  — Aquinas,  in  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  46. 

dens   et   consequens  .    .    .   propter  Q.  1.  A.  1. 

diversas  conditiones  ipsius  voliti.  Si  '  Quicquid  vult   Deus     voluntate 

in  homine   tantum     natura   ipsius  consequent!  totum    fit,   non  autem 

consideretur,  aequaliter   bonum  est  quicquid  vult  voluntate  antecedent! ; 

omnem    hominem    salvari,    et    hoc  quia  hoc  non  simpliciter  vult,   sed 

Deus  vult,  et  hsec  est  voluntas  ante-  secundum   quid  tantum  ;    nee   ista 

cedens.    .    .    .    Consideratis   autem  imperfectio  est  ex  parte  voluntatis, 

circumstantiis,    non     vult    omnem  sed  ex  conditione  voliti.' — In  Lomb. 

.  .  .  non  volentem  et  resistentem.'  Dist.  47.  Q.  1.  A.  1. 


250  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  ix. 

not  opposed  to  the  evil  of  their  punishment.  The  evil  of 
punishment,  then,  is  here  accounted  for  and  made  to 
agree  with  the  Divine  Power,  because  made  to  agree  with 
the  Divine  Will :  but  what  account  is  given  of  the  evil  of 
that  sin  which  is  the  reason  of  punishment  ?  This  evil  is 
passed  over  altogether.  Yet  it  is  a  plain  evil  which  takes 
place  in  the  universe,  and  we  must  either  say  that  the  will 
of  God  is  opposed  to  it  or  not;  the  former  alternative 
being  apparently  inconsistent  with  the  Divine  Power,  the 
latter  with  the  Divine  Goodness.  The  difficulty  put  off 
at  one  stage  thus  meets  us  at  another ;  and  an  evil  remains 
which  we  cannot  without  impiety  assert  not  to  be  opposed 
to  the  Divine  Will,  and  the  existence  of  which  therefore  is 
inconsistent  apparently  with  the  Divine  Power. 

II.  To  these  verbal  explanations,  however,  there  suc 
ceeded  two  which  were  attempts  at  real  explanation.  One 
of  these  was  the  argument  of  variety,  which  was  put  in 
two  forms ;  under  the  first  of  which,  however,  it  did  not 
satisfy  its  own  employers,  who  used  it  with  evident  mis 
givings,  though  they  would  not  deprive  themselves  of  its 
aid  altogether.  Should  there  not  be  evil  in  the  world, 
that  the  contrast  may  heighten  the  good  and  set  it  off  to 
better  advantage  ?  Would  the  good  be  appreciated  as  it 
should  be,  and  its  real  nature  come  to  light,  but  for  this 
evil  ?  And  in  this  way  is  not  evil  of  the  perfection  of  the 
universe — de  perfections  universi?  The  solution  was  a 
tempting  one  ;  but  it  was  resisted,  on  the  ground  that  the 
loss  which  evil  caused  was  greater  than  the  compensation 
it  gave  for  it ;  inasmuch  as  it  took  away  absolute  good, 
and  only  gave  comparative.1  The  solid  justice  of  this 

1  '  Illud  sine  quo  universum  me-  tionale  of  the  existence  of  evil  with 

lius  esset  non  confert  ad  perfecti-  approval:  '  Dicendum  quod  ex  ipsa 

onem  universi :  sed  si  malum  non  bonitate  Divina  ratio  sumi  potest 

esset  universum  melius  esset,  quia  prsedestinationis  aliquorum  et  repro- 

malum  plus  tollit  uni  quam  addit  bationis  aliquorum.  .  .  .  Ad  com- 

alteri,  quia  ei  cujus  est  tollit  boni-  pletionem  enim universi  requiruntur 

tatem  absolutam,  alteri  autem  ad-  diversi  gradus  rerum,  quarum  quse- 

dit  bonitatem  comparationis.' — In  dam  altumetqusedaminfiinum  locum 

Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  46.  Q.  1.  A.  3.  teneant  in  universo.' — Sum.  Theol. 

Yet  Aquinas  reverts  to  this  ra-  lma  Q.  23.  A.  5. 


OHA?.  ix.  of  Necessity.  251 

reply  embraces  within  a  short  compass  all  the  points  of 
the  case.  Variety  is  a  sound  explanation  indeed  of  a  cer 
tain  class  of  evil.  The  decay  and  corruption  of  the  vege 
table  world  set  off  by  contrast  the  birth  and  growth; 
summer  is  all  the  more  agreeable  for  winter  ;  the  decay  of 
autumn  heightens  the  freshness  of  the  spring.  And  on 
the  same  law  rest  is  all  the  more  pleasant  after  fatigue, 
food  after  hunger;  and  much  even  of  the  higher  and  more 
intellectual  kind  of  pleasure  is  relished  the  more  for  the 
void  and  dulness  alternating  with  it.  But  this  is  only  by 
a  law  of  our  nature  in  present  operation,  in  consequence 
of  which  change  is  necessary  for  us,  though  at  the  cost  of 
pain.  Such  a  law  is  acknowledged  to  be  a  sign  of  great 
imperfection.  And,  what  is  more  to  the  purpose,  all  these 
are  cases  in  which  ourselves  alone  and  our  own  enjoyment 
are  concerned.  To  inanimate  nature  it  is  all  the  same 
whether  it  decays  or  endures,  lives  or  dies ;  and  therefore 
we  need  not  take  its  part  in  the  matter  into  account. 
But  when  we  come  to  moral  evil  the  case  is  very  different. 
It  is  true  the  law  of  comparison  or  contrast  operates  even 
here,  and  we  are  pleased  with  the  virtue  which  meets  us 
in  the  world,  all  the  more  for  the  evil  which  we  see  in  it. 
Indeed,  the  nature  or  quality  of  goodness — the  light  that 
issues  from  a  good  character,  is  so  completely  seen  in  the 
sense  and  degree  in  which  we  do  see  it,  by  means  of  this 
assistance — i.e.  by  the  contrast  between  this  goodness  and 
a  background  of  average  and  indifferent  character,  formed 
as  an  image  in  our  mind  from  the  experience  of  human 
life — that  it  is  difficult  to  contemplate  without  some  sur 
prise  and  awe  the  signal  and  noble  use  which  the  wicked 
ness  of  the  world  answers  ;  inasmuch  as  for  anything  we 
see  to  the  contrary,  in  the  present  state  of  our  capacities, 
in  which  contrast  seems  to  be  so  essential  to  true  percep 
tion,  virtue  could  not  be  appreciated  as  it  is  without  this 
contrast,  or  be  the  bright  light  which  it  is  without  this 
dark  background.  The  light  shineth  in  darkness.  But 
though  moral  evil  answers  this  high  purpose  in  the  world, 
is  it  a  sufficient  account  of  its  existence  that  it  does  so  ? 
Is  it  just  that  one  man  should  be  wicked  in  order  that  the 


252  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  ix. 

virtue  of  another  may  be  set  off  ?  The  spectator  may  de 
rive  benefit  from  the  contrast,  but  there  is  another  whose 
interests  are  quite  as  important  as  his. 

And  the  same  may  be  said  of  the  use  of  which  the 
moral  evil  in  the  world  is,  for  the  trial,  purification,  and 
confirmation  of  the  good.  The  wickedness  of  the  bad 
portion  of  mankind  is  indeed  one  of  the  principal  means 
by  which  the  good  portion  is  educated  and  disciplined ; 
the  pride  and  tyranny  of  one  man  serve  to  produce  the 
virtue  of  patience  in  another;  the  wrongs  of  the  world 
subdue  and  temper,  its  corruptions  and  temptations  fortify, 
those  minds  that  are  disposed  to  make  this  use  of  them. 
But  though  the  schoolman  appeals  to  this  effect  of  moral 
evil  as  a  j  ustification  of  its  existence,1  such  an  argument 
admits  of  the  obvious  answer,  that  it  is  not  just  that  one 
man  should  be  wicked  in  order  that  another  should  be  good. 

The  argument  of  variety,  however,  was  put  in  another 
form,  and  another  explanation  extracted  from  it.  The 
principle  of  variety  demanded  that  there  should  be  differ 
ent  natures  in  the  universe  ;  and  that,  besides  such  natures 
as  were  subject  to  necessary  laws,  there  should  be  other 
nobler  ones  possessing  will.  But  this  conceded,  moral  evil, 
it  was  said,  followed.  For  such  natures  as  the  latter  must, 
as  the  very  condition  of  this  higher  good,  have  the  power 
of  going  wrong  and  receding  from  the  end  designed  for 
them  ;  and,  with  the  power  to  do  so,  the  fact  would  in 
some  instances  take  place.2  Now,  this  is  a  substantially 

'   '  Si  enim  omnia  mala  impedi-  naturam,   quod  est  voluntas,   quod 

rentur,multabonadeessent  universe;  quanto  vicinius    est   Deo,   tanto    a 

rion    enim  esset  vita  leonis,  si  non  necessitate     naturalium     causarum 

esset  occisio  animalium ;  nee   esset  magis    est    liberum.    .  .  .  Et  ideo 

patientia  martyrum  si  non  esset  per-  taliter  a  Deo  instituta  est  ut  deficere 

secutio  tyrannorum.'  — Sum.  Theol.  posset.   ...  Si  autem  inevitabiliter 

lma  Q.  22.  A,  2.  in     finem     tenderet    per    divinam 

'  Multa  bona  tollerentur,  si  Deus  providentiam  tolleretur  sibi  conditio 

nullum    malum   permitteret    esse  ;  suse  naturae.' — In  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist. 

non    enim    generaretur    ignis    nisi  39.  Q.  2.  A.  2. 

corrumperetur    aer;  neque    conser-  '  Perfectio    Universi    requirit  ut 

varetur  vita  leonis,  nisi  occideretur  sint  qusedam  quse  a  bonitate  deficere 

asinus.' — Q,.  48.  A.  2.  possint :  ad  quod  sequitur  ea  inter- 

2  'Sed.in   nobilioribus  creaturis  dnm  deficere.' — Sum.   Theol.   I01*  Q. 

invenitur  aliud   principium   prater  48.  A.  2. 


ix.  of  Necessity.  253 

different  argument  from  the  former,  and  is  perhaps  the 
nearest  approach  we  can  make  to  an  account  of  the  exist 
ence  of  moral  evil  in  the  world.  But  it  is  in  truth  no 
explanation  ;  for  is  this  will  of  the  creature  to  which  evil 
is  referred  an  original  cause  or  only  a  secondary  one?  If 
the  former,  this  argument  only  explains  one  difficulty  by 
another  as  great,  the  existence  of  evil  by  the  existence  of 
an  original  cause  in  nature  besides  God.  If  the  latter, 
the  existence  of  moral  evil  falls  back,  as  before,  upon  the 
First  Cause ;  the  human  will  in  that  case  being  no  such 
barrier  intervening  between  moral  evil  and  God,  as  is 
wanted  for  the  present  purpose. 

But  the  principal  explanation  which  was  given  of  this 
difficulty,  and  that  in  which  Aquinas  appears  finally  to 
repose,  was  borrowed  from  his  master.  Every  reader  of  S. 
Augustine  is  familiar  with  a  certain  view  of  the  nature  of 
evil,  to  which  he  constantly  recurs,  and  which  he  seems  to 
cherish  in  his  mind  as  a  great  moral  discovery,  a  funda 
mental  set-off  and  answer  to  the  great  difficulty  of  the 
existence  of  evil,  and  the  true  and  perfect  mode  of  extri 
cating  the  Divine  attribute  of  Power  from  the  responsibility 
of  permitting  it, — the  position,  viz.  that  evil  is  nothing — 
nifiil.  God  was  the  source  ;  and  as  being  the  source  of, 
included  and  comprised,  all  existence.  Evil  was  a  depar 
ture  from  God.  Evil,  therefore,  was  a  departure  from 
existence.  External  to  God,  it  was  outside  of  all  being 
and  substance  ;  i.e.  was  no-being  or  nothing. 

Aquinas  adopts  this  position,  and  improves  upon  it  in 
his  usual  way.  Evil  was  nothing  in  another  sense  besides 
that  of  pure  negation,  which  is  the  common  meaning  of 
nothing,  viz.,  that  of  privation.  Every  nature  aimed  at 
good  as  its  perfection  or  true  existence ;  evil  was  a  depri 
vation  of  this  good  or  true  existence.  In  the  case  of  evil, 
then,  there  was  something  in  our  idea  antecedent  to  it,  of 
which  it  was  a  loss  or  absence.  That  which  every  nature 
truly  and  properly  was,  was  in  scholastic  language  its  form, 
whence  the  formal  cause  of  a  thing  is  that  which  makes  a 
thing  to  be  what  it  is.  Evil  was  a  privation  of  form. 
There  was  an  end,  and  there  was  an  action  proper  to  every 


254  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  ix. 

thing  in  the  universe  ;  evil  was  inordination  to  the  end,  a 
defect  of  action.1  The  evil  proper  to  the  nature  of  fire  was 
cold;  the  evil  proper  to  the  nature  of  water  was  drought. 
Thus  while,  in  the  collision  of  different  natures  in  the  uni 
verse,  the  defect  of  one  was  the  growth  of  another,  the  evil  to 
each  nature  was  the  defect  of  that  nature.2  Everything, 
so  far  as  it  was,  was  good — omne  ens  in  quantum  hujus- 
modi  bonum;  and  evil  was  no-thing — non-ens,  and  no 
part  of  the  universe.3 

And  that  which  was  true  of  evil  in  general,  was  true  in 
particular  of  moral  evil.  The  act  of  sin  was  defined  as  an 
act  contrary  to  the  end  for  which  the  moral  creature  is 
designed,  or,  as  is  expressed  in  modern  language,  to  the 
constitution  of  man — actus  inordinatus  ;  which  consisted, 
however,  of  two  separate  and  distinct  parts.  The  act — 
actus  peccati — was  simply  the  material,  bodily  or  mental, 
employed  in  the  sin,  whether  outward  motion,  or  inward 
passion,  feeling,  desire  ;  and  this  was  real  substance  and 
part  of  the  universe  of  God.  A  man  who  committed,  for 
example,  an  act  of  intemperance  or  anger,  sinned  with  and 
by  the  natural  sensation  of  hunger  or  thirst,  or  the  natural 
passion  or  resentment,  as  the  internal  material  of  his  sin ; 
he  sinned  with  the  motion  of  his  mouth  by  which  he  eat 
or  drank,  or  with  a  motion  of  his  arm  by  which  he  struck 
a  blow,  as  its  external  material.  All  these  motions,  then, 
considered  simply  as  such,  whether  within  or  without,  were 

1    '  Causam     formalem      nullam  absentia  boni. — lma  Q.  48.  A.  t. 
habet,  sed  est  magis  privatio  formes :  2  '  Corruptio  aeris  et  aquae  est  ex 

et  similiter  nee  causam  finalem,  sed  perfectione  ignis.    ...    Si  sit  de- 

magis  est  privatio  ordinis  adfinem.'  fectus  in  effectu  proprio  ignis,  puta 

—Sum.  Theol.  I™*  Q.  49.  A.  1.  quod  deficiat  a  calefaciendo,  hoc  est 

'Malum  quod  in  defectu  actionis  propter  defectum  actionis,  sed  hoc 

consistit,  semper  causatur  ex  defectu  ipsum  quod  est  esse  deficiens  accidit 

agentis.' — A.  2.  bono  cui  per   se  competit  agere.' — 

Cum  omnis  natura  appetat  suum  lma  Q.  49.  A.  1. 

esse  et  suam  profectionem,  necesse  3  Nihil    potest    esse    per    suam 

est  dicere  quod  et  perfectio  cujus-  essentiam  malum. — lma  Q.  49.  A.  3. 

cunque     naturae    rationem     habeat  Malum  non  est  pars  universi  quia 

bonitatis.     Unde   non    potest    esse  neque    habet    naturam   substantiae 

quod   malum     significet     quoddam  neque    accidentis,    sed    privationis 

esse,    aut    quandam    formam,    seu  tantum.'—  In  Lorn.  1.  1.  Dist.  46.  Q. 

naturam.      Kelinquitur   ergo    quod  1.  A.  3. 
nomine   mali   significetur   qusedam 


CHAP.  TX.  of  Necessity.  255 

substantial ;  and  the  act  of  sin,  as  such,  existed.  But  the 
inordinateness  of  the  act,  or  the  sin  of  it — the  error  in 
the  use  and  application  of  these  natural  passions,  these 
bodily  organs,  was  no  thing.1  As  evil  in  the  case  of  fire 
was  a  defect  of  the  natural  action  of  fire,  so  evil  in  the 
case  of  the  will  was  a  defect  of  the  natural  action  of  the 
will. 

This  position,  then,  was  applied  as  the  key  to  the 
solution  of  the  great  difficulty  of  the  existence  of  evil.  The 
difficulty  of  the  existence  of  evil  respected  its  cause,  how 
evil  had  an  existence  at  all,  when  the  Universal  Cause,  or 
cause  of  everything,  could  not  have  given  it.  It  was  a 
direct  answer,  then,  to  this  difficulty,  to  say  that  it  was  a 
mistake  to  begin  with,  to  suppose  that  evil  had  existence. 
This  original  mistake  removed,  all  was  clear ;  for  that 
which  had  no  existence  needed  no  cause,2  and  that  which 
needed  no  cause  could  dispense  with  the  Universal  Cause. 
A  universal  cause  was  necessary ;  but  this  inconvenience 
attended  it,  viz.  that  it  was  universal,  and  thus  contracted 
responsibilities  from  which  it  had  rather  be  relieved.  This 
rationale  exactly  relieved  it  of  its  inconvenient  charge. 
Evil  was  regarded  in  an  aspect  in  which  it  ceased  to  belong 
to  the  domain  even  of  a  universal  cause.  The  fact  or 
phenomenon  of  evil,  emptied  of  true  or  logical  essence, 
had  no  place  in  the  nature  of  things ;  seen  everywhere,  it 
existed  nowhere,  a  universal  nothing  attending  on  sub 
stance  as  a  shadow,  but  no  occupant  of  room,  and  without 
insertion  in  the  system.  This  unsubstantial  presence,  this 
inane  in  the  midst  of  things,  escaped  as  such  the  action 
of  the  First  Cause  ;  unsusceptible,  as  a  pure  negative,  of 
connection  or  relation,  it  was  in  its  very  nature  a  breaking 
off  from  the  chain  of  causes  and  effects  in  nature,  and  not  a 
link  of  it.3  Had  evil  a  cause,  indeed,  it  could  have  but 

1  '  Peccatum  est  actus  inordina-  lam  habet. — lm*  Q.  49.  A.  1. 
tus.     Ex  parte  igitur  actus  potest  s  '  Effectus  causae  mediae  secundum 

habere  causam,  ex  parte  autem  in-  quod  exit  ordinem  causse  primae  non 

ordinationis  habet  causam  eo  modo  reducitur  in  causam  primam.  .  .  . 

quo  negatio  vel  privatio  potest  ha-  Defectus  a  libero  arbitrio  non  re- 

bere  causam.' — lma  2dae  Q,.  75.  A.  1.  ducitur  in  Deum  sicut  in  causam.' — 

8  Malum  causam  formalem  mil-  lm*  2(1*e  Q,.  79.  A.  l. 


256  Scholastic  Theory  CHAP.  ix. 

one,  viz.  God ;  but  nothing  had  no  cause,  and  was,  there 
fore,  wholly  independent  of  the  Universal  Cause. 

Such   an    explanation    as    this,  however,  it  is  hardly 
necessary  to  say,  is  no  real  explanation  of  the  difficulty. 
It  is  undoubtedly  the  first  truth  of  religion  that  true  being 
and  good  are  identical.    The  same  argument,  which  proves 
a  First  Cause  at  all,  proves  His  goodness ;  and  if  Being  in 
the  Cause  must  be  good,  being  in  the  effect  must  be  good 
too ;  for  the  effect  must  follow  the  nature  of  the  cause. 
Nor  can  we  avoid  this  conclusion  but   by  a  scheme    of 
dualism,  which  allows  an  evil  first  cause  of  being  ;  and, 
therefore,  evil  being  as  its  effect.     So  far  the  above  ra 
tionale  is  true,  and  is   the  proper  contrary  to  dualism. 
But  this  first  truth  of  sound  religion  is,  when  examined, 
no  explanation  of  the  mystery  of  the  existence  of  evil,  but 
only  another  mode  of  stating  it.    We  rightly  say  that  true 
being  is  identical  with  good  ;  but  how  comes  there  to  be 
being  which  is  not  true  being  ?     On  the  religious  ground, 
and  as  believers  in  a  God,  we  say,  that  evil  cannot  be  an 
existing  thing ;  because  God  is  the  Author  of  everything, 
and  yet  not  the  Author  of  evil.     But  plain  common  sense 
tells  us  clearly  enough  that  evil  exists,  and  exists  just  as 
really  as  good.     A  man  commits  some  act  of  violence  under 
the  influence  of  strong  passion,  malignant  hatred,  revenge, 
cupidity  ;  his  state  of  mind  is  as  intense  as  possible;  there 
is  the  fullest  determination  and  absorption  in  the  act.     Is 
not  this  something — something  going  on  and  taking  place 
in  his  mind  ?     We  may  distinguish,  indeed,  between  the 
animus  and  the  material  of  the  act,  or,  in  the  scholastic 
language,  between  the  act  and  the  sin  ;  but  this  distinc 
tion  applies  as  much  to  good  acts  as  to  bad.     The  virtue 
of  a  good  act  is  something  quite  distinct  from  the  feelings 
and  faculties  of  mind  and  body  employed  in  it,  of  which 
it  is  the  direction.     If  virtue,  then,  is  something,  is  not 
vice  something  too  ? 

The  real  source  of  these  argumentative  struggles  and 
vain  solutions  was  the  original  position  respecting  the 
Divine  Power,  which,  however  true,  was  laid  down  without 
that  reserve  which  is  necessary  for  this  kind  of  truth.  It 


CHAP.  TX.  of  Necessity.  257 

is  evident  that  the  Divine  Power  is  incomprehensible  to 
us,  and  that  therefore  we  cannot  proceed  upon  it,  as  if  it 
were  a  known  premiss,  and  argue  upon  the  vague  abstract 
idea  of  omnipotence  in  our  minds  as  if  it  were  the  real 
truth  on  this  subject.  Aquinas  himself  defines  the  Divine 
Power  at  the  outset  with  a  reserve :  it  was  the  power  of 
doing  any  thing  which  was  possible — omnia  possibilia  ; 
and  the  principle  he  lays  down  with  respect  to  the  sense 
in  which  the  Divine  attributes  are  to  be  understood  is 
philosophical ;  viz.  that  they  are  to  be  understood  neither 
as  wholly  the  same  with  (univoce),  or  wholly  different 
from,  the  corresponding  attributes  in  man  (cequivoce\  but 
as  analogous  to  them — analogice.1  The  univocal  sense 
confounded  (rod  with  the  creature  ;  the  equivocal  hid  God 
from  the  creature,  removing  and  alienating  Him  altogether 
as  an  object  of  human  thought ;  the  analogical  allowed  an 
idea  of  Grod,  which  was  true  as  far  as  it  went,  but  imper 
fect.  But  thougli  the  human  mind,  under  scholasticism, 
saw,  as  it  always  must  do  whenever  sane,  its  own  ignor 
ance,  it  did  not  see  it  so  clearly  or  scientifically  as  it  has 
done  subsequently,  when  a  later  philosophy  has  thrown  it 
back  upon  itself,  and  forced  it  to  examine  its  own  ideas, 
how  far  they  go,  and  where  they  stop  short.  The  mediaeval 
mind  forgot,  then,  in  the  conduct  of  the  argument,  the 
principle  it  had  laid  down  at  its  commencement ;  and,  just 
as  a  boy  in  learning  a  problem  of  Euclid  sees  some  critical 
point  of  the  demonstration,  but  does  not  see  it  sufficiently 
clearly,  or  master  it  enough  to  carry  it  with  him  through 
out  the  proof,  the  schoolman  first  saw  that  he  was  ignorant, 
and  then  argued  as  if  he  knew.  Thus,  notwithstanding 
the  preliminary  reserve  in  the  definition  of  the  Divine 

1  '  Tribus  modis  contingit  aliquid  citur  alterum,  ut  quando  idem  nomen 

aliquibus  commune  esse,  velunivoce,  duobus  hominibus  convenit.     Cum 

vel  sequivoce,  vel  analogice.  Univoce  igitur  per  scientiam  noBtram  deve- 

non   potest  aliquid  de   Deo  et    de  niatur  in  cognitionem  Divinse  sci- 

creatura  dici  .  .   .  et  ideo  quidam  entiae,   non    potest    esse    quod    sit 

dicunt   quod    quicquid    de   Deo  et  omnino   aequivocum.     Et    ideo   di- 

creatura  dicitur,  per  puram   aequi-  cendum  quod  scientia  analogice  dici- 

vocationem  dicitur.     Sed  hoc  etiam  tur  de  Deo  et  creatura  ;  et  simihter 

non  potest  esse  quia  in  his  quse  sunt  omnia    hujusmodi.'  —  Aquinas,   in 

pure  aequivoca   ex  uno  non  agnos-  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  35.  Q,.  1.  A.  4. 

8 


258  Scholastic  Theory  of  Necessity.      CHAP.  ix. 

Power,  the  vague  abstract  idea  of  omnipotence  prevailed 
as  if  it  were  a  known  premiss  in  the  argument,  entailing 
these  struggles  with  the  fact  of  evil  as  the  consequences 
of  it ;  for  with  absolute  power  in  God  to  prevent  it,  how 
could  evil  exist  ?  Hence  these  vain  efforts  of  reason,  these 
blind  explanations  ;  for  it  was  necessary  to  reconcile  a 
known  premiss  with  facts.  As  an  unknown  premiss,  the 
Divine  Power  is  in  no  contradiction  to  the  fact  of  evil,  for 
we  must  know  what  a  truth  is  before  we  see  a  contra 
diction  in  it  to  another  truth ;  and  with  no  contradic 
tion,  no  solution  would  have  been  wanted.  But  the 
schoolman  vaguely  fancied  that  he  knew  his  premiss,  and 
therefore  involved  himself  in  these  elaborate  and  futile 
explanations.  We  may  admire  indeed  an  obstinate  intel 
lectual  energy,  which  struggles  against  insuperable  diffi 
culties,  and  tries  to  beat  down  by  force  what  it  cannot 
disentangle,  and  lay  down  a  path  which  must  be  stopped 
at  last.  We  admire  his  resolution,  as  we  would  that  of 
some  strong  animal  caught  in  a  net,  the  thin  meshes  of 
which  it  would  burst  any  moment  with  the  least  part 
of  that  blind  force  which  it  exerts,  were  it  not  that  their 
multiplicity  and  intricacy  baffle  it.  But  the  resignation 
of  the  philosopher  is  to  be  admired  more,  who  has  one  great 
difficulty  at  starting,  and  a  tranquil  path  after  it,  who  sees 
to  begin  with  the  inexplicableness  of  things,  and  is  saved 
by  the  admission  from  the  trouble  of  subsequent  solution. 
The  clear  perception  by  the  mind  of  its  own  ignorance  is 
the  secret  of  all  true  success  in  philosophy  ;  while  explana 
tions  which  assume  that  the  constitution  of  things  can 
really  be  explained,  can  only  be  a  fruitless  waste  of  strength. 
The  fault  of  the  schoolman  throughout  this  whole  argu 
ment  is,  that  he  vaguely  imagines,  that  he  really  can 
explain  the  origin  of  evil ;  that  he  sets  out  with  that  aim  ; 
that  he  really  fancies  himself  in  a  line  of  discovery  while 
he  argues,  and  thinks  that  he  has  in  his  conclusion  some 
thing  of  the  nature  of  a  true  solution.  He  does  not  actu 
ally  profess  so  much,  but  his  general  argument  betrays 
the  latent  assumption  in  his  mind.  His  fault  then  was  a 
want  of  a  clear  and  acute  perception  of  his  own  ignorance ; 


CHAP.  x.     Scholastic  Doctrine  of  Predestination.   259 

such  a  perception  as  the  mind  acquires  by  the  long-sus 
tained  stationary  attitude  of  reflexion  upon  itself.  There 
must  be  a  pause,  a  cessation  from  active  speculation  and 
inference,  from  argument,  from  words,  while  the  reason 
looks  within,  and  observes  itself.  The  passive  attitude  re 
quired  for  this  simple  act  of  sight,  more  difficult  really 
than  all  active  arguing,  requires  a  lull  and  a  calm,  an  in 
terruption  of  the  busy  operations  of  the  mind,  a  voluntary 
suspension  of  the  motion  of  that  whole  machinery  of  active 
thought,  which  is  generally  going  on  in  intellectual  minds, 
and  constitutes  their  normal  state.  But  the  schoolman 
was  always  busy,  always  arguing,  always  in  the  thick  of 
words,  always  constructing  upon  assumption,  and  pushing 
on  to  conclusion  after  conclusion.  He  could  not  afford 
the  time  to  stop  to  examine  fairly  a  single  assumption  on 
which  he  went.  He  had  not  the  patience  to  pause,  and 
look  within.  He  had  other  work  always  to  do,  as  he 
thought  more  important.  A  passive  attitude  was  intoler 
able  to  a  mind  accustomed  exclusively  to  busy  construc 
tion  ;  and  thought  internal  and  without  words  to  one,  to 
whom  words  were  the  great  machinery  by  which  he  thought. 
Put  him  to  such  a  task,  and  he  would  feel  like  a  workman 
without  his  accustomed  tools,  or  like  a  man  of  practical 
talent  and  energy  shut  up  in  a  dark  room  and  told  to  think. 
The  consequence  was,  that  it  was  a  chance  whether  his 
assumptions  were  true  or  false.  When  he  thought  as  a 
man  and  with  mankind  at  large,  they  were  right ;  when 
he  thought  as  a  philosopher  they  were  too  often  mistaken, 
extreme  and  unqualified  when  they  should  have  been  limited, 
and  absolute  when  they  should  have  been  with  a  condition 
and  reserve. 


CHAPTER  X. 

SCHOLASTIC    DOCTRINE    OF    PREDESTINATION. 

THE  last  chapter  explained  the  scholastic  theory  of  the 
physical  predetermination  of  the  will,  or  the  subordination  of 

8   2 


260  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

the  will  to  the  universal  cause — a  philosophical  doctrine  of 
necessity.  To  this  theory  succeeded  the  proper  or  Augus- 
tinian  doctrine  of  predestination,  which  went  upon  the  basis 
of  original  sin.  All  mankind  being  previously  in  a  state 
of  ruin  owing  to  original  sin,  Grod  chose  to  exercise  His 
mercy  upon  some  of  this  whole  mass,  His  judgment  upon 
others ;  to  bring  some  to  glory,  and  others  to  punishment. 
Nor  was  this  Divine  determination  in  favour  of  one,  and 
against  the  other  portion  of  the  human  race,  to  be  attributed 
to  any  foreseen  difference  of  character  between  the  two : 
this  difference  of  character  being  the  effect  of  that  deter 
mination,  instead  of  the  determination  the  effect  of  that 
difference.  On  the  principle  that  the  end  includes  the 
means,  the  predestination  of  the  individual  to  eternal  life 
included  in  it  the  bestowal  of  all  those  qualifications  of 
virtue  and  piety  which  were  necessary  for  his  admission  to 
that  final  state.  These  qualifications  were  therefore  the 
effect,  and  not  the  cause  of  predestination,  for  which  no 
cause  was  to  be  assigned  but  (rod's  sovereign  will  and  plea 
sure.1  Nor  had  the  creature  any  ground  of  complaint 
against  this  Divine  arrangement.  For  all  deserved  eternal 
punishment ;  and  therefore  those  upon  whom  the  punish 
ment  was  inflicted  only  got  their  deserts,  while  those  who 
were  spared  received  a  favour  to  which  they  had  in  justice 
no  right,  and  were  indebted  to  a  gratuitous  act  of  mercy, 
and  an  excess  of  the  Divine  goodness.2 

1  Prsescientia  meritorum  non  est  tamen  oportet  quod  ratio  electionis 

causa    vel    ratio    prsedestinationis.  sit  merittim ;  sed  in    ipsa  electione 

.  .  .  Manifestum  est  quod  id  quod  ratio  est  divina  bonitas :  ratio  autem 

est  gratise  est  prsedestinntionis  effec-  reprobationis    est   originate    pecca- 

tus  ;  et  hoc  non  potest  poni  ut  ratio  turn. — -Aquinas,  vol.  8.  p.  330. 
praedestinationis,  cum  hoc  sub  prte-  2  Voluit  Deus  in  hominibus,  quan- 

destinatione  concludatur.     Si  igirur  turn  ad   aliquos   quos    prsedestinat, 

aliquid   aliud   ex   parte    nostra    sit  suara   reprsesentare    bonitatem   per 

ratio  prsedestinationis,  hoc  est  prseter  modum    misericordise   parcendo,    et 

effectum  prgedestinationis.     Non  est  quantum  ad  aliquos  quos  reprobat, 

autem  distinctum  quod  est  ex  libero  per  modum  justitise  puniendo.  .  .  . 

arbitrio  et  ex  prsedestinatione,  sicut  Neque  tameu  propter  hoc  est  iniqui- 

nec  est  distinctum  quod  est  ex  causa  tas  apud   Deum,  si   insequalia   non 

secunda  et  causa  prima. — lma  Q.  23.  insequalibus   prseparat.      Hoc  enim 

A.  5.  esset  contra  justitise   rationem,    si 

Electio  Dei  qua   unum   eligit  et  prsedestinationis  effectus  ex  debito 

alium  reprobat  rationabilis  est,  nee  redderetur,  et  non  daretur  ex  gratia. 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  261 

The  doctrine  of  necessity,  however,  explained  in  the 
last  chapter,  and  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  are  in  sub 
stance  the  same  doctrine,  and  only  differ  in  their  ground, 
which  is  in  one  a  ground  of  philosophy,  in  the  other  one  of 
Scripture.  The  schoolmen  attached  indeed  to  these  two 
doctrines  different  functions  and  operations  of  the  Divine 
Power.  Under  the  one,  God  acted  as  universal  mover ; 
under  the  other  as  special  mover  ;  under  the  one  He  ex 
erted  a  natural  power,  under  the  other  a  spiritual  or  grace  ; 
under  the  one  He  moved  men  to  a  good  proportionate  to 
their  nature,  under  the  other  to  a  good  exceeding  the  pro 
portions  of  nature ;  *  under  the  one  He  supported  the  natural 
goodness  of  man  unfallen,  under  the  other  He  healed  man 
fallen.  And  in  all  acts  in  which  the  special  power  operated, 
the  general  power  operated  too  :  so  that  God  acted  in  both 
capacities,  in  the  case  of  the  same  act.2  But  thus  described 
as  two  separate  and  distinct  actions,  the  universal  and 
special  action  were  really  only  the  same  action,  in  a  higher 
and  lower  degree,  of  the  Divine  motive  Power  over  the 
human  will. 

Thus  clearly  and  strongly  laid  down,  however,  the 
doctrine  of  Aquinas  and  the  Augustinian  schoolmen  on 
the  subject  of  predestination  has  been  mistaken  in  a  well- 
In  his  enim  quae  ex  gratia  dantur,  turae,  ad  quam  scilicet  homo  per- 
potest  aliquis  pro  libitu  suo  dare  cui  venire  potest  per  principia  SUSP  na- 
vult  plus  vel  minus,  dummodo  nulii  turae  :  alia  autem  est  beatitude 
subtrahat  debitum,  absque  prseju-  naturam  hominis  excedens,  ad  quam 
dicio  justitiae.  Et  hoc  est  quod  dicit  homo  sola  divina  virtute  perv<-nire 
paterfamilias.  Matt.  20.  15.  'Tolle  potest  secundum  quandam  Divinita- 
quod  tuum  est  ec  vade;  an  lion  licet  tis  participationem." — I1™  2dae  Q. 
mihi  quod  volo  facere  ?  '—  lnia  Q.  62.  A.  1. 
23.  A.  5.  2  Homo  in  statu  naturae  integrae 

1  Deus  movet  voluntatem  hominis  potest  operari  virtute  suae  naturae 
sicut  Universalis  motor  ad  univer-  bonum  quod  est  sibi  connaturale, 
sale  objectum  voluntatis,  quod  est  absque  superadditione  gratuiti  doni, 
bonum  ;  et  sine  hac  universali  moti-  licet  non  absque  auxilio  Dei  moven- 
one  homo  non  potest  aliquid  velle.  tis.—  1™  2dae  Q.  109.  A.  3. 
.  .  .  Sedtameninterdum  specialiter  Secundum  utrumque  statumnatura 
Deus  movet  aliquos  ad  aliquid  de-  humana  indiget  Divino  auxilio,  ad 
terminate  volendum,  quod  est  bonum,  faciendum  et  volendum  quodcunque 
sicut  inhisquos  movet  per  gratiam.'  bonum,  sicut  primo  movente.  Vir- 
g  T.  lma  2dae  Q,.  10.  A.  6.  tute  gratuita  superaddita  indiget  ad 

Est  duplex  hominis  beatitudo;  una       bonum  supernaturale.— Ibid.  A.  2. 
quidem  proportionata  humanse  na- 


262  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 


known  treatise,  whicL  professes  to  give  a  resume  of  the 
opinions  of  the  schools  on  this  subject.  Archbishop  Lau 
rence  asserts  the  predestination  maintained  by  the  school 
men  to  be,  a  predestination  in  consequence  of  foreseen 
good  works  in  the  individual.  '  Almighty  Grod  before  the 
foundations  of  the  world  were  laid,  surveying  in  His  com 
prehensive  idea,  or,  as  they  phrased  it,  in  His  prescience 
of  simple  intelligence,  the  possibilities  of  all  things,  before 
He  determined  their  actual  existence,  foresaw,  if  mankind 
were  created,  although  He  willed  the  salvation  of  all,  and 
was  inclined  to  all  indifferently,  yet  that  some  would  de 
serve  eternal  happiness,  and  others  eternal  misery ;  and 
that,  therefore,  He  approved  and  elected  the  former,  but 
disapproved  or  reprobated  the  latter.  Thus  grounding 
election  upon  foreknowledge,  they  contemplated  it  not  as 
an  arbitrary  principle,  separating  one  individual  from  an 
other,  under  the  influence  of  a  blind  chance,  or  an  irrational 
caprice  ;  but  on  the  contrary,  as  a  wise  and  just  one,  which 
presupposes  a  diversity  of  nature  between  those  who  are 
accepted,  and  those  who  are  rejected.  Persuaded  that  Grod 
is  the  fountain  of  all  good,  that  from  His  Divine  preordi 
nation  freely  flows  the  stream  of  grace,  which  refreshes  and 
invigorates  the  soul,  they  believed  that  He  has  regulated 
His  predetermination  by  the  quality  of  the  soil  through 
which  His  grace  passes,  and  the  effects  which  in  any  case 
it  produces,  not  restricting  His  favours,  but  distributing 
them  with  an  impartial  hand ;  equally  disposed  toward  all 
men,  but,  because  all  are  not  equally  (disposed  toward  Him, 
distinguishing  only  such  as  prove  deserving  of  His  bounty. 

They  considered  the  dignity  of  the  individual  as 

the  meritorious  basis  of  predestination.'  1 

The  first  remark  that  this  passage  suggests,  is  that  the 
writer  confuses  all  the  schoolmen  together,  and  attributes 
one  common  opinion  to  them  on  this  subject  ;  whereas 
there  were  different  schools  amongst  them,  as  among 
modern  thinkers,  some  taking  the  predestinarian  side,  and 
others  that  of  freewill ;  though  the  great  names  are  chiefly 
on  the  former  side.  The  writer,  however,  treats  them  all 

1  Laurence's  Bampton  Lectures,  pp.  148.  152. 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  263 

as  one  school,  and  considers  the  predestination  taught  by 
the  Augustinian  Aquinas  to  be  of  the  kind  which  he  here 
describes ;  i.e.  a  predestination  on  the  ground  of  foreseen 
good  life.  Of  course  if  this  is  so,  this  is  all  the  difference 
between  predestinarianism  and  the  doctrine  of  freewill. 
But  I  cannot  understand  how  he  can  put  this  interpreta 
tion  upon  the  doctrine  of  Aquinas,  when  the  latter  plainly 
and  expressly  asserts  the  contrary;  viz.,  that  foreseen 
merits  are  not  the  cause  of  predestination, — prcvscientia 
meritorum  non  est  causa  vel  ratio  predestinationis,  but 
predestination  the  cause  of  these  foreseen  merits ;  these 
merits  being  the  effect  of  grace,  and  grace  the  effect  of 
predestination ; — id  quod  est  gratiw  est  prcedestinationis 
effectus.  Archbishop  Laurence  appears  to  have  been  misled 
by  two  classes  of  expressions  in  Aquinas,  one  relating  to  con 
tingency,  the  other,  to  human  blame  and  responsibility. 

He  refers  in  support  of  this  interpretation  of  the  doc 
trine  of  Aquinas,  to  the  latter's  assertion  of  contingency. 
'  The  mistakes  upon  this  subject  of  those  who  have  but 
partially  consulted  the  speculations  of  the  schools  (he  is 
speaking  of  those  who  have  interpreted  these  speculations 
in  a  predestinarian  sense)  seem  to  have  arisen  from  the 
want  of  properly  comprehending  what  was  meant  by  the 
effect  of  predestination,  an  effect  always  supposed  to  be 
contingent ;  the  operations  of  freewill,  whether  with  or 
without  grace,  being  considered  only  as  foreknown,  and 
not  necessarily  predetermined.' l  And  he  quotes  a  passage 
relating  to  contingent  causes,  as  distinguished  from  neces 
sary  ones — 'Although  all  things  are  subject  matter  of 
Providence,  all  things  do  not  take  place  necessarily,  but 
according  to  the  condition  of  their  proximate  causes, — 
secundum  conditionem  causarum  proximamrnj  2  which 
are  in  some  cases  not  necessary  but  contingent  causes. 
Archbishop  Laurence  understands  this  assertion  of  contin 
gency  as  a  denial  of  the  doctrine  of  necessity,  and  an  asser 
tion  of  the  received  doctrine  of  freewill.  But  the  system 
of  Aquinas,  as  explained  in  the  last  chapter,  does  not  verify 

1  Bampton  Lectures,  p.  152.  Q.  3.  A.  1.;  Bampton  Lectures,  p. 

2  Aquinas  in  Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  40.       354. 


264  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

such  an  inference  from  his « use  of  the  term  contingent. 
Aquinas  divides  proximate  or  mediate  or  secondary  causes 
into  two  classes,  necessary  and  contingent ;  but  the  con 
tingent  causes  are  still  mediate  causes  only,  not  original 
ones.  They  are  as  in  complete  subordination  to  the  first 
cause,  as  necessary  causes  are  ;  only  differing  from  the 
latter  in  their  manner  of  operation,  which  is  variable  and 
irregular,  instead  of  fixed  and  uniform.  And  the  human 
will,  as  a  contingent  cause,  is  no  more  than  a  mediate  one. 
(rod  is  cause  of  the  will — ipse  actus  liberi  arbitrii  redu- 
citur  in  Deum  sicut  in  causam.  Contingency  then  in 
acts  is  not,  according  to  the  doctrine  of  Aquinas,  opposed 
to  their  ultimate  causation  from  without ;  which  is  the 
doctrine  of  necessity  :  contingency  is  a  certain  mode  in 
which  things  take  place  ;  and  volition  is  such  a  mode  in 
the  case  of  actions ;  but  volition  is  a  mode,  and  not  the 
cause,  in  the  sense  of  original  cause,  of  them. 

There  is  another  set  of  expressions  in  the  Augustinian 
schoolmen  relating  to  human  blame  and  responsibility,  to 
which  Archbishop  Laurence  refers.  '  To  the  inquiry  why 
some  are  unendowed  with  grace,  their  answer  was,  because 
some  are  not  willing  to  receive  it,  and  not  because  (rod  is 
unwilling  to  give  it ;  He,  they  said,  offers  His  light  to  all : 
He  is  absent  from  none,  but  man  absents  himself  from  the 
present  Deity,  like  one  who  shuts  his  eyes  against  the  noon 
day  blaze.' J  The  language  he  refers  to  is  that  of  Aquinas, 
whom  again  he  quotes  as  saying  that  there  are  two  reasons 
why  grace,  where  it  is  withheld,  is  withheld ;  one  because 
the  man  is  not  willing  to  receive  it,  the  other  because  Grod 
does  not  will  to  give  it ;  of  which  two  the  latter  is  posterior 
in  order  to  the  former — talis  est  ordo  ut  secundum  non 
sit  nisi  ex  suppositione  primi.*  Understanding  the  want 
of  desire  for  grace,  referred  to  here,  to  be  the  opposition  of 
the  individual's  free  and  self-determining  will,  he  takes 
these  expressions  as  involving  the  common  doctrine  of 
freewill,  that  Grod  offers  His  grace  to  all,  while  man  rejects 
or  accepts  it  according  to  his  own  choice.  But  the  fault 

1  Bampton  Lectures,  p.  151. 

3  Aquinas  inLomb.  1.  1.  Dist.  40.  Q.  4.  A.  2. 


CHAP.  x.  of  P rcdtstination.  265 

in  the  human  agent  here  referred  to  is  not  one  to  be  con 
founded  with  the  fault  of  individual  choice :  it  is  the  ori 
ginal  fault  of  the  whole  race.  All  mankind  are  to  begin 
with,  according  to  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  disinclined 
to  grace,  and,  so  far  as  themselves  are  concerned,  reject  it. 
Aquinas  then  can  assert  that  the  reason  why  grace  is  with 
held  is  man's  own  fault,  without  committing  himself  in 
saying  so  to  the  common  doctrine  of  freewill.  It  is  the  old 
position  which  meets  us  in  S.  Augustine.  The  will  of  man  is 
naturally  a  corrupt  and  faulty  will,  but  it  is  so  at  the  same 
time  necessarily,  and  as  the  effect  of  original  sin.  Respon 
sibility  attaches  to  it  as  being  will ;  the  voluntary  agent  is 
as  such  susceptible  of  praise  or  blame — ut  ei  imputetur 
aliquid  ad  culpam  vel  ad  meritum  ; * — and  legitimately 
comes  under  a  dispensation  of  rewards  and  punishments. 
Such  is  the  sense  in  which  man's  fault  is  said  by  Aquinas 
to  be  the  first  cause  why  grace,  where  it  is  withheld,  is 
withheld.  It  is  the  faulty  will  of  the  race,  not  the  mere 
choice  of  the  person,  which  is  this  cause  ;  which  faultiness 
is  therefore  consistent  with  necessity,  and  not  opposed  to 
it.  It  is  a  further  test  of  such  a  sense,  that  the  will  thus 
represented  as  the  original  barrier  against  grace,  is  next 
represented  as  wholly  able  to  be  changed  and  made  a  dif 
ferent  will,  by  grace.  '  Grod  is  able  when,  where,  and  in 
whomever  He  pleases,  to  convert  men's  evil  wills  from 
evil  to  good.' 2  It  follows  that  when  man's  will  is  changed 
from  evil  to  good,  it  is  by  His  irresistible  power ;  and 
therefore  that  the  admission  into  a  state  of  grace  takes 
place,  according  to  this  system,  on  a  ground  quite  different 
from  that  on  which  Archbishop  Laurence  considers  it  to 
do,  upon  his  too  hasty  and  superficial  interpretation  of  the 
scholastic  language.  Indeed,  if  none  are  to  be  considered 
necessitarians  who  make  man  a  responsible  being,  and  lay 
his  sins  and  their  consequences  at  his  own  door,  there  can 
not  be  a  Christian  necessitarian ;  for  we  must  either  do 

1  S.  T.  lma  Q.  22.  A.  2.  converters.'—  Augustine,   quoted  by 

2'Quis   tarn   impie    desipiat,   ut  Lombard,  1.  1.  Dist.  47.  '  Neque  ideo 

dicat  Deum  malas  hominum  volun-  prsecepit  omnibus  bona,  quia  vellet 

tates  quas  voluerit,  et  quando  voluerit  ab  omnibus  bona  fieri,  si  enim  vellet 

et  ubi  voluerit  in  bonum  non  posse  utique  fierent.' — Ibid. 


266 


Scholastic  Doctrine 


CHAP.   X. 


this,  or  charge  (rod  with  them — which  latter  no  Christian 
can  do.  The  most  rigid  predestinarian  writers  impose  this 
responsibility  upon  man.1 


1  Archbp.  Laurence's  use  of  the 
following  statement  iu  Aquinas  (B. 
L.  p.  151.)  shows  the  same  want  of 
insight  into  his  system,  and  the 
same  contented  resting  on  the  ap 
parent  meaning  of  particular  langu 
age,  without  any  consciousness  of  a 
different  interpretation,  which  in  a 
vast  and  intricate  theological  fabric 
might  be  reflected  from  other  quar 
ters  upon  it.  'Dicendum  quod  elec- 
tio  divina  non  praeexigit  diversitatem 
gratiae,  quia  haec  electionem  conse- 
quitur ;  sed  praeexigit  diversitatem 
naturae  in  divina  cognitioue,  et  facit 
diversitatem  gratiae,  sicut  dispositio 
diversitatem  naturae  facit.'  —  In 
Lomb.  1.  1.  Dist.-il.  Q.  1.  A.  2.  He  in 
fers  from  this  that  election  is  asserted 
by  Aquinas  to  be  on  the  ground  of 
foreseen  merits  in  the  individual, — a 
diversitas  natures  in  the  good  man 
from  that  of  the  bad  man.  But  this 
very  statement  says  that  this  diver 
sitas  natures  is  the  effect  of  a  divine 
arrangement  or  disposing — dispositio 
diversitatem  natures  facit.  And 
when  we  turn  to  the  part  of  Aquinas' 
system  which  relates  to  grace,  we 
find  that  a  certain  Divine  prepara 
tion  of  the  man,  while  in  a  state  of 
nature  and  previous  to  a  state  of 
grace,  is  necessary  as  a  preparation 
for  grace — pr&paratio  voluntatis 
humance  ad  consequendum  ipsum 
gratiee  habitualis  donum — auxilium 
yratuitum  Dei  interius  animam  mo- 
vent  is. — lraa  2llac  Q.  109.  A.  6.  Gratiae 
causa  non  potest  esse  actus  humanus 
per  modum  meriti,  sed  dispositio  na- 
turalis  quaedam  in  quantum  per  actus 
praeparamur  ad  gratiae  susceptionem. 
—Aquinas,  vol.  viii.  De  Praed.  This 
is,  then,  the  dispositio  natures  here 
referred  to,  which  is  a  Divine  mould 
ing  of  the  natural  man  to  fit  him 
for  grace.  The  statement,  again, 


on  which  Archbp.  Laurence  relies — 
Dicendum  quod  quamvis  Deus,  quan 
tum  in  se  est,  sequaliter  se  habeat 
ad  omnes,  non  tamen  aequaliter  se 
habeant  omnes  ad  ipsum,  et  ideo 
non  aequaliter  omnibus  gratia  prae- 
paratur  (in  Lomb.  1.  i.  Dist.  40.  Q. 
2.  A.  2.) — cannot  be  reposed  in 
against  a  whole  interpretative  force 
of  the  system  explaining  it  the  other 
way.  In  the  first  stage  of  original 
sin  all  men  do  eequaliter  se  habvnt 
ad  Deum  :  but  God  lifts  some  out  of 
this  state,  and  others  not,  previously, 
as  we  have  just  seen,  to  conferring 
actual  grace  upon  them.  In  this 
intermediate  stage,  then,  all  men  do 
not  eequetliter  se  habent  ad  Deum,  but 
some  are  and  some  are  not  in  a 
preparatory  state  for  grace :  but 
this  difference  is  the  result  of  the 
Divine  will. 

Archbp.  Laurence  relies  on  Cal 
vin's  dissatisfaction  with  Aquinas, 
but  the  instance  to  which  he  refers 
is  no  case  of  substantial  disagree 
ment  between  the  two,  but  only  of  a 
difference  between  a  more  subtle  and 
a  broader  mode  of  statement.  Cal 
vin  censures  the  refinement  or  quib 
ble — argutia,  of  Aquinas  in  saying 
that  foreseen  human  merit,  though 
not  the  cause  of  predestination  on 
God's  part,  may  be  called  the  cause 
of  it  in  a  certain  way — quodammodo 
— on  man's  part ;  because  God,  hav 
ing  predestinated  men  to  goodness, 
predestinates  them  to  glory  because 
they  are  good.  Such  a  statement 
makes  no  difference  in  the  doctrine 
of  predestination  as  a  whole ;  be 
cause  though  one  part  of  it  is  re 
garded  as  dependent  on  another, 
the  whole  is  made  to  depend  on  the 
Divine  will  solely.  But  Calvin 
dislikes  the  subtlety  as  interfering 
with  the  breadth  of  the  doctrine: 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  267 

To  the  doctrine  of  predestination  thus  laid  down  by 
Aquinas  succeeded  a  corresponding  doctrine  of  grace.  If 
eternal  happiness  is  ensured  to  the  individual  by  a  Divine 
decree,  the  means  to  it,  i.e.  a  good  life,  must  be  ensured 
also ;  and  this  can  only  be  ensured  by  the  operation  of  a 
Divine  grace  or  influence  upon  him,  the  effect  of  which  is 
not  dependent  on  his  own  will,  but  is  necessary.  Aquinas 
accordingly  proceeds  to  lay  down  the  doctrine  of  effective 
or  irresistible  grace. 

And  first  it  must  be  observed  that,  without  appending 
the  term  efficacious,  the  use  of  which  was  introduced  by 
the  later  Thomist^,  grace  of  itself  bears  in  Aquinas  the 
sense  of  efficacious,  i.e.  means  something,  which  simply 
by  the  fact  of  its  being  given  us  by  God,  and  of  the  man 
himself  having  it,  has  the  effect  of  making  the  man  good 
and  acceptable  to  (rod.  The  leaning  to  the  side  of  free 
will  which  has  marked  church  authority  for  the  last  three 
centuries,  has  impressed  for  the  most  part  upon  the  term 
grace  the  sense  of  assisting  grace;  i.e.  a  Divine  influence 
which  excites,  prompts,  suggests,  and  encourages,  but  which 
depends  on  the  human  will  for  its  proper  and  intended 
effect,  and  does  not  issue  in  any  good  act  or  good  and  ac 
ceptable  state  of  mind,  unless  the  will  has  by  an  original 
movement  of  its  own  converted  it  to  use.  And  this  is 
perhaps  the  sense  in  which  grace  is  more  generally  and 
popularly  understood  at  the  present  day.  But  the  Augus- 
tinian  schoolmen,  following  their  master,  do  not  mean  by 
grace  such  an  influence  as  this,  but  a  different  one  ;  one 
which,  when  received,  produces  of  itself  its  designed  effect 
— an  acceptable  and  justifying  state  of  the  soul.  They 
divide  grace  into  two  great  kinds,  one  which  is  designed 
for  the  good  of  the  individual,  and  makes  him  acceptable 

'Ac  ne   illam  quidem   Thomse   ar-  tur  Deus  praedestinare  homini  glo- 

gutiammoramur,praescientiammeri-  riam   ex   mentis,   quia  gratiam   ei 

torum  non  ex  parte  quidem  actus  largiri  decrevit  qua  gloriam  merea- 

prsedestinatis  esse  prsedestinationis  tur.' — Instit.  1.  3.  c.  22.  8.9. 
causam;    ex    parte    autem   nostra,  Between    the    Augustinian    and 

quodammodo  sic  vocari  posse,  nempe  Thomist  doctrine  of  predestination, 

secundum  particularem  prsedestina-  and   that  of  Calvin,  I  can  see  no 

tionis  sestimationem ;  ut  quum  dici-  substantial  difference.     NOTE  XXI. 


268  Scholastic  Doctrine 


CHAT.    X. 


to  GK>d, — gratia  gratum  faciens ;  the  other,  which  is  not 
the  grace  of  acceptableness,  but  only  some  gift  or  power 
with  which  the  individual  is  endowed  for  the  benefit  of  the 
church, — gratia  gratis  data.1  The  former  grace  becomes 
when  imparted  a  quality  of  the  soul,  a  certain  graciousness 
and  goodness  belonging  to  it,  as  beauty  belongs  to  the  body 
— nitor  animai.2 

The  question  then  is  how  this  grace  is  obtained  in  the 
first  place,  and  how  in  the  next  place  it  is  sustained  and 
preserved.  Is  it  obtained  by  any  merit  of  the  individual 
in  the  first  place,  i.e.  is  it  the  reward  of  any  original  exer 
tion  of  the  will  ?  Or,  if  not  obtained  in  this  way,  is  it 
preserved  in  this  way,  i.e.  by  the  freewill  of  the  individual 
sustaining  and  guarding  it  ?  In  either  of  these  cases  such 
a  grace  as  this  involves  no  doctrine  of  efficacious  and  irre 
sistible  grace ;  because  in  the  former  case  it  is  a  state  of 
the  mind  which  the  will  has  in  part  earned  ;  in  the  latter 
it  is  one,  which,  though  the  individual  is  endowed  with  it, 
by  an  act  of  (rod,  as  Adam  according  to  the  authorized 
doctrine  was  with  a  certain  good  disposition  at  his  creation  ; 
the  individual  has  to  maintain,  as  Adarn  had,  by  his  own 
freewill.  But  if  this  grace  is  neither  obtained  nor  preserved 
by  the  freewill  of  the  individual,  but  is  given  in  the  first 
instance  as  a  free  gift  of  Grod,  and  sustained  afterwards  by 
the  supporting  power  of  God,  exerted  gratuitously  and 

1  Duplex  est  gratia,  una  quidam  dinat  liominem  immediate  ad  con- 

per  quamipse  homo  Deo  conjungitur,  junctionem  ultimi  finis;  gratise  au- 

quse  vocatur  gratia  gratum  faciens ;  tern  gratis  datae  ordinant  hominem 

alia    vero    per    quam    unus   homo  ad  qusedam  prseparatoria  finis  nltimi, 

cooperatur  alteri    ad  hoc   quod   ad  sicut  per  prophetiam  et   miracula. 

Deum  reducatur  :  hujusmodi  autem  Et   ideo   gratia  gratum  faciens  est 

donum  vocatur  gratia  gratis  data;  multo     excellentior     quam     gratia 

quia  supra  facultatem  naturae,  et  gratis  data. — lma  2dae  Q.  iii.  A.  1.  5. 
supra  meritum  personse  homini  con-  Gratia  habitus  gratus  a  Deo — 

ceditur.    Sed  quia  non  datur  ad  hoc  causa  efficiens  meriti    .  .  .  Virtutes 

ut  homo  ipse  per  earn  justificetur,  theologicse    et    supernaturales,    non 

sed  potius  ut  ad  justificationem  al-  sunt  minus  efficaces  similium  actuum 

terius  cooperetur,  ideo  non  vocatur  quam  virtutes  morales. — Bradwar- 

gratum    faciens.     Et   de   hac   dicit  dine,  p.  364.  et  seq. 
Apostolus   1.  ad  Cor.  12.  7.     Uni-  2  Gratia  est  nitor  animae  sanctum 

cuique   datur  manifestatio   spiritus  concilians  amorem. — lraa  2"ae  Q.  110. 

ad  utilitatem,  scilicet,  aliorum.  A.  2. 

Gratia  autem  gratum  faciens  or- 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  269 

arbitrarily ;  it  then  involves  the  doctrine  of  efficacious 
grace  ;  for  there  is  no  room  at  either  end  for  any  original 
motion  of  the  will,  upon  which  the  possession  of  such  grace 
depends. 

But  the  latter  is,  according  to  the  Thomist  doctrine, 
the  mode  in  which  this  grace  is  obtained  and  preserved. 
First,  the  primary  possession  of  this  grace  is  not  owing,  in 
whole  or  in  part,  to  any  merit  or  original  act  of  will  in  the 
individual.  It  was  laid  down  that  to  a  man  who  prepared 
himself  as  much  as  possible  for  grace,  grace  was  still  not 
necessarily  given ; — non  necessario  data  se  prceparanti 
ad  gratiam  et  facienti  quod  in  se  est.}  But  if  a  man's 
best  possible  preparation  of  himself  for  it  was  no  claim  in 
the  eye  of  (rod  to  it,  the  bestowal  of  it  evidently  did  not 
depend  upon  any  thing  in  a  man  himself,  but  proceeded 
upon  a  different  law.  And  when  we  are  let  into  the  real 
meaning  of  this  position,  the  same  conclusion  is  still  more 
clear.  For  when  this  position  comes  to  be  explained,  as  it 
is  further  on  in  the  argument,  it  turns  out  to  be  only  an 
other  form  of  the  position  that  nobody  can  prepare  him 
self,  either  in  whole  or  in  part,  for  grace,  i.e.  have  any 
original  share  in  this  work.  The  preparation  of  the  human 
heart  for  the  reception  of  grace  was  a  Divine  work,  in 
which  God  was  the  mover,  and  the  human  will  the  tiling 
moved. 

The  distinction  indeed  of  operating  and  co-operating 
grace,  gratia  operans  et  cooperans,  appears  at  first  sight 
to  imply  an  original  act  of  the  will,  with  which  Divine 
grace  co-operates,  and  which  is  co-ordinate  with  that  grace. 
But  as  explained,  it  carries  no  such  meaning  with  it,  and 
issues  in  a  verbal  subtlety.  Two  acts  are  attributed  to  the 
will,  one  interior,  the  other  exterior,  the  one  being  the 
substance  of  the  act,  the  other  its  manifestation ;  the  one 
the  real  moral  act  itself,  the  other  that  act  as  expressed  in 
outward  form.  Of  these  two  acts  then,  the  former  is  attri- 
1  Homo  comparator  ad  Deum  formam  a  figulo,^  quantumcunque  sit 
sicut  lutum  ad  figulum,  secundum  praeparatum.  Ergo  neque  homo  re- 
illud  Jer.  18.  6.  Sicut  lutum  in  cipit  ex  necessitate  gratiam  a  Deo, 
manu  figuli  sic  vos  in  manu  mea.  quantumcunque  se  praeparet.— I1" 
Sed  lutum  non  ex  necessitate  accipit  2dae  Q.  112.  A.  3. 


270  Scholastic  Doctrine  CTTAP.  x. 

buted  to  Divine  grace  alone, — gratia  operans,  the  human 
will  not  co-operating  with  it,  but  being  simply  moved  by 
it.  The  latter  is  allowed  to  co-operate  with  Divine  grace. 
But  this  is  no  independent  but  a  wholly  moved  and  dictated 
co-operation.  The  will  having  being  wholly  moved  to 
action  by  grace,  that  action  is  then  called  a  co-operation 
with  grace.1 

The  bestowal  of  justifying  grace,  then,  does  not,  in  the 
system  ot  Aquinas,  depend  in  the  first  instance  upon  any 
act  of  man's  will ;  nor  does  its  continuance  depend  on  it 
either.  The  continuance  of  this  grace  depends  on  the  gift 
of  perseverance,  which  is  a  gratuitous  gift  of  God,  given 
to  whom,  and  withheld  from  whom  He  will ; 2  and  to  which 
no  life  and  conduct  of  man  can  afford  any  claim.  Suppose 
a  person  in  a  good  present  state  of  mind,  leading  a  good 
life,  and  therefore,  for  the  time  being,  in  a  state  of  accept 
ance  ;  the  question  is,  upon  what  law  does  this  state  of 
things  last  ?  Does  its  permanence  depend  on  the  indi 
vidual's  own  original  will,  which  performing  its  part  in  the 
guard  and  maintenance  of  this  state,  God  performs  His, 

1  '  In    illo  effectu   in  quo   mens  habet  a   Deo  petere   perse verantiae 
nostra  et  movet  et  movetur,  operatic  donum  ;    ut   scilicet   custodiatur   a 
non  solum  attribuitur  Deo  sed  etiam  malo  usque  ad  finem  vitfe.     Multis 
animse  ;    et   secundum   hoc   dicitur  enim  datur  gratia  quibus  non  datur 
gratia   cooperans.      Est   autem    in  perseverare  in  gratia.' — lm*  2dae  Q. 
nobis  duplex  actus ;  primus  quidc.ru  110.  A.  10. 

interior  voluntatis ;    et  quantum  ad  '  Omne  quod  quis  meretur  a  Deo 

istum   actum    voluntas  se   habet   ut  consequitur,  nisi  impediatur  per  pec- 

mota ;  Deus  autem  ut  movens  ;  et  catum.      Sed    multi    habent    opera 

prsesertim  cum  voluntas  incipit  bo-  meritoria,    qui    non     consequuntur 

num  velle,  quae  prius  malum  volebat ;  perseverantiam  ;  nee  potest  dici  quod 

et  ideo  secundum  quod  Deus  movet  hoc  fiat  propter  impedimentum  pec- 

humanam  mentem  ad  hunc  actum,  cati,  quia  hoc  ipsum  quod  est  peccare, 

dicitur  gratia  operans.     Alius  autem  opponitur  perseverantipe  ;    ita  quod 

est  actus  exterior,  qui  cum  a  volun-  si  aliquis  perseverantiam  mereretur, 

tate  imperetur,  consequent  est  quod  Deus  non  permitteret  ilium 'cadere 

ad  hunc  actum  operatio  attribuator  in    peccatum.      Non    igitur    perse- 

voluntati.    Et.  .   .  .  respectu  hujus-  verantia  cadit  sub  merito.  .  .  .  Per- 

modi  actus  dicitur  gratia  cooperans.'  severantia  vise  non  cadit  sub  merito, 

— }ma  2<*<»e  Q.  iii.  A.  2.  quia    dependet   solum   ex   motione 

2  '  Homo  etiam  in  gratia  consti-  divina,  quae   est   principium  omnis 
tutus  indiget  ut  ei  perseverantia  a  meriti.        Sed    Deus    gratis   perse- 
Deo   detur.  .  .  .  Postquam    aliquis  verantice   bonum   laroitur  cuicungue 
est  justificatus  per  gratiam,  necesse  illud  largitur? — 1 ma  2dae  Q.  1 14.  A.  9. 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  271 

and  supplies  the  complement  ?  Not,  according  to  Aquinas. 
The  continuance  of  this  state  of  things  is,  from  moment  to 
moment,  a  gratuitous  act  of  God's  sustaining  power,  who 
keeps  up  this  moral  and  spiritual  fabric,  as  He  does  that 
of  the  material  world,  so  long  as  it  suits  His  sovereign 
pleasure,  and  no  longer.  The  creature  cannot  conditionate 
this  Will  Supreme,  or  impose  any  obligation  in  justice 
upon  it,  in  this  matter.  Thus,  guarded  at  both  ends  from 
dependence  on  the  human  will,  given  as  the  free  gift  of 
God  in  the  first  instance,  and  sustained  by  His  absolute 
power  afterwards,  justifying  grace — gratia  gratumfaciens, 
was  effective  or  irresistible  grace. 

So  far,  however,  theThomist  doctrine  of  grace  was  only 
the  Augustinian  doctrine,  which  was  a  perfectly  simple 
one,  regarding  the  operation  of  grace  as  the  action  on  each 
successive  occasion  of  Divine  power ;  upon  which  action 
the  effect  of  goodness  in  the  soul  followed,  and  upon  its 
cessation  or  interruption  ceased.  But  the  schoolmen  added 
to  this  doctrine  a  distinction,  which,  though  founded  in 
reason  and  nature,  ended,  in  their  hands,  in  greatly  bur 
dening  and  perplexing  it.  Aristotle  had  laid  down  the 
very  natural  position,  that  what  constituted  a  man  good, 
was  not  the  good  act  on  the  particular  occasion,  but  a 
habit  of  mind  :  this  habit  was  productive,  indeed,  of  acts, 
and  defined  ag  such  ;  but  still  it  was  from  having  this 
source  of  acts  in  his  mind,  that  a  man  was  good,  rather 
than  from  the  acts  considered  in  themselves.  As  grace 
was  concerned,  then,  with  the  production  of  goodness,  the 
schoolmen,  incorporating  the  Aristotelian  doctrine  of  habits 
with  the  doctrine  of  grace,  maintained  that  God  imparted 
goodness  in  the  shape  of  habit ;  and  the  result  was,  the 
distinction  between  habitual  and  actual  grace— gratia 
habitualis  et  actualisl',—  a  distinction  which,  in  their 

1  'Homo     ad     recte     vivendum  dunt    proportionem    naturae:     alio 

duplicitur  auxilio  Dei  indiget :  uno  modo  indiget  homo  auxilio  gratiae, 

quidem  modo  quantum  ad  aliquod  ut  a  Deo  moveatur  ad  agendum.  .  .  . 

habituate  donum,  per  quod   natura  et  hoc  propter  duo ;  primo  quidem 

humana  corrupta  sanetur,  et  etiam  ratione  generali,  propter   hoc   quod 

sanata  elevetur  ad  operanda  opera  nulla  res  create potest  in  quemcunque 

meritoria    vitae  aeternae,  quse   exce-  actum  prodire,  nisi  virtute  motionis 


272  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

mode  of  carrying  it  out,  produced  such  a  labyrinth  of 
compartments  and  network  of  verbal  subtleties,  that  it 
requires  some  patience  in  a  reader  to  extricate  any  mean 
ing  at  all  from  such  confusion,  or  arrive  at  the  substance 
and  kernel  of  the  system,  amidst  such  obstructions. 

Aquinas  then  commences  with  laying  down,  in  general 
terms,  the  doctrine  of  infused  habits, — a  doctrine  which, 
as  I  have  explained  in  a  preceding  chapter,  is  in  itself  a 
natural  one,  and  agreeable  to  our  experience.  He  asserts, 
in  the  first  place,  that  there  are  such  things  as  natural 
habits1,  or  dispositions,  moral  and  intellectual,  which  are 
born  with  men  ;  though  he  artificially  limits  the  former  to 
such  as  are  evidently  connected  with  the  bodily  tempera 
ment,  such  as  temperance.  And  upon  this  foundation  of 
natural  truth,  he  proceeds  to  erect  another,  and  a  more 
important  class  of  infused  habits,  connected  with  grace. 

Besides  habits  infused  by  nature,  then,  there  were 
habits  '  infused  by  Grod  ; '  which  differed  from  the  natural 
virtues  in  this,  that  they  were  designed  for  the  spiritual 
good  of  man,  as  the  former  were  for  his  temporal  and 
worldly.  These  were  certain  imparted  holy  dispositions, 
or  spiritual  virtues,  produced  in  the  soul  without  any  efforts 
of  its  own — quas  Deus  in  nobis  sine  nobis  operatur.* 

divinse :  secundo  ratione  special!  complexione  ad  castitatem  vel  man- 
propter  conditionem  status  humanae  suetudinem,  vel  ad  aliquid  hujus- 
naturse  ;  quae  quidem  licet  per  gra-  modi.' — lma  2dfte  Q.  51.  A.  1. 
tiani  sanetur  quantum  ad  mentem,  2  '  Habitus  homini  a  Deo  infun- 
remanet,  tamen  in  eo  corruptio  et  duntur.  .  .  .  Ratio  est  quia  aliqui 
infectio  quantum  ad  carnem  .  .  .  et  habitus  sunt  quibus  homo  bene  dis- 
ideo  necesse  est  nobis  ut  a  Deo  ponitur  ad  finem  excedentem  facul- 
dirigarnur  et  protegamur,  quia  omnia  tatem  humanae  naturae,  .  .  .  et  quia 
movet  et  omnia  potest.  .  .  .  Donum  habitus  oportet  esse  proportionates 
habitualis  graticB  non  ad  hoc  datur  ei  ad  quod  homo  disponitur  secun- 
nobis  ut  'per  ipsum  non  indigeamus  dum  ipsos,  ideo  necesse  est  quod 
ulterius  divino  auxilio?  —  lma  2'Iae  Q.  etiam  habitus  ad  hujusmodi  finem 
110.  A.  9.  disponentes,  excedant  facultatem 
1  '  Sunt  in  hominibus  aliqui  habi-  humanae  naturae.  Unde  tales  habi 
tus  naturales.  ...  In  appetitivis  tus  nunquam  possunt  homini  inesse, 
autem  polentiis  non  est  aliquis  habi-  nisi  ex  infusione  divina.' — Though 
tusnaturalissecunduminchoationem  God  is  also  able  to  infuse  common 
ex  parte  ipsius  animae.  .  .  Sed  ex  habits,  such  as  are  ordinarily  ac- 
parte  corporis  .  .  .  sunt  enim  qui-  quired  by  acts. — 'Deus  potest  pro- 
dam  dispositi  ex  propria  corporis  ducere  effectus  causarum  secundarum 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  273 

First  in  order,  came  the  Theological  virtues, — Faith,  Hope, 
and  Charity.  Then  came  the  gifts — Dona ;  which  were 
seven  in  number, — Wisdom,  Understanding,  Knowledge, 
Counsel,  Piety,  Fortitude,  and  Fear.  But,  besides  these, 
were  also  infused  moral  virtues — virtutes  morales  infuscv ; 
which  were  the  same  in  matter  with  natural  or  acquired 
virtues,  but  differed  in  the  end  or  motive,  which  was  a 
spiritual  one,  while  that  of  the  former  was  natural.  The 
acquired,  and  the  infused,  virtue  of  temperance,  for  ex 
ample,  were  both  expressed  by  the  same  acts ;  but  the  one 
aimed  at  bodily  health,  or  an  undisturbed  exertion  of  the 
intellectual  faculties,  the  other  at  spiritual  discipline. 

Now,  so  far  as  the  schoolman  in  this  scheme  simply 
asserts  that  Grod  can,  and  often  does,  implant  holy  dispo 
sitions  and  habits  in  human  souls,  without  previous  disci 
pline  and  training  on  their  part;  or  maintains  the  principle 
of  infused  habits,  as  distinguished  from  habits  acquired 
by  acts,  his  position  is  a  natural  one,  and  agrees  with  our 
experience,  as  well  as  with  the  doctrine  of  the  early  Church. 
We  mean  by  a  habit,  a  certain  bias  or  proneness  to  act  in  a 
particular  direction ;  and  this  bias  or  proneness  is  obtained 
in  one  way  by  successive  acts.  But  it  would  be  untrue, 
and  contrary  to  the  plainest  facts  of  nature,  to  suppose 
that  this  is  the  only  way  in  which  such  a  bias  of  the  mind 
is  ever  obtained.  God  evidently  imparts  it  to  men,  at 
birth,  in  different  moral  directions  ;  for  we  see  them  born 
with  particular  dispositions  and  characters.  And  as  He 
imparts  it  at  birth,  He  appears  also  sometimes  to  impart 
it  on  subsequent  occasions,  by  powerful  impulses,  commu 
nicated  to  the  souls  of  man,  either  internally,  or  by  the 
machinery  of  his  outward  providence  ;  by  sudden  junctures, 
emergencies,  in  private  or  public  life.  We  see  great 
changes  produced  in  men's  characters  by  these  exciting 
causes,  and  their  minds  put,  by  the  force  of  events,  into 
particular  states  and  tempers,  which  they  retain  afterwards. 

ftbsque  ipsis  causis  secundis.   .   .  .  tiimen  per  naturam  posset  causari ; 

Sicut   igitur   quandoque   ad   osten-  itaetiam  quandpqueinfundit  hommi 

sionem  suse  yirtutis  producit  sani-  illos habitus  qui  natural,  yirtutepos- 

tatem  absque  causa  natural! ;  quae  sunt  causan.  — 

T 


274  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

That  is  to  say,  habits  are  sometimes  imparted  to  men 
at  once,  and  from  without,  in  distinction  to  being  the 
result  of  successive  acts.  The  doctrine  of  Conversion, 
is  the  application  of  this  truth  to  the  department  of 
religion  :  what  this  doctrine  asserts  being,  that  God,  by 
particular  impulses,  either  wholly  internal  or  connected 
with  outward  events,  imparts  at  once  a  religious  disposi 
tion  or  habit  to  the  mind;  so  that,  from  being  careless  and 
indifferent,  it  immediately  becomes  serious  ;  which  is  un 
doubtedly  sometimes  the  case.  So  far,  then,  as  the  school 
man  simply  maintains  in  this  scheme  the  position  of 
infused  habits,  or  that  habits  need  not  necessarily  be 
obtained  by  acts,  he  maintains  a  true  and  natural  doctrine. 
And  this  was  an  important  modification  of  the  Aristotelian 
doctrine,  which  rested  too  exclusively  upon  acts  as  the 
cause  of  habits.  So  acute  an  observer,  indeed,  of  facts, 
as  that  great  philosopher  was,  could  not  but  see  himself 
that  this  cause  did  not  apply  in  all  cases ; — and  the  obser 
vation  extracted  from  him  a  partial  modification  of  his 
own  system,  in  the  shape  of  the  admission  of  natural 
virtue — (frvaircr)  aoerr).  But  the  addition  of  infusion, 
as  a  formal  and  regular  cause,  in  the  case  of  habits,  was  a 
substantial  modification  of  the  Aristotelian  doctrine.  It 
was,  however,  a  modification,  which  naturally  followed  from 
Christianity.  The  idea  of  the  Divine  power,  which  was 
not  fully  embraced  by  the  Pagan  philosopher,  was  brought 
out  by  the  true  religion,  and  applied  to  the  moral,  as  well 
as  to  the  physical  world,  to  the  department  of  will,  as  well 
as  that  of  matter.  In  other  words,  it  taught  a  doctrine, 
which  the  pagan  philosopher  did  not  hold,  that  of  Divine 
Grace  ;  which  immediately  became  a  fresh  element  in  the 
argument,  and  supplied  a  new  cause  for  the  formation  of 
the  habit. 

But,  while  the  scheme  thns  rested  upon  a  basis  of 
nature  and  truth,  two  great  causes  of  confusion  were  at  work 
in  it.  One  was  an  unreal  or  artificial  distinction  in  the 
subject  matter  of  acquired  and  infused  habits.  It  will  be 
evident  to  any  one,  on  reflection,  that  the  distinction  be 
tween  these  two  kinds  of  habits,  is  a  distinction  simply  in 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  275 

the  mode  in  which  they  are  formed,  and  not  at  all  in  the 
nature  or  matter  of  the  habits  themselves  ;  the  same  state 
and  disposition  of  mind  being  formed  in  the  one  case  by 
time,  custom,  successive  acts,  and  in  the  other  by  Divine 
power  producing  it,  without  the  aid  of  these  previous 
steps.  All  habits,  as  such,  then,  whatever  be  their  subject 
matter,  or  rank,  come  alike  under  both  these  modes  of 
formation  :  an  ordinary  moral  habit,  such  as  honesty  or 
temperance,  is  as  much  a  subject  of  infusion  as  a  spiritual 
one,  such  as  faith  or  charity ;  and  a  spiritual  habit,  such 
as  faith  or  charity,  is  as  much  a  subject  of  acquisition,  as 
a  common  moral  one  of  temperance  or  honesty.  Infusion 
and  acquisition  apply  alike  to  both.  A  habit  of  faith  is 
acquired  by  acts  of  faith,  and  a  habit  of  love  by  acts  of 
love  ;  and  the  natural  or  Aristotelian  law  of  the  formation 
of  habits,  is  as  true  of  spiritual  as  of  common  moral  habits. 
Again,  the  commonest  moral  dispositions  are  as  capable, 
as  spiritual  ones,  of  being  imparted  in  the  other  way,  '/.«. 
without  previous  acts ;  and  we  see  them  so  imparted  often 
at  birth.  But  Aquinas  artificially  appropriates  infusion 
to  spiritual  virtues,  acquisition  to  moral  ones;1  as  if  the 
former  were  never  acquired  by  acts,  and  the  latter  never 
but  by  them.  It  depends  on  the  dispensation  under  which 
a  person  is  individually  placed,  in  what  way  he  obtains 
either  spiritual  or  moral  habits  ;  whether  both  are  the 
simple  growth  of  time  and  acts  in  him,  or  whether  he 
obtains  both  in  the  more  immediate  way  :  though  we  must 
not  so  divide  the  two  modes  of  formation  of  character  as  to 
forget  that  both  may  go  on  together  in  the  same  person, 
and  that  mankind  are  all  more  or  less  under  both  systems. 
Another  cause  of  confusion  was  the  technical  and  quaint 
division  of  these  habits,  followed  by  the  artificial  subordi 
nation  of  one  division  to  another,  the  attempt  being  to 
construct  them  into  one  harmonious  machinery  for  the 
building  up  of  the  human  soul,— one  set,  at  the  point 
where  its  power  failed,  being  taken  up,  and  its  action  car 
ried  on  by  another.  The  Theological  virtues,  Faith,  Hope, 
and  Charity,  were  infused  habits.  But  though,  their 
1  He  admits  natural  moral  virtue  in  a  limited  way.  p.  291. 
T  2 


276  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

infusion  into  a  pdrticular  soul  being  supposed,  these  were 
true  habits  or  dispositions  of  that  soul ;  they  were  passive 
and  inert,  not  producing  acts  until  they  were  removed  from 
another  quarter  to  do  so.  They  were  habits  indeed,  but 
elementary  ones,  imperfectly  possessed,  and  rather  of  the 
nature  of  principles  or  faculties — principia  supernatu- 
ralia,  corresponding  to  the  natural  faculties  of  man — 
principia  naturalia.1  While  the  natural  will  of  man, 
then,  could  put  the  natural  principles  into  action,  because 
these  were  possessed  perfectly,  it  could  not,  of  itself,  put 
into  action  the  supernatural  principles.  To  put  these  into 
action  another  spiritual  force  was  necessary.2  To  the  theo 
logical  virtues,  therefore,  succeeded  the  Dona.  Now  it  is 
true  that  a  habit  does  not  move  itself  to  action,  but  re 
quires  to  be  put  in  motion  by  a  particular  act  of  freewill, 
on  one  theory,  by  a  particular  act  of  grace,  on  another. 
But  the  Dona  were  themselves  only  imparted  habits. 
Here,  then,  was  one  set  of  habits,  which  was  necessary  to 
put  in  motion  another.  And  as  the  Dona  succeeded  the 
theological  virtues,  the  '  infused  moral  virtues '  succeeded 
the  Dona ;  being  those  final  and  settled  spiritual  habits  to 
which  the  supernatural  principles  in  man,  i.e.  the  theo 
logical  virtues,  tended ;  as  the  acquired  habits  were  the 
completion  of  his  natural  principles.3  Yet  this  accumula- 

1  Et    quia   hujusmodi    beatitudo  dum    quas    sit    dispositus   ad    hoc 
proportionem  humanre   natime    ex-  quod    divinitus    moveatur ;    et   istfg 
cedit,    principia    naturalia   hominis  perfcctioncs  vocantur  dona. — -im»2dae 
non  sufficiunt  ad  ordinandum  homi-  Q.  68.  A.  1.      The   Theological  vir- 
nem    in    beatitudinem    praedictam  ;  tues  are  imperfect  agents  and  cannot 
unde    oportet   quod    superadclantur  move   without    the    Dona. — Prima 
homini   divinitus  aliqua  principia,  (naturalis)  virtus  habeturabhomine 
per  quse  ita  ordinetur  ad  beatitu-  quasi     plena     possessio  :     secunda 
dinem    super naturalem,    sicut    per  autem   (theologica)    habetur   quasi 
principia    naturalia    ordinatur     ad  imperfecta.    Sed  id  quod  imperfecte 
finem  connaturalem :    et  hujusmodi  habet  naturam  aliquam   non  habet 
principiadicunturmrtutestheologicce:  per  se  operari,  nisi  ab  altero  move- 
turn  quia  habent  Deum  pro  objecto,  atur.  ...  Ad  finem  ultimum  natu- 
tum  quia  a  solo  Deo  nobis  inftm-  ralemadquamratiomovet,secundum 
duntur. — lma  2dae  Q.  62.  A.  1.  quod    est   imperfecte    formata    per 

2  Manifestum   est   quod   virtutes  theologicas  virtutes,  non  suffi cit  ipsa 
humanse  proficiunt  hominem,  secun-  motio   rationis,  nisi    desuper  adsit 
dum  quod  homo  natus  est  moveri  per  instinctus  Spiritus  Sancti. — A.  2. 
rationem.       Oportet    igiuir    inesse  *  Loco   naturalium   principiorum 
homini  altiores  perfectiones,  secun-  conferuntur   nobis   a    Deo  virtutes 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  277 

tion  of  habits,  rising  one  above  another  in  formal  scale' 
this  whole  complex  machinery,  did  not  complete  the  moral 
being,  who  seemed  always  approaching  the  terminus  of 
action,  and  never  attaining  it. 

For,  secondly,  habitual  grace,  with  all  this  multiplicity 
of  internal  construction,  could  still  not  put  itself  in  action. 
It  was  still  no  more  than  a  habit  of  the  mind,  imparted 
by  God  :  and  no  habit,  as  has  been  just  said,  can  put  itself 
in  action ;  for  a  man  does  not  necessarily  do  a  thing,  in 
fact,  because  he  has  a  certain  disposition  to  do  it.  It  be 
came  then  a  vital  question,  what  it  was  which  put  habitual 
grace  into  action.  Was  it  the  freewill  of  man  ?  If  it  was, 
then  the  human  will  had  an  original  and  independent  act 
assigned  to  it;  a  position  which  was  contrary  to  this  whole 
scholastic  doctrine  of  grace.  It  was  not  freewill,  then,  but 
another  and  a  further  grace,  which  set  in  motion  habitual, 
viz.  grace  actual' — gratia  actual-is.1  This  was  the  com 
pletion  of  the  system,  the  key-stone  of  the  arch.  Habitual 
grace  could  be  admitted  without  any  serious  drawback  from 
the  power  of  the  natural  will ;  for  God  might  impart  a  cer 
tain  disposition,  or  continuous  impulse  ;  while  it  depended 
wholly  on  the  independent  motion  of  the  will,  whether  the 
man  ac^ed  upon  it  or  not.  The  turning  and  distinctive 
assertion  in  the  system,  then,  was  the  assertion  of  actual 
grace,  as  that  which  moved  habitual :  and  to  this  cardinal 
position  the  Thomists,  and  their  successors  the  Janseuists, 
directed  their  most  zealous  and  anxious  attention,  repelling 
all  interference  with  it  as  a  subversion  of  the  whole  Gospel 
doctrine  of  grace.  The  admission  of  habitual  grace  set 
aside  as  one  which  the  Semi-Pelagian  or  even  the  Pelagian 
could  make,  without  danger  in  principle  to  his  theory  ; 
grace  actual  was  defended  as  the  central  fort  of  Christian 
truth  in  this  department.2 

theologicae.  .  .  .  Unde  oportet  quod  '  See  p.  290. 

his  etiam  virtutibus  theolojdcis  pro-  2  Kon  est  habitus  qui  facit  facere, 

portioualiter  respondeant  alii  habi-  says  Jansen.     No  habit,  he  urges,  is 

tus  divinitus  causati   in   nobis,  qui  the   cause    of   action,    but    Ititrum 

sic  sehabentadvirtutestheologicas,  arbitrium   at  the  time.— De  Gratia 

sicut  se  habent  virtutes  morales  ad  Christi,  pp.  186,  996.     Nee  est  lux 

principia   naturalia  virtutum. — I"*  vel  habitus  quse  velle  vel  non  velle, 

2<i»e  Q  63   A.  3.  videre  vel  non  videre  iaciunt,   sed 


278  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

As  then  in  the  simpler  and  Augustinian,  so  in  the  com 
plex  and  Aristotelian  statement  of  the  doctrine  of  grace, 
in  which  the  distinction  of  habitual  and  actual  is  intro 
duced,  Aquinas  maintains,  we  see,  an  irresistible  or  effec 
tive  grace.  Habitual  grace  is  guarded  carefully  at  both 
ends  from  dependence  on  the  human  will.  It  was  alike 
imparted  and  applied  by  an  act  of  Divine  Power.  Had 
the  spiritual  habit  been  either  obtained  in  the  first  instance 
by  an  act  of  the  will,  or,  when  imparted  as  a  free  gift,  de 
pended  for  its  use  on  the  will,  a  place  for  freewill  would 
have  been  allowed.  But  if  freewill  comes  in  neither  at  the 
beginning  nor  at  the  end,  neither  as  obtaining  the  habit 

o  o  o 

in  the  first  instance  nor  as  using  it  in  the  next,  or  causing 
it  to  terminate  in  act,  one  operation  of  an  irresistible 
Divine  influence  is  maintained  throughout. 

The  Summa  Theologica  thus  lays  down  a  doctrine  of 
absolute  predestination,  with  its  complemental  doctrine  of 
irresistible  grace — that  the  whole  world,  being  by  original 
sin  one  mass  of  perdition,  it  pleased  Grod  of  His  sovereign 
mercy  to  rescue  some  and  to  leave  others  where  they  were; 
to  raise  some  to  glory,  giving  them  such  grace  as  neces- 

tantunimodo  sine  quibits  actus    vo-  ground  of  merit  from  man.    Did  he 

lendi     vel    videndi     non    fit.  —  p.  use  habitual  grace  by  his  own  power 

935.     And  this  motion  of  libcruin  of  choice,  he  would  have  the  merit 

aibitrium  at  the  time,  is  produced  of  his  own  use  of  this  grace  (p.  186.); 

by  grace  at  the  time — gratia  sped-  but  if  this  grace  is  put  in  action  by 

alls,    actualis  —  adjutorium   gratise  another  grace,  no  ground  of  merit 

actualis   quod   tune   datur,  quando  in  the  man  himself  remains.     And 

act u  volumus  et  operamur.  ...  in-  a  distinction  is  drawn  in  this  re- 

spiraus    eliam    habitualiter    justis  spect  between  fallen  man  and  the 

velle  et  operari. — pp.  151.  153.    He  angels. — -Hinc  nascebatur  ut  neque 

adds:  Tota  disputatio  cum  Pelagio  volitiones  neque actiones  augelorum 

de  justorum,    hoc   est,   habitualeru  essent  specialia  Dei  dona,  hoc  est, 

gratiam  jam  habentium  fervuit.  .  .  non  eis  Deus  speciali  donatione  sou 

Non  ita  deliravit  Pelagius,  ut  exis-  gratia     largiretur.        Tantummodo 

timaret    justitiam    habitualem,   ad  enim  donabat  ea  in  radice,  quatenus 

opera  justa  suo  modo  non  adjuvare.  eis  adjutorium  quoddam  gratise  tri- 

— p.   153.      'Actualis   gratia'  thus  buebat,  sine  quo  .  .  .  non  poterant: 

gives  the  '  completum  posse,'  which  sed  ipsum  velle,  agere,  et  perseve- 

is  'per  liberum  arbitrium  remotior,  rare,  non  eis  dabat  adjutorium  gratiae, 

per   fidem   propinquior,    per  chari-  sed  propria  voluntas  .  .  .  Tune  igitur 

tatem   multo   propinquior,    per   ac-  velle  et  agere  bonum  non  erat  spe- 

tualem     gratiam,'   really    had. — p.  ciale  Dei  donum,  sed  tantum  gene- 

338.     This  position  is    maintained  rale. — pp.  935,  936. 
as  the  only  one  which  cuts  off  i.he 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  279 

sarily  qualified  them  for  it,  and  abandon  the  rest,  from 
whom  He  withheld  such  grace,  to  eternal  punishment.  But 
this  formal  scheme  laid  down,  the  attentive  reader  of 
Aquinas  will  next  observe  a  certain  general  leaning  and 
bias  towards  a  modifying  interpretation  of  it.  Having 
constructed  a  system  on  the  strict  Augustinian  basis,  the 
mind  of  the  great  schoolman  appears  to  have  shrunk  from 
the  extreme  results  which  it  involved  ;  and  without  com 
mitting  himself  to  any  substantial  difference  from  his 
master,  he  yet  uses  modes  of  speaking  suggestive  of  an 
other  view  of  the  question  than  that  which  lie  had  bor 
rowed  from  him ;  and  a  phraseology,  which  is  not  casual, 
but  set  and  constant,  insinuates  a  relaxation  of  the  Augus 
tinian  doctrine. 

And  first  I  will  make  the  preliminary  remark,  that  a 
difference  is  to  be  observed  in  the  general  tone  of  these 
two  great  theological  minds,  tending  more  or  less  to  affect 
their  respective  views  on  this  subject.  Aquinas  is  more 
of  a  philosopher  than  his  master,  and  has  greater  sympa 
thies  with  the  human  mind  as  such,  with  the  natural 
intellect,  reason,  and  moral  ideas  of  mankind.  His  vast 
acquaintance  with  heathen  philosophy  opens  his  mind  to 
the  valuable  gifts  even  of  unenlightened  man,  his  deep 
reflections  upon  himself,  his  knowledge  of  (rod, — true  as 
far  as  it  goes, — and  his  advancement  in  virtue,  under  the 
guidance  of  reason  and  conscience.  Nor  is  the  deference 
which  he  shows  to  heathen  authority,  in  philosophical  and 
moral  questions,  altogether  consistent  with  the  position 
which  his  formal  theology,  as  an  Augustinian,  assigned  to 
unconverted  human  nature,  which  it  represented  as  in  the 
depths  of  sin,  and  unable  to  do  or  to  think  anything  good. 
The  perplexity,  again,  with  respect  to  the  existence  of 
evil,  appears  in  a  deeper  and  more  sensitive  form  in  the 
mind  of  Aquinas  than  it  does  in  that  of  his  master.  Au 
gustine  sees  as  a  theologian  an  inexplicable  mystery ;  but 
Aquinas  shows  more  of  that  human  sentiment,  with  respect 
to  the  great  fact  of  evil  in  the  world,1  which  has  rested 

1  Bradwardine  has  less  scruple.       utilitas  electorum,  bonum  naturae, 
— Ecce  triplex  bonum  ex  reprobis :       seculique  ornatua.     Ponatur  quoque 


280  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

upon  so  many  of  the  deep  and  philosophical  minds  of  dif 
ferent  ages,  and  especially  of  modern  times,  disquieting 
some,  and  sobering  and  subduing  others.  His  perception 
not  dulled  by  the  commonness  and  constancy  of  the  fact, 
as  inferior  ones  are,  but  ever  retaining  something  of  a  first 
surprise,  acknowledges,  as  the  eye  of  a  naturalist  would 
some  remarkable  law  in  his  department,  the  prevalence  of 
moral  evil  in  this  lower  world — bonum  videtur  esse  ut  in 
paucioribus  ; — a  fact  which,  as  he  cannot  explain,  he  en 
deavours  to  outweigh,  conjecturing  some  compensation  for 
it  in  other  parts  of  the  universe,  and  isolating  this  sublu 
nary  world  as  one  exception  to  a  universal  law.  This 
sphere  of  natural  evil,  of  generation  and  corruption,  was 
small  in  comparison  with  the  world  of  heavenly  bodies, 
whose  existence  was  eternal  and  fixed.  This  sphere  of 
moral  evil  in  the  majority  was  small,  again,  in  comparison 
with  the  angelic  world,  where  a  different  law  was  in  opera 
tion  ;  and  the  angels  who  stood  were  much  more  in  number 
than  those  who  fell,  and,  perhaps,  even  than  the  whole 
number  of  the  condemned,  both  men  and  demons — et  forte 
etiam  multo  plures  quam  omnes  damnandi  dcemones  et 
homines.1  Such  a  line  of  thought  had  a  bearing  upon  the 
present  question,  and  tended  to  affect  his  view  upon  it ; 
because  an  attempt  to  reduce  the  amount  of  evil  in  the 
universe  at  large  disposed  to  reducing,  as  far  as  might  be, 
the  alarming  estimate  of  it  in  this  world. 

The  distinction,  then,  involved  in  Augustinian  predes 
tination  and  reprobation,  being  a  distinction  between  posi- 

secundum   pium    zelum   multorum,  veluti    contrarietatis  extremse  con- 

licet  non  secundum  scientiam,  quod  fert  justis,  tanquam    scintillse   ful- 

totus   infernus    cum   omnibus   suis  gentibus,  et  ut  stellse.     Quis  enim 

domesticis  reprobatis  tolleretur  de  vel  cujus  ratio  prohibuisset  Dominum 

medio,  essetque  ccelum  tantummodo  ab  initio,  si  fuisset  placitum  coram 

cum  civibus  suis  sanctis ;  tune  se-  eo,  creasse  ccelum  plenum  electis  in 

culum  esset  multum  perfectum,  et  si  gloria,  et  infernum  plenum  reprobis 

Deus  sic  fecisset  multum  bene  fecis-  in  poena,  ut  hoc  illi  comparate  appa- 

set.     Nunc  autem  tanto  perfectius  ruisset  gloriosius  et  fuisset  ?     Non 

et  tanto  melius  fecit  Deus,  quantum  deerunt    tamen    qui    hos    humano 

perfectionis  et  bonitatis  continent  in  misererentur  affectu,  et  pia  compas- 

se  illce  nobiles   creatures  damnatce,  sione  contenderent   sic   facere   non 

quantum    etiam    resplendent  iae   et  debere. — p.  355. 
apparent!*  purioris  ilia  comparatio  '  InLomb.l.  1.  Dist.  39.  Q.  2.  A.  2. 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  281 

tive  good  and  positive  evil,  goodness  and  wickedness,  and 
their  consequences,  eternal  happiness  and  eternal  misery, 
to  two  portions  of  the  world  respectively ;  there  is  a  ten 
dency  in  the  language  of  Aquinas  to  reduce  this  distinc 
tion  to  a  distinction  between  higher  and  lower  good.  Two 
kinds  of  happiness  are  laid  down  in  his  system,  4  one  of 
which  is  proportioned  to  human  nature,  and  to  which  a 
man  can  arrive  by  this  principle  of  his  own  nature ;  the 
other  exceeding  human  nature,  and  to  which  a  man  can 
arrive  only  by  Divine  virtue  and  by  a  participation  of  the 
Divinity,  according  to  the  text  in  8.  Peter,  that  we  are  by 
Christ  made  partakers  of  the  Divine  Nature.' }  Here, 
then,  are  two  kinds  of  happiness,  and  two  kinds  of  virtues, 
which  respectively  qualify  for  them.  There  is  one  class 
of  virtues,  which  tits  a  rnan  for  his  place  in  the  order  of 
nature,  and  makes  him  a  worthy  member  of  the  world  of 
God?s  natural  providence — secundum  quas  homo  se  beue 
habet  in  ordine  ad  res  humanas ;  another  class,  which 
fits  a  man  for  a  place  in  a  supernatural  order  of  things 
and  a  heavenly  citizenship — ad  hoc  quod  sint  civts  sanc 
torum  et  domestici  Dei.2  Expressed  with  scholastic  for 
mality,  here  is  a  very  obvious  distinction,  and  one  whicli 
we  cannot  avoid  observing  in  the  world  around  us, — one 
which  is  recognised  in  the  common  language  and  writings 
of  Christians.  We  see  as  a  plain  fact,  that  there  is  a  kind 
of  goodness,  which,  as  distinguished  from  another  kind, 
must  be  pronounced  to  belong  to  this  world, — that  men 
may  be  honest,  conscientious,  and  high-principled  in  their 
worldly  callings,  still  having  their  view  conh'ned  to  this 
world.  It  is  a  virtuous  mould  and  character  of  mind, — 
that  of  a  man  who  recognises  the  world  as  a  true  sphere 
of  moral  action,  desires  to  be  on  the  right  side,  and  culti 
vates  with  that  view  various  moral  qualities ;  who,  there- 

1  Estautem  duplex  hominis  beati-  potest  secundum  quandam  Divini- 

tudo ;    una    quidem    proportionate-  tatis     participationem  ;    secundum 

humanse  naturae,  ad  quam  scilicet  quod   dicitur  (2   Pet.  i.)  quod  per 

homo  pervenlre  potest  per  principia  Christum  facti  sumus  consorte*  di 

suae  naturae.      Alia  autem  beatitude  vines  naturce. — lm*  2<Ue  Q.  62.  A.  1. 

naturam  homiais  excedens,  ad  quam  2  1™*  2*1**  Q.  63.  A.  4. 
homo  sola  divina  virtute  pervenire 


282  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

fore,  so  far  as  the  spiritual  principle  is  involved  in  any 
bond  fide  and  honest  distinction  of  good  and  evil,  acknow 
ledges  a  spiritual  law  in  his  own  nature  and  the  constitu 
tion  of  things,  to  which  he  defers,  and  on  which  he  frames 
his  life  and  conduct ;  but  who  lowers  this  law  by  his  narrow 
and  confined  application  of  it  to  present  things  and  visible 
relations.  This,  then,  is  what  Christian  moralists  call  the 
virtue  of  the  natural  man  ;  and  its  defect  is  in  the  prin 
ciple  of  faith,  which,  by  opening  another  world  for  them, 
and  so  enlarging  their  scope  and  field,  would  have  given  a 
spring  and  impulse  to  these  moral  perceptions,  quickening 
and  strengthening  them  ;  whereas  they  are  now  kept  down 
to  a  particular  level.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  an  essential 
part  of  Christian  doctrine,  that  there  is  a  temper  of  mind 
so  far  in  advance  of  this  natural  morality,  as  to  seem  to 
differ  from  it  in  kind  :  in  the  sense  in  which  everything 
seems  at  its  perfection  and  final  point,  to  be  a  different 
thing  from  what  it  was  before,  as  a  lens  burns  at  its  centre 
only.  This  is  the  supernatural  temper  of  charity.1 

From  morals  the  distinction  of  natural  and  supernatural 
is  then  extended  by  Aquinas  to  religion.  It  was  obvious 
that  the  natural  man  had  not  only  moral  virtue  of  some 
kind,  but  religion  as  well.  For,  independent  of  the  reli 
gious  men  which  Paganism  had  produced,  what  is  the 
obedience  which  the  natural  man,  in  his  moral  course  of 
life,  pays  to  his  own  conscience,  but  an  obedience  to  God, 
whom  he  virtually  recognises  as  speaking  to  him  by  that 
internal  voice  ?  And  as  he  will  obey  that  conscience,  even 
at  the  cost  of  his  worldly  interests,  suffering  the  greatest 
inconveniences  rather  than  offend  against  probity  and 

1  La  distance  infinie  des  corps  aux  valent  pas  le  moindre  mouvement  de 
esprits  figure  la  distance  infiniment  charite ;  car  elle  est  d'un  ordre  in- 
plus  infinie  des  esprits  a  la  charite  ;  finiment  plus  eleve. 
ear  elle  est  surnaturelle.  De  tous  les  corps  ensemble  on  ne 

Tous  les  corps,  le  firmament,  les  saurait  tirer  la  moindre  pensee  :  cela 

etoiles,  la  terre  et  les  roy;iumes  ne  est  impossible,  et  d'un  autre  ordre. 

valent  pas  le  moindre  des  esprits ;  Tous  les  corps  et  les  esprits  ensemble 

car   il   connait    tout    cela,    et   soi-  ne   sauraient   produire   un   mouve- 

meme ;  et   le  corps,  rien.     Et  tous  ment  de  vraie  charite  :  cela  est  im- 

les  corps,  et  tous  les  esprits  ensem-  possible,  et  d'un  autre  ordre   tout 

ble,  et  toutes  leurs  productions,  ne  surnaturel. — Pascal. 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  283 

honesty,  it  is  plain  that  in  some  sense  he  prefers  the 
Divine  approbation  to  everything  else.  It  was  accord 
ingly  laid  down  that  the  natural  man  was  able  to  love 
God  above  all  things — homo  potest  diligere  Deum  super 
omnia  ex  soils  naturallbus  sine  gratia.  But  the  distinc 
tion  was  then  applied  that  he  loved  (rod  naturally,  not 
supernaturally,  '  as  the  source  and  end  of  natural  good ; 
whereas  charity  loved  Him  as  the  centre  of  spiritual  good 
or  happiness.  Charity  had,  moreover,  a  positive  commu 
nion  with  (rod,  which  nature  had  not ;  of  which  communion 
a  certain  promptitude  and  delight  were  the  results,  which 
did  not  belong  to  the  natural  love  of  God.' ! 

These  two  kinds  of  goodness,  then,  natural  and  super 
natural,  had  their  respective  sources  assigned  to  them,  and 
the  cause  or  motive  power  was  pronounced,  by  an  abbre 
viation,  in  the  one  case  to  be  reason,  in  the  other  God— 
Ratio  et  Deus : 2  the  Divine  Power,  however,  operating 
alike  in  both  cases  as  true  and  original  Cause.  The  Divine 
Power,  acting  simply  as  the  First  or  Universal  Cause  in 
nature,  moved  the  freewill  of  man  to  natural  virtue  ;  acting 
in  a  special  way  or  by  grace,  it  moved  the  same  freewill 
to  supernatural  virtue.3  '  All  things,'  says  Aquinas,  '  are 
subject  to  Providence,  and  it  pertains  to  Providence  to 
ordain  all  things  to  their  end.  But  the  end  to  which 
created  things  are  ordained  by  God  is  twofold.  One  is  the 
end  which  exceeds  the  proportion  and  faculty  of  created 
nature ;  that  is  to  say,  the  life  eternal,  which  consists  in 
the  Divine  vision, — which  vision  is  above  the  nature  of 
every  creature.  Another  is  the  end  proportioned  to  created 
nature,  and  which  that  nature  can  attain  by  the  virtue  of 
that  nature.  Now,  that  which  cannot  arrive  at  a  point  by 
its  own  virtue  must  be  transmitted  thither  by  another,  as 
an  arrow  is  sent  by  an  archer  at  a  mark.  Wherefore,  pro- 

1  'Charitas  diligit  Deum   super  quaudam  soeietatem  spiritualem  cum 

omnia    eminentius     quam    natura.  Deo.     Addit  etiam   charitas   super 

Natura   enim   diligit    Deum   super  naturalem  dilectionem  Dei,  prompti- 

omnia,  prout  est  principium  et  finis  tudinem  quandam  et  delectationem.' 
naturalis  boni ;  charitas  autem,  se- 

cundum  quod  est  objectum  beatitu-  ™*  2"*  Q.  68.  A.  1. 

dinis,  et  secundum  quod  homo  habet  '  1"*  2<u<>  Q.  10.  A.  6. 


284  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

perly  speaking,  the  rational  creature,  which  is  capable  of 
life  eternal,  is  conducted  up  to  it,  or  transmitted  to  it  by 
G-od.  Of  which  transmission  the  reason  pre-exists  in  the 
mind  of  God,  even  as  there  exists  generally  the  reason  of 
the  ordination  of  all  things  whatever  to  the  end.  But  the 
reason  of  anything  being  done  is  a  certain  pre-existence  in 
the  mind  of  the  doer  of  the  thing  itself  to  be  done  ;  whence 
the  reason  of  the  transmission  of  the  rational  creature  to 
life  eternal  is  called  predestination — nam  destinare  est 
mittere.' 1  While  the  cause,  then,  of  natural  virtue  is  the 
Divine  Power  acting  in  its  ordinary  function,  as  prede 
termining  universally  the  created  wills  of  men,  the  cause  of 
supernatural  virtue  in  man  is  the  Divine  Power  acting  in  pre 
destination,  or  in  the  execution  of  a  certain  special  decree. 
'  The  virtue  which  qualifies  man  for  good  as  defined  by  the 
Divine  Law,  in  distinction  to  reason,  cannot  be  caused  by 
human  acts  of  which  the  principle  is  reason,  but  is  caused 
in  us  by  the  Divine  operation  alone.'  2  And  this  Divine 
operation  is  carried  on  by  means  of  that  machinery  of  in 
fused  supernatural  virtues  above  described.  For  '  as  God 
provides  for  His  natural  creatures  in  such  wise,  that  He 
not  only  moves  them  to  natural  acts,  but  even  endows 
them  with  certain  forms  and  virtues  to  act  as  principles 
of  action  and  to  be  in  themselves  dispositions  to  such 
action ;  so  into  those  whom  He  moves  to  attain  eternal 
and  supernatural  good  He  infuses  certain  supernatural 
forms  or  qualities,  by  which  they  are  sweetly  and  promptly 
disposed  to  attain  that  good.' 3  Supernatural  virtue  is 

1  'Ad  illud  autem,  ad  quod  non  sionis  creaturae  rationalis  in  finem 

potest  aliquid  virtute  suae  naturae  vitse  aeternae  praedestinatio  nomina- 

pervenire,  oportet  quod  abalio  trans-  tur  ;    nam  destinare  est  mittere.' — 

mittatur,  sicut  sagitta  a  sagittante  I™  2dae  Q,.  23.  A.  1. 
mittitur  ad  signum.     Unde  proprie  2  '  Virtus  vero  ordinans  hominem 

loquendo,  rationalis   creatura,    quse  ad  bonum  secundum  quod  modinca- 

est  capax  vita;   aeternae  perducitur  tur  per  legem  divinam,  et  non  per 

in  ipsarn  quasi  a   Deo   transmissa.  rationem     humanam,     non     potest 

Cujus  quidem  transmissionis   ratio  causari  per  actus  humanos  quorum 

in  Deo  praeexistit,  sicut  et  in  eo  est  principium  est  ratio ;  sed  causatur 

ratio  ordinis  omnium  in  finem.  Ratio  solum    in    nobis    per   operationem 

autem   alicujus  fiendi  existens  est  divinam.' — lma  2dae  Q.  63.  A.  2. 
quaedam  praeexistentia  rei  fiendae  in  3 '  Creaturis  autem  naturalibus  sic 

eo.     Unde  ratio  praedictae  transmis-  providet  ut  non  solum  moveat  eas 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  285 

thus  an  extraordinary,  natural  an  ordinary,  gift  ;  the  one 
an  inspiration,  the  other  a  providential  endowment. 

But  while  these  two  kinds  of  virtue,  and  the  ends  to 
which  they  respectively  tend,  differ  in  the  quality  of  good 
which  belongs  to  them,  both  have,  according  to  this  lan 
guage,  some  ;  and  the  difference  between  these  two  states 
is  one  of  higher  and  lower  good,  and  not  one  of  good  and 
evil.  As  a  disciple  of  S.  Augustine,  indeed,  Aquinas  is 
obliged  formally  to  preserve  the  distinction  between  the 
natural  and  spiritual  man  as  one  of  positive  good  and  posi 
tive  evil,  and  to  use  the  terms  predestination  and  reproba 
tion  as  involving  this  difference  ;  to  represent  inclusion 
within  the  Divine  decree  as  salvation,  exclusion  from  it  as 
damnation.  The  pure  Augustinian  doctrine  admitted  of 
no  medium  between  these  two  results ;  which  it  defends 
on  the  ground  of  an  original  guilt  in  the  human  race, 
which  meets  with  its  due  punishment  in  one  of  these,  with 
a  gratuitous  pardon  in  the  other.  Aquinas,  then,  formally 
adopts  the  Augustinian  scheme,  with  the  established  de 
fences.  But  a  careful  observation  of  his  language  will 
detect  a  contest  between  two  different  rationales  in  his 
mind ;  the  Clementine  view  of  human  nature  struggling 
with  the  Augustinian.  Reprobation,  maintained  on  one 
side  in  full  severity,  is  softened  down  on  another,  and  iden 
tified  with  a  lower  step  in  the  scale  of  being  ;  and  the  rigid 
Augustinian  line  of  defence  for  the  doctrine  mixes  with 
another,  which  implies  a  reduced  doctrine  to  be  defended. 
We  are  referred,  together  with  an  original  guilt  in  human 
nature,  to  a  principle  of  variety  in  the  constitution  of 
things,  which  requires  that  there  should  be  higher  and 
lower  places  in  the  universe,  down  even  to  some  lowest 
place  of  all,  which  must  be  occupied.  '  As  created  things,' 
he  says,  'cannot  attain  to  the  Divine  simplicity,  it  is 
necessary  that  the  Divine  goodness,  which  is  in  itself  one 
and  simple,  should  be  represented  multiforinly  in  them ; 
ad  actus  naturales,  sed  etiam  largi-  ale  seternnmmfnnditali^uasformas. 
tur  eis  formas  et  virtutes  quasdam  seu  quaHtates  supernaturales,  secun- 
quae  sunt  principia  actuum.  .  .  .  dura  quas  suaviter  et  prompte  ab  ipso 
Multo  igitur  magis  illos  quos  movet  moveantur  ad  bonura  seternum  con- 
ad  consequendum  bonum  supernatur-  sequendum.'— 1°"  2<Ue  Q.  110.  A.  2. 


286  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

and  the  completeness  of  the  universe  requires  a  difference 
of  grades,  some  high  and  others  low  in  it.  And  on  this 
account  Grod  permits  evils  to  take  place,  lest  good  should 
be  obstructed  by  its  own  abundance,  and  to  preserve  this 
multiformity  of  grades  in  the  universe.  And  He  deals 
with  the  human  race  as  He  does  with  the  universe, — He 
represents  His  goodness  with  that  variety  which  is  neces 
sary  to  such  representation,  in  the  shape  of  mercy  to  those 
whom  He  spares,  of  punishment  to  those  whom  He  repro 
bates "  Grod  willing  to  show  His  wrath,  and  to 

make  His  power  known,  endured  (i.e.  permitted)  with 
much  long-suffering  the  vessels  of  wrath  fitted  to  destruc 
tion,  that  He  might  make  known  the  riches  of  His  glory 
on  the  vessels  of  mercy,  which  He  had  afore  prepared  for 
glory  ;"  and  "in  a  great  house  there  are  not  only  vessels  of 
gold  and  silver,  but  also  of  wood  and  earth,  and  some  to 
honour  and  some  to  dishonour."  But  why  He  has  elected 
these,  and  reprobated  those,  there  is  no  reason  but  the 
Divine  Will,  as  Augustine  saith,  "  Why  He  draws  this  man, 
and  not  that,  do  not  inquire,  if  thou  wouldest  not  err." 
Just  as  in  natural  things,  a  reason  can  be  assigned,  why 
out  of  uniform  elemental  matter  one  part  is  put  under  the 
form  of  fire,  and  another  under  the  form  of  earth,  and  so 
on ;  but  why  this  or  that  part  of  matter  is  chosen  for  this 
or  that  form  none  can  be,  except  the  arbitrary  will  of  the 
Creator :  and  as  in  the  case  of  a  building  there  is  a  reason 
why  some  stones  or  other  should  be  put  in  particular  places, 
but  why  these  or  those  stones  are  selected  to  be  put  in  the 
places,  none — except  the  arbitrary  will  of  the  builder.' ! 
Two  interpretations  evidently  divide  this  explanation  and 
defence  of  reprobation,  one  a  severer,  the  other  a  milder 
one.  It  is  spoken  of  as  positive  evil,  punishment  on  sin — 

1  '  Sicut  in  rebus  naturalibus  po-  forma,  et  ilia  sub  alia,  dependet  ex 

test  assignari  ratio,  cum  prima  ma-  simplici  divina  voluntate ;  sicut  ex 

teria  tota  sit  in  se  uniformis,  quare  simplici  voluntate  artificis  dependet 

una  pars  ejus  est  sub  forma  ignis,  et  quod   ille   lapis   est  in     ista   parte 

alia  sub  forma  terrse  a  Deo  in  prin-  parietis,  et  ille  in  alia,  quamvis  ratio 

cipio  condita,  ut  sic  sit  diversitas  artis  habeat  quod  aliqui  sint  in  hac, 

specierum  in  rebus  naturalibus;  sed  et  aliqui  sint  in  ilia.' — !"•  Q.   23. 

quare  haec  pars  materiae  est  sub  ista  A.  5. 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  287 

vindicta,  justitice ;  and  it  is  spoken  of  as  lower  good,  for  it 

is  represented  as  a  lower  grade  in  the  scale  of  being 

infimus  locus  in  universo.  But,  according  to  Aquinas,  evil 
is  no  part  of  the  universe,  of  which,  however  varied  and 
graduated  that  good  may  be,  the  whole  is  good ;  so  that  a 
lower,  or  the  lowest  place  in  it  is  a  place  of  good  and  not 
of  evil.  And  according  as  reprobation  is  regarded  in  one 
light  or  the  other,  the  appeal  in  defence  of  it  is  made  either 
to  original  sin  or  the  principle  of  variety  in  nature. 

The  religious  philosophy  of  Aquinas,  then,  of  which 
these  are  the  hints,  tends  simply  to  two  different  moral 
creations,  a  higher  and  a  lower  one.  The  natural  man  is 
created  and  has  the  advantages  of  his  creation  ;  the  spiri 
tual  man  is  created  and  has  the  advantages  of  his  :  and 
predestination  marks  for  a  special  glory,  and  a  higher  place 
in  the  universe  ;  but  exclusion  from  it  does  not  involve 
positive  evil  or  misery.  But  it  is  remarkable  that,  while 
he  systematically  hints  at  such  a  conclusion  as  this,  in  one 
peculiar  remote  and  isolated  case  alone  does  he  apply  it — 
a  case  outside  of  the  general  mass  of  moral  beings  which 
it  so  deeply  affects,  and  to  which  the  substantial  interest 
of  any  application  of  it  attaches — the  case  of  infants 
dying  unbaptized  or  in  original  sin.  Yet  the  elaborate 
and  minute  care  with  which  he  examines  this  particular 
case,  with  a  view  to  relieving  it  of  the  pressure  which  the 
Augustinian  doctrine,  in  its  natural  meaning,  left  upon  it, 
is  deserving  of  attention  ;  as  showing  the  strength  and 
firmness  of  the  basis,  which,  however  little  built  upon,  was 
formed  in  the  mind  of  the  writer  for  a  general  decision  on 
this  subject. 

Infants  dying,  then,  in  original  sin,  necessarily  came,  ac 
cording  to  the  pure  Augustinian  doctrine,  under  the  Divine 
wrath  which  was  due  to  that  sin.  Being  by  nature  repro 
bates,  and  not  being  included  within  the  remedial  decree  of 
predestination,  they  were,  in  common  with  all  the  rest  of 
mankind  who  were  bom  under  this  curse  and  were  not  re 
lieved  by  this  decree,  subject  to  the  sentence  of  eternal 
punishment ;  which  sentence  was  executed  upon  them.  How 
ever  repugnant,  then,  to  natural  reason  and  natural  feeling, 


2 88  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

the  Augustinian  schoolman  could  not  expressly  contradict 
this  position ;  but  what  he  could  not  contradict  he  could 
explain.  Augustine  had  laid  down  that  the  punishment  of 
such  children  was  the  mildest  of  all  punishments  in  hell — 
omnium  esse  mitisslmam.  Taking  this  as  the  authorised 
definition  of  the  punishment  of  unbaptized  infants,  he 
proceeded  to  raise  a  structure  of  explanation  upon  it.  First, 
was  the  punishment  of  such  infants  sensible  punishment 
— sensibilis  poena  ?  No  ;  because  then  it  would  not  be 
mitissima,  the  mildest  of  all.  Moreover,  sensible  pain  is 
a  personal  thing — personce  proprium,  and  therefore  in 
appropriate  to  a  kind  of  sin  which  is  not  personal.  Nor 
could  any  argument  be  drawn  from  the  fact,  that  children 
suffered  pain  in  this  world ;  because  this  world  was  not 
under  the  strict  law  of  justice,  as  the  next  was.  Nor  did 
this  immunity  from  pain  imply  in  their  case  any  invasion 
of  the  special  privilege  of  the  saints  ;  for  they  enjoyed  no 
internal  impassibility,  but  only  a  freedom  from  external 
causes  of  suffering.  Did  the  punishment  of  such  infants, 
again,  involve  affliction  of  soul — animce  afflictionem 
spiritualem  ?  No ;  for  such  affliction  must  arise  either 
on  account  of  their  sin,  or  of  their  punishment — de  culpa 
or  de  poena.  But  if  it  arose  on  account  of  their  sin,  it 
would  involve  despair  and  the  worm  of  conscience ;  in 
which  case  their  punishment  would  not  be  the  mildest  one, 
and  would  therefore  be  opposed  to  the  original  supposi 
tion.  If  it  arose  on  account  of  their  punishment,  it 
would  involve  an  opposition  in  their  will  to  the  will  of 
God ;  in  which  case,  their  will  would  actually  be  deformed 
—  actualiter  deformis  ;  which  would  imply  actual  sin,  and 
so  be  contrary  to  the  original  supposition. 

The  punishment  of  such  children,  then,  not  being  pain 
either  of  body  or  mind,  what  is  it  ?  Aquinas  answers,  it  is 
the  want  of  the  Divine  Vision,  or  exclusion  from  the  sight 
of  Grod — carentia  Divince  visionis,  quce  est  propria  et 
sola  poena  originalis  peccati  post  mortem ;  which  he 
proves  by  the  following  argument. 

Original  sin,  he  says,  is  not  the  corruption  of  natural 
good,  but  the  subtraction  of  supernatural ;  its  final  punish- 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  289 

ment  therefore  must  correspond,  and  be  the  exclusion,  not 
from  that  end  to  which  the  natural,  but  from  that  end 
only  to  which  the  supernatural  faculties  tend.  But  the 
end  of  the  supernatural  faculties  is  the  Divine  Vision.  It 
is  the  want,  then,  of  this  vision  which  is  the  punishment 
of  original  sin  ;  not  the  want  of  any  good  which  properly 
belongs  to  nature.  '  In  the  other  perfections  and  goods 
to  which  nature  tends  upon  her  own  principles,  those  con 
demned  for  original  sin  will  sustain  no  detriment.' l 

The  want  of  the  Divine  Vision,  however,  being  thus  laid 
down  as  the  punishment  of  unbaptized  infants,  an  argu- 
mental  obstacle  arose  from  the  quarter  of  the  original 
definition.  For,  according  to  Chrysostom,  the  exclusion 
from  the  sight  of  Grod  is  the  severest  part  of  the  punish 
ment  of  the  damned ;  at  any  rate  the  want  of  that  which 
we  wish  to  have  cannot  be  without  affliction,  and  unbap 
tized  infants  wish  to  have  the  sight  of  (rod — pueri  vellent 
DivinaJrm  visionem  habere ;  otherwise  their  wills  would  be 
actually  perverse.  It  would  therefore  appear,  that  this 
want  or  loss  would  be  affliction  to  them  ;  and  therefore, 
that,  if  this  were  their  punishment,  their  punishment 
would  not  be  the  mildest  of  all — mitissima.  Nor,  adds 
Aquinas,  is  it  any  answer  to  this  objection  to  say,  that  this 
exclusion  does  not  arise  from  their  own  personal  fault ;  for 
immunity  from  blame  does  not  diminish,  but  increase  the 
pain  of  punishment :  or,  again,  correct  to  say,  that  they 
are  happy  because  they  do  not  know  what  they  have  lost ; 
for  the  soul  freed  from  the  burden  of  the  ^  body  must 
know  whatever  reason  can  discover — et  etiam  multo 
plura. 

The  general  solution,  then,  of  this  difficulty,  is,  that  it 
is  no  pain  to  any  one  of  well-ordered  mind  not  to  have 
that  to  which  his  nature  is  in  no  way  proportioned,  pro 
vided  the  want  is  not  owing  to  any  personal  fault  of  his 
own.  A  man  regrets  the  disappointment  of  some  natural 
want,  even  though  he  is  not  to  blame  for  it ;  and  the 

1  '  In   aliis  autem   perfectionibus       nullum    detriment™     suatmebunt 
etbonitatibus  quse  naturam  huma-       propeccato  originali  daninati.  — 
nam  consequuntur  ex  suis  principiis,       Lomb.  1.  2.  Dist.  33.  U.  1.  A.  1. 


290  Scholastic  Doctrine  CHAP.  x. 

exclusion  from  a  good  exceeding  nature,  if  he  is.  But  the 
combination  of  blamelessness  in  himself  and  excess  in  the 
good  protects  him.  Such  a  case  comes  under  the  rule  of 
Seneca,  that  perturbation  does  not  fall  on  the  wise  man 
for  that  which  is  unavoidable ;  and  children  dying  under 
original  sin  alone  are  wise — sed  in  pueris  recta  est  ratio 
nullo  actuati  peccato  obliquata.  They  will  therefore  feel 
no  more  pain  under  the  want  which  attaches  to  their  con 
dition,  than  a  reasonable  man  does  because  he  cannot  fly 
like  a  bird,  or  because  he  is  not  a  king  or  an  emperor. 
Bather  they  will  rejoice  in  their  share  of  the  Divine  bounty, 
and  in  the  natural  perfections  they  will  have  attained.1 

It  will  be  seen  that  the  whole  of  this  elaborate  position 
rests  upon  a  particular  interpretation  of  original  sin;  viz., 
as  a  privation  or  loss  of  perfection,  and  not  a  positive  evil. 
Having  constructed  his  system  on  the  strict  Augustinian 
sense  of  original  sin,  Aquinas  falls  back  on  the  Clementine 
when  he  comes  to  an  individual  case  ;  and  avails  himself  of 
the  milder  theology  of  the  early  fathers.  Such  a  position, 
however,  when  once  laid  down  in  the  case  of  infants  dying 
under  original  sin,  evidently  cannot  stop  short  of  a  much 
wider  application.  Man  is  the  same,  as  regards  his  nature, 
whether  he  dies  as  an  infant  or  grows  up  to  maturity ;  and 
therefore  the  whole  condition  of  the  natural  man,  whether 

1  Sicut  nullus  sapiens  homo  affli-  putes  at  the  Council  of  Trent,  in 

gitur  de  hoc  quod  non  potest  volare  which  the  majority  appear  to  have 

sicut  avis,  vel  quia  non  est  rex  vel  favoured  the  position  of  Aquinas ; 

imperator;  cum  sibi  non  sit  de-  but  not  without  distinctions;  'For 

bitum.  .  .  .  Si  ab  hoc  deficiant  (qui  the  Dominicans  said  that  the  chil- 

liberum  arbitrium  habent),  maximus  dren  dead  without  baptism  before 

erit  dolor  eis  quia  amittunt  illucl  the  use  of  reason  remain  after  the 

quod  suum  esse  possibile  fuit.  Pueri  resurrection  in  a  limbo  and  darkness 

autem  nunquam  fuerunt  proportion-  under  the  earth,  but  without  fire ; 

ati  ad  hoc,  quod  vitam  aeternam  the  Franciscans  say  they  are  to  re- 

haberent,  quae  nee  eis  debebatur  ex  main  upon  the  earth,  and  in  light, 

principiis  naturae,  nee  actus  proprios  Some  affirmed  also,  that  they  should 

habere  potuerunt :  et  ideo  nihil  be  philosophers,  busying  themselves 

omnino  dolebunt  de  carentia  divinse  in  natural  things,-  not  without  that 

visionis:  immo  magis  gaudebunt  de  greatest  pleasure  which  happeneth 

hoc  quod  participabunt  multum  de  when  curiosity  is  satisfied  by  inven- 

divina  bonitate,  et  perfectionibus  tion,' — Paul's  History  of  the  Council 

naturalibus. — In  Lomb.  A.  2.  of  Trent. 

The  question  came  up  in  the  dis- 


CHAP.  x.  of  Predestination.  291 

heathen  or  professedly  Christian,  is  involved  in  this  conclu 
sion,  and  may  demand  admission  to  the  benefit  of  that 
explanation  which  the  particular  case  of  infants  has  evoked. 
The  life  which  is  conducted  upon  principles  of  honesty,  jus 
tice,  and  reason,  though  it  be  not  upon  that  of  Christian 
faith, — the  morality  of  the  conscientious  man  of  the  world, 
— in  a  word,  the  well  ordered  natural  life,  though  below 
the  spiritual,  may  claim  not  to  be  condemned.  And  while 
the  formal  theology  of  the  Augustinian  allows  no  interval 
between  the  child  of  (rod  and  the  child  of  the  devil,  the 
faithful  and  the  unbelieving,  the  spiritual  and  the  carnal 
man,  and  their  respective  ends,  eternal  happiness  and  eter 
nal  misery ;  a  modification  of  the  meaning  of  a  term,  iu 
one  particular  case,  undermines  in  principle  this  whole 
division ;  punishment  reduced  from  its  positive  to  a  merely 
negative  and  privative  sense,  becomes  another  word  for  a 
lower  reward,  and  admits  to  a  valuable  and  a  substantial, 
though  not  the  highest,  happiness,  both  in  this  life  and  the 
next,  that  not  inconsiderable  portion  of  mankind  who  are 
moral  without  being  spiritual,  well  disposed  without  faith, 
and  reasonable  without  illumination. 

It  may  be  added,  that  the  difficulty  involved  in  these 
considerations  is  one  which  meets  us  on  either  theory,  that 
of  necessity  or  of  freewill.  The  necessitarianism  indeed  of 
Aquinas  marks  the  natural  and  the  spiritual  life  alike  as 
creations  of  Grod  ;  but  however  we  may  account  for  them, 
the  natural  life  and  the  spiritual  life,  in  the  sense  in  which 
they  have  been  spoken  of,  exist  as  facts  in  the  world  ;  and 
we  see  these  two  moral  classes  and  types  around  us.  Scrip 
ture  speaks  indeed,  speaks  only  of  a  way  which  leadeth  to 
life,  and  a  way  which  leadeth  to  salvation  ;  and  separates 
the  few  who  attain  to  eternal  glory  from  a  wicked  world. 
But  it  must  be  confessed  that,  when  we  look  at  the  world 
around  us,  the  application  of  the  truth  of  Scripture  is  not 
free  from  difficulty,  and  that  it  depends  much  on  the  frame 
of  mind  which  we  assume,  and  the  point  of  view  which  we 
adopt,  whether  society  at  large  most  aptly  confirms  the 
scriptural  position,  or  apparently  contradicts  it.  In  one 
aspect  all  is  mixture  and  balance  in  the  world  of  moral  lite 

u  2 


292    Scholastic  Doctrine  of  Predestination.  CHAP.  x. 

around  us, — a  nicely  graduated  scale  of  human  character, 
division  gliding  into  division,  and  shade  deepening  or 
softening  into  shade.  Men  are  such  combinations  of  good 
and  evil,  that  we  hardly  know  where  to  place  them  ;  and  a 
large  portion  of  the  world  seems  to  occupy  a  middle  place, 
in  opposition  to  the  twofold  destination  of  mankind  in 
Scripture  to  glory  on  the  one  hand,  and  misery  on  the  other. 
The  idea  of  a  middle  state  has  thus  always  recommended 
itself  more  or  less  as  a  conjecture  to  human  thought ;  and 
a  tendency  to  this  doctrine,  even  where  not  formally  ex 
pressed,  is  observable  in  all  ages  of  the  Church ;  nor,  so 
long  as  the  facts  of  the  world  around  us  remain  the  same, 
will  it  be  otherwise.  In  another  aspect  the  world  presents 
itself  to  our  minds  in  harmony  with  the  scriptural  division, 
as  consisting  of  the  good  few  and  the  wicked  and  depraved 
mass  ;  vice,  selfishness,  and  corruption  appearing  the  gene 
ral  rule,  to  which  the  disinterestedness  or  genuine  goodness 
of  a  select  number  is  the  exception.  The  wickedness  of 
the  world  is  thus  a  recognised  maxim  in  the  world  itself; 
and  is  one  of  the  deepest  sentiments  of  the  human  mind, 
whose  universal  judgment  one  wise  man  of  even  heathen 
times  expressed  in  the  great  proverb. 

In  this  state  of  the  case  it  is  needless  to  add,  that  the 
plain  statements  of  Scripture  on  this  subject  are  to  be  im 
plicitly  received,  as  containing  certain  and  important  truth. 
One  great  division  of  mankind  is  seen  there,  that  of  good 
and  bad  ;  one  great  distinction  of  eternal  lot,  that  of 
heaven  and  hell.  It  remains  that  those  who  have  received 
this  revelation  should  act  accordingly,  and,  instead  of 
forming  conjectures  about  a  middle  state,  live  as  for  the 
highest.  Those  who  accept  a  revelation  generally  are 
bound  in  consistency  to  accept  its  plain  assertions  in  par 
ticulars  ;  nor  does  this  obligation  cease  because  difficulties 
may  follow.  Those  who  accept  a  revelation  accept  in  doing 
so  a  limitation  to  the  rights  of  human  reason.  There  are 
great  and  important  differences  in  the  Christian  world  as  to 
the  point  at  which  such  limitation  comes  in  ;  but  whether 
traditional  interpretation  of  Scripture,  or  a  present  infal 
lible  one,  or  the  letter  of  the  Bible  itself  is  the  check,  a 


CHAP.  xi.  Conclusion.  293 

check  to  private  judgment  is  implied  in  the  very  fact  of  a 
revelation,  and  is  the  common  admission  of  all  who  accept 
that  revelation ;  who  so  far — and  a  very  important  and 
vital  measure  of  agreement  it  is — agree  with  each  other. 
But  when  men  have  accepted  the  check  in  general,  they 
must  submit  to  it  in  the  particular  case.  There  is  no 
obligation  indeed  on  any  one  to  think  any  individual  either 
better  or  worse  than  his  observation  or  knowledge  of  his 
character  warrants  ;  rather  he  is  bound  not  to  do  so  :  nor, 
because  general  statements  are  made  in  Scripture  are  we 
bound  to  apply  them,  and  bring  particular  persons  under 
one  head  or  another.  An  impenetrable  veil  hides  the  heart 
of  one  man  from  another,  and  we  see  the  manifestation, 
but  not  the  substance,  of  the  moral  creature.  In  the 
application,  then,  of  the  scriptural  assertion  all  is  mystery 
and  uncertainty  ;  but  the  statement  itself  is  clear  and 
distinct ;  and  while  that  dispensation  of  ignorance  under 
which  we  are  placed,  in  mercy  as  well  as  discipline,  relieves 
us  from  the  difficulties  of  the  individual  case,  the  general 
truth  is  calculated  to  produce  the  most  salutary  effect 
upon  us. 


CHAPTER    XL 

CONCLUSION. 

IT  were  to  be  wished  that  that  active  penetration  and  close 
and  acute  attention  which  mankind  have  applied  to  so  many 
subjects  of  knowledge,  and  so  successfully,  had  been  applied, 
in  somewhat  greater  proportion  than  it  has  been,  to  the  due 
apprehension  of  that  very  important  article  of  knowledge, 
their  own  ignorance.  Not  that  all  men  have  not  acknow 
ledged,  and  in  some  sense  perceived,  this  truth.  How, 
indeed,  could  they  avoid  doing  so  ?  But  over  and  above 
thin  general  and  vague  confession  of  ignorance,  it  might 
have  been  expected,  perhaps,  that  more  would  have  at 
tained,  than  appear  to  have  done,  to  something  like  an 


294  Conclusion.  CHAP.  xr. 

accurate  or  philosophical  perception  of  it ;  such  as  arises 
from  the  mind's  contemplation  and  examination  of  itself, 
and  its  own  perceptions  ;  a  scrutiny  into  its  own  insight 
into  truth,  and  a  comparison  of  the  different  modes  in 
which  it  perceives  and  entertains  truth  ;  which  modes  or 
kinds  of  perception  widely  differ,  and  being  with  respect 
to  some  truths,  distinct,  complete,  and  absolute,  are  with 
respect  to  others  dim,  confused,  and  imperfect.  To  judge 
from  the  way  in  which  people  in  general  express  themselves 
on  this  subject  of  human  ignorance,  they  have  no  very 
accurate  perception  of  it ;  seldom  going  out  of  certain 
commonplace  phrases  and  forms  of  speech,—  forms  of 
speech,  indeed,  which  mean  much  when  used  by  those  who 
see  their  true  meaning,  but  mean  much  less,  though  still 
perhaps  something,  when  used  vaguely  and  without  atten 
tion,  and  because  the  whole  thing  is  taken  for  granted 
immediately,  and  then  dismissed  from  the  mind.  This 
general  admission  and  confession  of  the  fact,  is  all  that  the 
mass  of  men  appear  to  attain  to  on  this  important  ques 
tion  ;  and  doubtless  it  is,  as  far  as  it  goes,  a  useful  and 
serviceable  conclusion  of  the  mind —  especially  in  the  case 
of  devout  persons,  whose  piety  compensates  for  the  want 
of  clearness  in  their  ideas,  and  sustains  in  them  a  perpetual 
practical  perception  of  this  truth,  together  with  its  natural 
fruits  of  humility,  sobriety,  and  resignation. 

But  though  it  is  undoubtedly  a  matter  of  regret  that 
more  should  not  have  attained,  than  appear  to  have  done, 
to  something  like  an  accurate  and  philosophical  perception 
of  their  own  ignorance ;  the  explanation  of  this  fact  is 
contained  in  the  very  statement  of  it,  as  just  given.  For 
this  deeper  perception  cannot  be  gained,  but  by  those 
minds  that  have  gone  through  something  of  that  process 
of  thought,  which  has  been  just  referred  to.  Men  must 
have  reflected  upon  themselves,  and  examined  to  a  certain 
extent  the  constitution  of  their  own  minds,  their  percep 
tions,  or  modes  of  entertaining  truth,  in  order  to  have 
gained  it.  But  this  internal  department  is  not  one  in 
which  any  large  proportion  of  men  take  much  interest ; 
and  a  taste  for  this  kind  of  inspection  is  perhaps  rarer 


CHAP.  xi.  Conclusion. 


295 


than  any  other, — I  mean  as  a  taste  seriously  and  regularly 
adopted,  and  made  a  work  of.  Many  indeed  start  with 
something  like  a  general  taste  or  a  fancy  for  metaphysics, 
which  they  indulge  so  long  as  it  gives  them  little  trouble, 
and  merely  ministers  to  pleasing  vague  sensations  of  depth, 
and  love  of  the  unknown  and  indefinite ;  affording  a  do 
main  for  dreamy  and  vaporous  evolutions  of  thought,  cloudy 
connections,  and  fictitious  ascents  of  the  intellect, — reason 
ings  somewhat  akin  to  what  people  carry  on  in  sleep,  and 
pursued  as  a  mere  diversion  and  vent  to,  rather  than  an 
exercise  of,  the  mind.  But  the  taste  is  given  up  as  soon 
as  they  have  to  examine  facts,  to  fasten  their  ideas  upon 
real  things, — real  truths  within  the  actual  mind, — for  the 
purpose  of  apprehension  and  knowledge.  This  internal 
field  of  examination,  I  say,  is  not  to  the  taste  of  any 
large  proportion  of  minds ;  because  it  requires  a  more 
patient  sort  of  attention,  a  more  enduring  and  passive 
attitude  of  the  whole  mind,  than  is  ordinarily  congenial 
to  the  human  temper.  The  act  necessary  here  is  an  act 
of  simple  internal  observation,  which,  while  it  is  a  very 
difficult  one  in  this  particular  department,  owing  to  the 
obscurity  and  subtlety  of  its  subject  matter,  is  at  the  same 
time  a  quiet  one ;  for  quiet  is  essential  to  secure  correct 
ness  of  observation  in  metaphysics  as  in  nature.  But 
this  combination  is  a  distasteful  one  to  most  minds.  In 
life,  practical  or  intellectual,  the  general  compensation  for 
difficulty  is  the  pleasure  of  action  ;  for  passiveness,  that 
of  repose.  The  energetic  man  delights  in  obstacles  which 
summon  forth  all  his  powers  and  put  them  into  active 
operation  ;  the  labour  is  forgotten  in  the  satisfaction  of 
exertion,  and  the  legitimate  play  and  excitement  of  the 
whole  system  carry  off  the  task,  and  convert  it  into  a 
pleasure.  The  natural  activity  of  the  human  mind,  again, 
so  opposed  to  the  passive  attitude  ordinarily,  puts  up  with 
it  at  certain  intervals,  for  the  sake  of  rest,  and  enjoys  it. 
But  difficulty  with  passiveness,  is  uncongenial.  We  want 
always,  when  we  are  at  work,  to  feel  ourselves  in  progress, 
in  action,  advancing  step  after  step ;  and  the  attitude  of 
standing  still  in  thought,  though  it  be  for  an  important 


\ 


296  Conclusion.  CHAP.  xr. 

result,  though  it  be  consciously  only  a  waiting  in  readiness 
to  catch  some  idea  when  it  may  turn  up,  is,  for  the  time 
that  it  is  such  a  waiting,  and  previous  to  its  reward,  a 
painful  void  and  hollowness  of  the  mind.  But  such  is 
the  attitude  which  is  required  for  true  analytical  thought, 
or  the  mind's  examination  of  itself.  For  the  ideas  which 
are  the  contents  of  that  inward  world,  wandering  in  and 
out  of  darkness,  emerging  for  an  instant  and  then  lost 
again,  and  carried  about  to  and  fro  in  the  vast  obscure, 
are  too  subtle  and  elusive  to  be  subject  matter  of  regular 
and  active  pursuit ;  but  must  be  waited  and  watched  for, 
with  strength  suspended  and  sustained  in  readiness  to  catch 
and  fasten  on  them  when  they  come  within  reach  ;  but  the 
exertion  being  that  of  suspended  and  sustained,  rather  than 
of  active  and  employed,  strength.  And  if  this  line  of 
thought  in  general  is  opposed  to  the  tastes  of  the  mass,  so 
that  even  a  moderate  degree  of  application  to  it  is  too 
much  for  them,  and  even  that  lower  insight  into  this  de 
partment  of  truth,  which  minds  of  average  ability  may 
gain,  is  a  part  of  knowledge  into  which  they  are  not 
admitted, — by  what  a  wide  and  immeasurable  interval  are 
they  separated  from  the  great  analytical  minds  which  have 
appeared  in  the  world,  who,  with  unwearied  patience  and 
keen  exertion  of  the  intellectual  eye,  have  caught  sharp 
glimpses  of  the  great  ideas  and  processes  of  the  human 
reason, — quick  and  momentary  sights,  which,  impressed 
by  their  vividness  upon  the  memory,  and  thence  transferred 
to  paper,  have  enabled  them  in  a  certain  sense  to  bring 
the  human  mind  to  light,  to  mark  its  main  outlines,  and 
distinguish  its  different  perceptions  or  ideas;  by  which 
genuine  and  authentic  originals  they  have  then  tested 
current  popular  and  second-hand  truths. 

This,  then,  is  the  reason  why  more  have  not  attained 
than  have  to  an  accurate  perception  of  their  own  ignorance 
as  human  creatures.  For  this  correcter  and  truer  percep 
tion  of  ignorance  is  the  correlative  of  a  correcter  and 
truer  knowledge.  Of  the  human  mind  there  is  a  luminous 
and  there  is  a  dark  side.  The  luminous  side  is  that  on 
which  it  clearly  perceives  and  apprehends  truths,  either  by 


CHAP.  xi.  Conclusion.  297 

simple  apprehension,  or  by  demonstrative  reasoning :  the 
dark  side  is  that  on  which  it  does  not  perceive  in  either 
of  these  two  ways  ;  but  either  does  not  see  at  all,  and  has 
a  blank  before  it,  or  has  only  an  incipient  and  indistinct 
sight,  not  amounting  to  perception  or  apprehension.1  In 
proportion,  then,  to  the  acuteness  with  which  the  mind 
perceives  truth,  either  by  apprehension  or  by  demonstra 
tion,  on  its  luminous  side,  in  that  proportion  it  sees  the 
defect  of  perception  on  its  dark  side.  The  clearness  of 
knowledge,  where  it  is  had,  reveals  and  exposes  by  the 
contrast  its  absence,  where  it  is  not  had ;  and  the  transi 
tion  from  light  heightens  the  obscurity.  Each  successive 
step  of  demonstrative  reasoning,  by  which  a  problem  in 
mathematics  is  proved,  from  the  first  up  to  the  conclusion, 
is  accomplished  by  means  of  a  certain  light  contained 
within  it — an  overpowering  light,  to  which  the  mind  suc 
cumbs,  unable  to  resist  its  penetrating  force,  but  pierced 
through  by  it,  as  by  lightning.  Even  that  elementary  and 
primary  piece  of  demonstrative  reasoning  which  is  called 
an  axiom, — that  first  inference  or  extraction  of  one  truth 
from  another,  which,  in  the  department  of  demonstration, 
we  are  called  upon  to  make, — is  accomplished  by  means 
of  such  a  vivid  and  penetrating  light  contained  within  it ; 
so  that  the  perception  of  the  simplest  axiom,  where  such 
perception  is  a  true  and  not  a  formal  one,  is,  by  reason  of 
this  perfection  of  light  in  it,  an  illumination  for  the  time 
of  the  whole  intellect,  and  may  be  regarded  as  a  kind  of 
natural  inspiration,  answering  to  passion  or  emotion  in 
moral  life.  In  proportion,  then,  to  the  keenness  with  which 
this  process  goes  on,  is  the  reaction  from  it ;  after  the  clear 
ness  of  sight  the  change  is  all  the  greater  to  its  dimness 
and  indistinctness ;  and  the  reason  turning,  while  full  of 
penetrating  light  from  one  side,  upon  the  darkness  of  the 
other,  receives,  as  it  were,  a  shock,  by  the  violence  of  the 
contrast.  The  difference  between  seeing  truth  and  not 
seeing  it,  between  knowledge  and  ignorance,  is  felt  in  a 
degree  and  manner  in  which  those  who  have  not  attained 
such  sight  or  knowledge,  cannot  feel  it.  The  analytical 
1  See  Chapter  II. 


298  Conclusion.  CHAP.  XT, 

class  of  intellects  that,  not  satisfied  with  the  vague  first- 
sight  impressions  and  notions  of  things,  follow  them  up  to 
that  ultimate  point  at  which  they  are  plainly  seen  to  be 
either  true  or  false, — that  draw  the  contents  of  the  mind 
from  their  obscurity  to  the  test  of  an  actual  examination, 
—that  see  clearly  the  truth  they  do  see,  whether  as  simply 
apprehended,  or  as  extracted  from  other  truth ; — these 
minds,  in  proportion  to  the  keenness  with  which  they  are 
conscious  of  perceiving  truth,  when  they  do  perceive  it, 
know  that  they  have  got  hold  of  it,  and  that  no  power  can 
wrest  it  from  them, — in  proportion,  i.e.*  to  the  measure  in 
which,  in  the  department  of  knowledge,  they  are  filled 
with  the  light  of  clear  apprehension  or  demonstrative  rea 
soning, — see  the  distinction  between  this  mode  of  percep 
tion  and  that  which  awaits  them  when  they  leave  the 
scientific  ground,  and  turn  from  the  truths  of  knowledge 
to  those  of  faith  and  of  religion.  They  see,  in  consequence 
of  their  appreciation  of  final  truth,  so  much  the  more 
clearly  the  defect  of  that  which  is  not  final ;  and  that 
which  has  come  to  a  point  contrasts  the  more  strongly, 
with  that  which  comes  to  none,  but  which  vanishes  and  is 
gone  before  it  reaches  a  conclusion  ;  ever  beginning,  ever 
tending  to  some  goal,  but  never  attaining  it ;  stopping 
short,  as  it  does,  at  its  very  starting,  and,  in  the  very  act 
of  progress,  absorbed  in  the  atmosphere  of  obscurity,  which 
limits  our  mental  view.  Then,  under  the  influence  of  such 
a  contrast,  it  is,  that,  the  reason  pauses,  stops  to  consider, 
to  reflect,  and  then  says  to  itself — this  is  ignorance. 

And  these  considerations,  while  they  serve  to  explain 
why  more  have  not  attained  to  an  accurate  knowledge  of 
their  own  ignorance,  as  human  creatures,  than  appear  to 
have  done,  serve,  also,  to  temper  our  regret  at  such  a 
deficiency ;  for  it  must  be  seen,  on  the  bare  description  of 
such  a  deep  and  peculiar  perception  of  ignorance  as  I  am 
now  referring  to,  that  it  is  a  state  of  mind  not  unattended 
by  danger.  No  perception  of  ignorance,  indeed,  however 
strong,  can  be  charged  with  any  legitimate  tendency  to 
produce  unbelief;  for  it  does  not  follow  that,  because  we 
see  some  truths  clearly  and  others  obscurely,  some  finally 


CHAP.  xi.  Conclusion. 


299 


and  others  incompletely  and  but  in  commencement,  that 
therefore  we  may  not  hold  these  latter  truths  so  far,  how 
ever  little  way  that  may  be,  as  we  do  perceive  them,  and 
accept  and  use  them  in  that  sense  and  manner  in  which 
we  find  our  minds  able  to  entertain  them.  And  thus  the 
truths  of  natural  and  revealed  religion,  incomprehensible 
as  they  are,  are  proper  subject  matter  of  belief.  Our 
minds  are  constituted  in  such  a  way,  as  that  we  can  enter 
tain  this  class  of  truths,  which  are  not  subject  matter  of 
knowledge,  and  yet  fall  under  some  indistinct  sort  of  per 
ception,  which  we  feel  properly  to  belong  to  us.  To  reject 
them,  then,  because  they  are  seen  imperfectly  and  obscurely, 
and  because  we  have  the  light  of  clear  apprehension  and 
demonstration  in  one  department,  to  claim  it,  and  be  con 
tent  with  nothing  else  in  another,  would  be  simply  unreason 
able.  The  deeper  sense  of  ignorance,  then,  has  no  legiti 
mate  tendency  to  lessen  belief  in  the  truths  of  natural 
and  revealed  religion :  more  than  this,  it  has  legitimately 
even  a  direct  tendency  to  strengthen  it ;  because  the  sense 
of  ignorance  tends  properly  to  produce  humility,  to  subdue, 
chasten,  and  temper  the  mind.  The  natural  result  of  see 
ing  how  poor  and  imperfect  creatures  we  are,  and  how 
small  and  limited  our  capacities,  is  to  lower  our  idea  of 
ourselves,  and  so  to  put  us  into  a  frame,  in  which  we  are 
the  more  ready  to  accept  and  use  whatever  measure  and 
kind  of  truth  we  may  possess  in  this  department.  But  it 
must  also,  on  the  other  side,  be  admitted,  that  there  is  a 
natural  tendency,  in  such  a  strong  contrast  as  that  which 
has  been  described,  to  overwhelm  that  class  of  truths 
which  has  the  disadvantage  in  it ;  and  that  minds  which 
turn,  full  of  the  clear  light  of  apprehension  and  reasoning, 
upon  the  obscurity  of  the  truths  of  faith,  will  be  apt  to 
suppose  that  they  see  nothing  because  they  do  not  see 
clearly,  and  that  they  have  a  simple  blank  before  them. 
And  the  natural  impatience  of  the  human  temper  will 
much  aid  such  a  conclusion ;  for  men  are  apt  to  see  every 
thing  in  extremes,  and  when  they  have  less  than  what  they 
want,  are  instantly  inclined  to  think  that  they  have  nothing. 
In  this  temper,  then,  men  set  down  the  ideas  belonging  to 


:oo  Conclusion. 


CHAP.   XI. 


religion,  as  not  only  indistinct,  but  as  no  ideas  at  all,  but 
mere  void  ;  and  urge  that  persons  are  under  a  mistake  in 
supposing  that  they  have  anything  really  in  their  minds 
when  they  profess  to  entertain  these  truths, — not  having, 
as  it  is  asserted,  any  idea  of  them.  In  this  way,  then, 
the  deeper  perception  of  ignorance  tends  to  lessen  belief 
in  the  truths  of  religion  ;  inclining  persons  to  set  them 
aside  altogether  as  truths  from  which  our  understandings 
are  entirely  separated  by  an  impassable  barrier,  and  with 
which,  therefore,  as  lying  whoDy  outside  of  us,  we  have  no 
concern.1 

Such  being,  then,  the  two  arguments  from  human 
ignorance,  the  two  modes  of  using  and  applying  the  fact, 
the  question  is,  supposing  the  mass  of  men  had  that  dis 
tinct  and  clear  perception  of  their  ignorance  which  analy 
tical  minds  acquire,  how  would  they  use  it  ?  Would  they 
use  it  for  the  purpose  of  deepening  their  humility,  chas 
tising  their  curiosity,  subduing  their  impatience  ?  Would 
they  frame  themselves  upon  a  pattern  of  intellectual  sub 
mission  and  be  grateful  for  such  a  measure  of  insight  into 
religious  truths  as  Grod  had  given  them  ?  or  would  they 
use  and  apply  it  in  the  other  way,  and,  struck  simply  by 
the  force  of  the  contrast  between  their  knowledge  in  one 
department  and  their  ignorance  in  another,  draw  from  it 
the  impatient  inference,  that  because  they  did  not  see  these 
truths  clearly,  they  did  not  see  them  at  all,  and  were 
rationally  disconnected  with  them?  It  is  to  be  feared 
that  the  natural  impatience  of  the  human  mind  would,  in 
the  majority  of  instances,  lean  to  the  latter  inference.  It  is 
indeed  true,  and  it  is  a  cheering  and  consolatory  fact,  that 
we  see  a  broad  division  among  the  great  analytical  minds 
on  this  head  ;  and  that  while  some  have  drawn  the  argument 
for  unbelief  from  the  fact  of  human  ignorance,  others  have 
drawn  from  it  the  argument  for  faith  ;  that  to  Hume  and 
Hobbes  on  the  one  side  we  may  oppose  Butler  and  Pascal 
on  the  other.  But  could  we  expect  that  the  generality  of 
men  would  exert  that  intellectual  self-discipline  which 

1  This   appears   to  have    been  Hume's   state  of  mind  with  respect  to 
religious  truths. 


CHAP.  xr.  Conclusion.  301 

these  devout  and  reverential  minds  did  ?  Would  not 
natural  impatience  rather  prevail,  and  the  more  immediate 
and  obvious  effect  of  a  contrast  be  yielded  to.  And  if  so, 
are  not  the  generality  of  men  spared  a  severe  trial,  with 
probably  an  unfavourable  issue,  in  not  having  in  the  first 
instance  this  deeper  sense  of  ignorance  at  all  ?  Is  not 
their  ignorance  veiled  in  mercy  from  them  by  a  kind  Pro 
vidence  ;  so  that,  with  respect  to  these  truths,  they  go  on 
for  their  whole  lives,  thinking  they  know  a  great  deal  more 
than  they  do  ?  Nor  does  this  apply  to  the  uninstructed 
and  uncultivated  part  of  mankind  only,  but  perhaps  even 
more  strongly  to  the  learned  and  controversial  class.  For, 
certainly,  to  hear  the  way  in  which  some  of  this  class 
argue,  and  draw  inferences  from  the  incomprehensible 
truths  of  revelation,  carrying  them,  as  they  say,  into  their 
consequences  and  logical  results,  upon  which,  however 
remote  and  far-fetched,  they  yet  insist,  as  if  they  were  of 
the  very  substance  of  the  primary  truth  itself; — to  judge, 
I  say,  from  the  long  and  fine  trains  of  inferences  drawn  by 
some  theologians  from  mysterious  doctrines, — endless  dis 
tinctions  spun  one  out  of  the  other  in  succession,  and  issu 
ing  in  subtleties  which  baffle  all  comprehension,  and  are, 
in  short,  mere  words  and  nothing  more,  but  for  which,  so 
long  as  at  each  successive  step  there  has  been  an  inference 
(or  something  which  to  the  controversially  wound-up  intel 
lect  or  fancy  at  the  time  appeared  such), — these  persons 
claim  the  most  absolute  deference  ;  as  if  some  subtlest  con 
ception  of  the  argumentative  brain,  some  needle's  point  so 
inconceivably  minute,  that  not  one  man  in  ten  thousand 
could  even  see  it  once  if  he  tried  for  his  whole  life,  were  of 
the  very  foundation  of  the  faith  ;— to  judge,  I  say,  from 
such  a  mode  of  arguing  from  religious  truths,  one  cannot 
avoid  two  reflections ;  one,  that  such  persons  do  not  know 
their  own  ignorance  ;  the  other,  that  it  is  probably  a  mercy 
to  them  that  they  do  not.  They  do  not  know  their  own 
ignorance  with  respect  to  these  truths ;  for  if  they  did, 
they  would  see  that  such  incomprehensible  truths  were  not 
known  premisses,  and  could  not  be  argued  upon  as  such, 
or  made  foundation  of  unlimited  inference :  and  that  they 


3<D2  Conclusion.  CHAP.  XT. 

do  not  know  it  is  probably  a  mercy  to  them ;  for  the  very 
same  hasty  and  audacious  temper  of  the  intellect  which 
leads  them  to  build  so  much  upon  assumptions,  the  nature 
of  which  they  have  never  examined,  would,  had  they 
examined  it,  and  so  arrived  at  a  real  perception  of  their 
unknown  nature,  have  inclined  them  to  reject  such  truths. 
Thus,  in  compassion  to  the  infirmity  of  man,  a  merciful 
Providence  hides  his  ignorance  from  him  ;  and  by  a  kind 
deceit,  such  as  parents  use  to  their  children,  allows  him  to 
suppose  that  he  knows  what  he  does  not  know.  He  is  thus 
saved  from  unbelief,  and  only  falls  into  a  well-meaning, 
though  foolish  and  presumptuous,  dogmatism. 

And  now,  to  bring  these  remarks  to  bear  on  the  subject 
of  this  treatise,  the  question  of  Divine  grace  is  a  question 
of  Divine  Power.  Grace  is  power.  That  power  whereby 
Grod  works  in  nature  is  called  power.  That  power  whereby 
He  works  in  the  wills  of  His  reasonable  creatures  is  called 
grace. 

With  respect,  then,  to  the  attribute  of  the  Divine 
Power,  S.  Augustine  and  his  school  took  up,  in  the  first 
instance,  a  hasty  and  ill-considered  position,  which,  once 
adopted,  committed  them  to  extreme  and  repulsive  results. 
And  the  reason  of  their  adopting  such  a  position  was,  that 
they  were  insufficiently  acquainted  with  the  limits  of 
human  reason.  For  it  must  be  evident  to  any  person  of 
reflection,  that  a  want  of  discernment  on  this  subject  is  not 
only  an  error  in  itself,  but  can  hardly  fail  to  be  the  source 
of  other  errors ;  because  persons  who  entertain  a  certain 
idea  with  respect  to  their  knowledge,  naturally  proceed  to 
act  upon  it  and  to  make  assertions  ;  and  it  must  be  a  chance 
whether  assertions  made  under  such  circumstances  are 
correct.  I  would  not  be  understood,  however,  to  cast  any 
blame  upon  these  writers.  The  limits  of  human  reason 
are  not  easy  to  discern.  It  is  not  easy,  as  I  have  said,  to 
judge  our  own  pretensions,  and  distinguish  between  one 
part  and  another  of  that  whole  body  of  ideas  and  assump 
tions  which  we  find  within  our  minds.  Some  philosophers 
have  settled  the  question  summarily,  by  saying  that  we 
know  nothing ;  others  have  extended  the  range  of  human 


CHAP.  xi.  Conclusion.  30^ 

\j   j 

knowledge  indefinitely,  and  given  it  a  right  to  decide  upon 
the  possibilities  of  things,  and  to  judge  the  scheme  of  Pro 
vidence.     To  draw  the  mean  between  these  two  extremes 
is  the  work  of  an  acute  and  original  judgment,  and  requires 
a   peculiar  constitution  of  mind.     The  tendency  of  even 
deep  and  able  minds  generally  is  so  immediately  to  fasten 
on  any  assumption,  especially  any  one  relating  to  divine 
things,  which  appears  at  first  sight  a  natural  one  to  them, 
that  their  very  power  becomes  a  snare,  and  before  they  have 
reflected  upon  an  idea  they  are  committed  to  it ;  so  that 
to  return  to  the  preliminary  question  of  its  truth  would  be 
in  the  highest  degree  difficult  to  them,  as  being  so  offen 
sive  to  an  already  formed  bias.     Indeed,  some  minds  of 
great  pretensions  appear  to  labour  under  a  moral  inability 
in  this  respect ;  their  intellect,  strong  in  pursuing  an  idea, 
is  so  utterly  unable  to  stop  itself  for  the  purpose  of  judg 
ment,  that  in  reference  to  that  particular  function  it  may 
be  said  to  have  almost  the  imperfection  of  a  mere  instinct, 
rather  than  to  operate  as  the  true  faculty  of  reason.     This 
mixture  of  singular  weakness   with   singular  power  it  is 
which  makes  the  task  of  estimating  authorities  so  difficult; 
opinions  of  the  greatest  value  on    details  and  collateral 
points  being  sometimes  of  the  very  least  on  fundamental 
questions,  or  those   concerned  with  the  soundness  or  un- 
soundness  of  original  assumptions.     Yet  assumptions  and 
particular  dicta,  laid  down  in  the  first  instance  by  minds 
of  this  latter  class,  have  had  great  weight  and  a  long  reign 
in  the  world ;  one  writer  taking  them  up  after  another ; 
till  some  person  of  original  powers  of  judgment  has  risen 
up  who,  on  comparing  an  assertion  carefully  with  his  own 
knowledge,  has  discovered  a  want  of  connection  between 
the  two.     He  has  not  seen  such  truth  included  within  that 
field  of  apprehended  truth,  set  out  and  divided  from  that 
of  conjecture,  in  his  mind  ;  and  this  negative  discovery  once 
made,  has,  like  other  discoveries,  approved  itself  to  the 
world,  people  seeing  it  when  it  was  pointed  out  to  them. 
Such  a  judgment  passed  upon  any  important  set  of  assump 
tions  is  a  discovery  in  philosophy;  and  in  this  respect 
modern  philosophy  has  improved  much  upon  the  ancient. 


304  Conclusion.  CHAP.  xi. 

It  has  given  us  an  acquaintance  with  the  limits  of  human 
reason  which  we  had  not  before,  and  has  enabled  us  to 
distinguish  more  accurately  what  we  know  from  what  we 
do  not  know,  what  we  can  say  from  what  we  cannot,  on 
some  important  questions ;  it  has  tested  the  correctness  of 
many  important  assumptions  :  but  it  does  not  follow  that 
those  are  particularly  to  blame  who  wrote  before  such  im 
provement  in  the  acquaintance  with  the  limits  of  human 
reason  took  place. 

On  this  definite  basis,  then,  and  with  the  great  dis 
advantage  of  a  less  accurate  knowledge  of  the  limits  of 
human  reason  than  has  been  attained  in  more  recent  times, 
S.  Augustine  and  his  school  proceeded  to  the  general  ques 
tion  of  the  Divine  Omnipotence.  And  they  commenced 
with  an  assumption,  which  no  modern  philosopher  would 
allow,  that  the  Divine  Power  must  be  an  absolutely  un 
limited  thing.  That  the  Divine  Power  is  not  liable  to  any 
foreign  control  is  a  principle  which  every  one  must  admit 
who  believes  properly  in  a  Deity  ;  but  that  there  is  no 
intrinsic  limit  to  it  in  the  possibilities  of  things  would  not 
be  admitted,  in  the  present  state  of  philosophy,  in  which 
this  whole  subject  is  properly  understood  to  be  out  of  the 
range  of  human  reason.  The  Divine  Omnipotence  must 
be  admitted  practically  and  in  every  sense  which  can  be 
wanted  for  the  purpose  of  religion ;  but  we  have  not  facul 
ties  for  speculation  upon  its  real  nature.  These  writers, 
however,  insisted  on  an  unlimited  omnipotence,  arguing 
logically  upon  the  simple  word  or  abstract  idea,  that  if 
omnipotence  was  limited,  it  was  not  omnipotence.  And 
upon  this  assumption  they  went  on  to  assert  that  God  could, 
had  He  pleased,  have  created  a  better  universe  than  He 
has ;  a  universe  without  evil  and  without  sin  ;  and  that, 
sin  existing  in  the  world,  He  could  by  His  simple  power 
have  removed  it,  and  have  changed  the  wills  of  all  wicked 
men  from  evil  to  good.  Upon  such  an  idea  of  the  Divine 
Power,  these  writers  were  indeed  somewhat  perplexed  for 
an  answer  to  the  objection  which  naturally  arose  to  the 
Divine  Goodness.  A  limit  supposed  to  the  possibilities  of 
things  is  indeed  an  impregnable  defence  to  the  theologian 


CFAP.  xi.  Conclusion.  305 

on  this  question  ;  for  no  one  can  be  blamed  for  not  doing 
that  which  is  impossible.  But  if  this  limit  is  not  allowed, 
and  if  God  could  have  created  a  universe  with  all  the  ad 
vantages  of  the  present  one  and  none  of  its  evils,  and  if, 
when  moral  evil  had  begun,  He  could  have  removed  it ;  it 
is  certainly  very  difficult  to  answer  the  question  why  He 
did  not ;  for  we  necessarily  attribute  consummate  benevo 
lence  to  the  Deity.  The  explanation  of  such  a  difficulty 
on  the  principle  of  variety,  that  evil  and  good  together, 
with  their  respective  reward  and  punishment,  redound  to 
the  glory  of  God  more  than  good  alone  of  itself  would  do, 
is  futile  and  puerile.  Variety  is,  ccvteris  paribus,  an  ad 
vantage;  and  we  praise  God's  natural  creation,  not  only 
because  it  is  good,  but  because  that  good  is  various.  Nor 
would  it  be  reasonable  to  object  to  different  degrees  of 
good  in  the  created  universe ;  to  complain  because  the 
earth  was  not  as  beautiful  all  over  as  it  is  at  its  most 
beautiful  part,  or  because  all  the  birds  of  the  air  have  not 
the  colours  of  the  tropical  birds  ;  or  even,  in  moral  life, 
because  all  have  not  the  same  moral  capabilities  or  power 
of  attaining  the  same  goodness.  But  when  it  comes  to  a 
comparison,  not  of  like  good  with  varied,  or  of  higher 
good  with  lower,  but  of  good  with  evil,  the  case  is  very 
different. 

Upon  this  abstract  idea,  then,  of  the  Divine  Power,  as 
an  unlimited  power,  rose  up  the  Augustinian  doctrine  of 
Predestination  and  grace ;  while  upon  the  abstract  idea  of 
free-will,  as  an  unlimited  faculty,  rose  up  the  Pelagian 
theory.  Had  men  perceived,  indeed,  more  clearly  and 
really  than  they  have  done,  their  ignorance  as  human 
creatures,  and  the  relation  in  which  the  human  reason 
stands  to  the  great  truths  involved  in  this  question,  they 
might  have  saved  themselves  the  trouble  of  this  whole 
controversy.  They  would  have  seen  that  this  question  can 
not  be  determined  absolutely,  one  way  or  another ;  that  it 
lies  between  two  great  contradictory  truths,  neither  < 
which  can  be  set  aside,  or  made  to  give  way  to  the  other 
two  opposing  tendencies  of  thought,  inherent  in  the  human 
mind,  which  go  on  side  by  side,  and  are  able  to  be  hel< 

x 


306  Conclusion.  CHAP.  xi. 

and  maintained  together,  although  thus  opposite  to  each 
other,  because  they  are  only  incipient,  and  not  final  and 
complete  truths  ; — the  great  truths,  I  mean,  of  the  Divine 
Power  on  the  one  side,  and  man's  freewill,  or  his  originality, 
as  an  agent,  on  the  other.     And  this  is,  in  fact,  the  mode 
in  which  this  question  is  settled  by  the  practical  common 
sense  of  mankind.     For  what  do  the  common  phrases  em 
ployed  in   ordinary    conversation   and  writing  upon  this 
question — the  popular  and  received  modes  of  deciding  it, 
whenever   it  incidentally  turns  up — amount  to  but  this 
solution  ?     Such  phrases,  I  mean,  as  that  we  must  hold 
man's  freewill  together  with  God's  foreknowledge  and  pre 
destination,  although  we  do  not  see  how  they  agree ;  and 
other  like  formulae.     Such  forms  of  language  for  deciding 
the  question  evidently  proceed  upon  the  acknowledgment 
of  two  contradictory  truths  on  this  subject,  which  can  not 
be  reconciled,  but  must  be  held  together  in  inconsistency. 
They  imply  that  the  doctrine  of  predestination  and  the 
doctrine  of  freewill  are  both  true,  and  that  one  who  would 
hold  the  truth  must  hold  both.     The  plain  natural  reason 
of  mankind  is  thus  always  large  and  comprehensive  ;  not 
afraid   of   inconsistency,   but    admitting    all  truth  which 
presents  itself  to  its  notice.     It  is  only  when  minds  begin 
to  philosophise  that  they  grow  narrow, — that  there  begins 
to  be  felt  the  appeal  to  consistency,  and  with  it  the  tempta 
tion  to  exclude  truths.     Then  begins  the  pride  of  argument, 
the  ingenuity  of  construction,  the  '  carrying  out '  of  ideas 
and  principles  into  successive  consequences  ;  which,  as  they 
oecome  more  and  more  remote,  and  leave  the  original  truth 
at  a  distance,  also  carry  the  mind  of  the  reasoner  himself 
away  from  the  first  and  natural  aspect  of  that  truth,  as 
imperfect  and  partial,  to  an  artificial  aspect  of  it  as  whole 
and  exclusive.     While   the  judgment,  however,  of  man's 
plain  and  natural  reason  on  this  question  is  a  comprehen 
sive  one,  men  have,  on  this  as  on  other  subjects,  left  the 
ground  of  plain  and  simple  reason  for  argument  and  philo 
sophy  ;  and  in  this  stage  of  things  they  have  adopted  man's 
freewill  or  the  Divine  Power  as  favourite  and  exclusive 
truths,  and  have  erected  systems  upon  them.  The  Pelagian 


CHAP.  xr.  Conclusion. 


307 


and  Augustinian  systems  are  thus  both  at  fault,  as  arising 
upon  narrow,  partial,  and  exclusive  bases.  But  while  both 
systems  are  at  fault,  they  are  at  fault  in  very  different 
degrees  and  manners  ;  and  while  the  Augustinian  is  only 
guilty  of  an  excess  in  carrying  out  certain  religious  ideas, 
the  Pelagian  offends  against  the  first  principles  of  religion, 
and  places  itself  outside  of  the  great  religious  ideas  and 
instincts  of  the  human  race. 

I.  The  predestinarian  is  at  fault  in  assuming  either 
the  Divine  Power,  or  original  sin,  as  singly  and  of  itself  a 
legitimate  basis  of  a  system, — in  not  allowing  side  by  side 
with  these  premisses  a  counter  premiss  of  freewill  and 
original  power  of  choice.  While  he  properly  regards  the 
created  will  as  an  effect,  he  is  wrong  in  not  also  regarding 
it  as  a  first  cause  in  nature.  But  while  this  is  a  decided 
error,  and  an  error  which  has  dangerous  moral  tendencies 
when  adopted  by  undisciplined  minds,  it  is  not  in  itself  an 
offence  against  morals  or  piety,  The  predestinarian,  while 
he  insists  on  the  will's  determination  from  without,  still 
allows  a  will ;  he  does  not  regard  man  as  an  inanimate 
machine,  but  as  a  living,  willing,  and  choosing  creature. 
And  as  he  admits  a  will,  he  assigns  in  every  respect  the 
same  moral  nature  to  man  that  his  opponent  does  ;  he  im 
poses  the  same  moral  obligations,  the  same  duty  to  God 
and  our  neighbours  ;  he  inculcates  the  same  affections,  he 
maintains  exactly  the  same  standard  in  morals  and  reli 
gion  that  his  opponent  maintains.  It  is  true  his  theory, 
as  taken  up  by  the  careless  unthinking  mass,  tends  to 
immorality  ;  for  the  mass  will  not  see  distinctions,  and 
confound  the  predestination  of  the  individual,  as  holy  and 
virtuous,  with  the  predestination  of  the  individual  as  suck, 
to  eternal  life;  and  because  the  end  is  assured,  suppose  it 
to  be  assured  without  the  necessary  means  and  qualifica 
tions  for  it.  And  such  a  practical  tendency  in  the  doctrine, 
however  justly  it  may  be  charged  to  a  misapprehension 
and  mistake  in  some  who  adopt  it,  is  still  a  reflection  upon 
the  doctrine  itself;  showing  how  truth  cannot  be  tampered 
with  without  bad  practical  effects ;  and  that  exclusive  and 

x  2 


308  Conchtsion.  CHAP.  xi. 

one-sided  theories  are  a  stumbling  block  to  ordinary  minds, 
tending  to  confuse  their  reason  and  moral  perceptions. 
Still,  regarding  the  error  of  the  predestinarian  apart  from 
those  consequences  which  it  tends  practically  to  produce 
in  the  minds  of  the  vulgar,  but  which  are  not  legitimately 
deducible  from  it,  it  cannot  perhaps  be  called  much  more 
than  a  metaphysical  mistake, — an  overlooking  of  a  truth 
in  human  nature  ;  a  truth  indistinctly  perceived  indeed, 
but  still  perceived  in  that  sense  and  mode  in  which  many 
other  recognised  truths  are  perceived.  The  predestinarian 
passes  over  the  incomplete  perception  we  have  of  our  ori 
ginality  as  agents,  because  his  mind  is  preoccupied  with  a 
rival  truth.  But  this  cannot  in  itself  be  called  an  offence 
against  piety :  rather  it  is  occasioned  by  a  well-intended 
though  excessive  regard  to  a  great  maxim  of  piety.  He  is 
unreasonably  jealous  for  the  Divine  Attribute,  and  afraid 
that  any  original  power  assigned  to  man  will  endanger  the 
Divine.  He  thus  allows  the  will  of  man  no  original  part 
in  good  action,  but  throws  all  goodness  back  upon  the 
Deity,  as  the  sole  Source  and  Creator  of  it,  forming  and 
fashioning  the  human  soul  as  the  potter  moulds  the  clay. 
It  may  be  said,  indeed,  that  his  doctrine,  in  attributing 
injustice  to  the  Deity,  is  inconsistent  with  piety :  but  he 
does  not  attribute  injustice  to  the  Deity;  but  only  a 
mode  of  acting,  which,  as  conceived  and  understood  by 
us,  is  unjust ;  or  which  we  cannot  explain  in  consistency 
with  justice. 

II.  Pelagianism,  on  the  other  hand,  offends  against  the 
first  principles  of  piety,  and  opposes  the  great  religious 
instincts  and  ideas  of  mankind.  It  first  tampers  with  the 
sense  of  sin.  The  sense  of  sin  as  actually  entertained  by 
the  human  mind ;  that  sense  of  it  which  we  perceive,  ob 
serve,  and  are  conscious  of,  as  a  great  religious  fact — a  part 
of  our  moral  nature  whenever  sufficiently  enlightened — is 
not  a  simple,  but  a  mysterious  and  a  complex  sense  ;  not 
confined  to  positive  action,  as  the  occasion  of  it,  but  going 
further  back  and  attaching  itself  to  desire ;  nor  attaching 
itself  to  desire  only  as  the  effect  of  free  choice,  but  to 


CHAP.  xi.  Conclusion.  309 

desire  as  in  some  sense  necessary  in  us,  belonging  to  our 
present  condition  as  human  beings,  and  such  as  we  cannot 
imagine  ourselves,  in  our  present  state,  in  some  degree  or 
other  not  having.     Mankind   know  and  feel  that  sin  is 
necessary  in  this  world,  and  cannot  be  avoided  ;  yet  simul 
taneously  with  this  sense  of  its  necessity  they  mourn  over 
it,  and  feel  themselves  blameworthy.     A  sense  of  such  a 
peculiar  kind  as  this,  of  moral  evil,  is  indeed  mysterious 
and  incomprehensible,  but  it  is  a  fact ;  it  is  a  part  of  a  whole 
nature  which  cannot  be  explained,  made  up  as  it  is  of  appa 
rent  inconsistencies  and  contradictions.    But  the  Pelagian 
would  only  allow   so  much  of  this  whole  sense  of  sin  in 
human  nature  as  he  could  rationally  and  intelligibly  account 
for  :  he  could  understand  voluntary  but  not  necessary  sin, 
how  man's  acts,  but  not  how  his  nature  should  humble  him. 
He  therefore  rejected  the  doctrine  of  original  sin.     And  as 
he  tampered  with  the  sense  of  moral  evil,  so  he  rejected 
the  sense  of  moral  weakness.     He  could  not  understand 
that  discord  and  opposition  in  the  will  which  the  Apostle 
expresses  in  the  text,  '  To   will  is  present  with  me,  but 
how  to  perform  that  which  is  good  I  know  not ;  for  the 
good  that   I  would  I  do  not,  but  the   evil  which  I  would 
not  that   I   do  ;'  and  he  therefore   thrust  it  aside  for  a 
mere   abstract    conception    of   freewill,  pronounced    man 
to  have   a  power  of  doing  anything  to  which  there  was 
no    physical   hindrance,    and    placed    an    absolute   origin 
and  source  of  good  in  human  nature.     The  principle  of 
humility  in    human  nature  which   leads   it   to  eject  the 
source  of  good  from  itself,  and  place  it  wholly  in  God,  was 
thus  disowned ;   and  with  it  the  earnest  craving  of  human 
nature  for  an  atonement  for  sin  ;  for  if  mankind  had  the 
power  to  avoid  sin,  and  if  some,  as  he  maintained,  had 
actually  lived  without  it,  mankind  did  not  in  their  corpo 
rate  capacity  want  a  Saviour  ;  and  the  sense  of  this  vital 
need  did  not  belong  to  human  nature. 

And  in  disowning  these  doctrines  the  Pelagian  at  the 
same  time  opposed  himself  to  facts.  The  doctrine  of  the 
Fall,  the  doctrine  of  Grace,  and  the  doctrine  of  the  Atone 
ment  are  grounded  in  the  instincts  of  mankind.  It  is  true 


i  o  Conclusion. 


CHAP.  XI. 


we  receive  these  truths  by  revelation,  and  should  not  other 
wise  have  possessed  them  in  anything  like  the  fulness  in 
which  we  do.     But  when  revealed  they  are  seen  to  lie  deep 
in  the  human  conscience.     The  doctrine  of  original  sin 
lies  deep  in  the  human  heart,  which  has  never  truly  and 
earnestly  perceived  its  guilt  at  all,,  without  coupling  with 
it  the  idea  of  a  mysterious  alloy  and  taint  antecedent  to 
action,  and  coeval  with  its  own  life.     And  in  like  manner 
man  has  in  all  ages  craved  an  atonement  for  sin ;  he  has 
always  ejected  the  source  of  good  from  himself,  and  referred 
it  to  Grod.     These  are  religious  feelings  and  instincts  be 
longing  to  human  nature,  and  which  can  never  be  eradi 
cated  so  long  as  that  nature  remains  itself.     The  Pelagian, 
then,  in  rejecting  these  doctrines,  opposed  himself  to  facts, 
he  separated  himself  from  that  whole  actual  body  of  senti 
ment,  instinct,  and  feeling  which  constitutes  the  religious 
life  of  mankind,  and  placed   himself  outside  of  human 
nature.     A  true  system  of  religion  must  represent  these 
facts  ;   these  large,  these  deep,  these  powerful,  these  pene 
trating,  and  marvellous  instincts :  and  it  is  the  glory  of 
Catholic  Christianity  that  it  does  this,  that  it  expounds 
faithfully  the  creed  of  the  human  heart,  that  nothing  in 
human  nature  is  left  unrepresented  in  it ;  but  that  in  its 
vast  and  intricate  fabric  of  doctrine  is  reflected,  as  in  a 
mirror,  every  vague  perception  of  our  nature,  every  inex 
plicable  fear   and    desire,  grief  and  joy ;  every  internal 
discord,  unfinished  thought,  beginning  of  unknown  truth  ; 
all  that  in  the  religious  conscience,  will,  and  affections  can 
or  cannot  be  understood.     But  the  Pelagian  discarded  the 
religion  of  human  nature  and  of  fact,  for  an  idea  of  his  own 
mind  ;   because  his  own  idea  was  simple  and  intelligible, 
and  the  religion  of  human  nature  was  mysterious  and  com 
plex  ;  as  if,  when  facts  were  mysterious,  it  were  anything 
in  favour  of  the  truth   of  a   religion    that  it  was   not. 
Rather  as  if  such  an  absence  of  mystery  did  not  prove  that 
the  system  was  a  fiction  and  a  fancy  ;  the  artificial  produc 
tion  of  human  thought,  instead  of  a  true  revelation  from 
the  Author  of  nature,  who  makes  all  things  double  one  of 
another,  and  who  adapts  His  revelations  to  that  human 


CHAP.  xr.  Conclusion.  311 

nature  which  He  has  made.  Nature  and  revelation,  as 
having  the  same  source,  are  both  expressions  of  the  same 
truth,  and  must  correspond  with  each  other.  If  a  religion 
is  true,  then,  it  must  harmonise  with  that  whole  complex 
and  intricate  body  of  feelings  and  ideas,  of  which  human 
nature  is  really  and  actually  composed.  The  Pelagian, 
then,  or — to  take  the  stronger  instance — the  Socinian,  may 
appeal  to  the  simplicity  and  plainness  of  his  system,  that 
it  contains  no  obscure  and  incomplete,  no  discordant  and 
irreconcilable  ideas ;  but  if  he  does,  he  boasts  of  a  religion 
which  is  self-convicted  of  falsehood  and  delusion,  and  is 
proved  on  its  own  showing  to  be  a  dream.  Such  a  religion 
may  satisfy  a  mind  that  has  thought  out  a  belief  for  itself, 
and  has  allowed  a  particular  line  of  thought  to  lead  it  out 
of  the  great  circle  of  human  feelings  and  instincts,  but  it 
cannot  satisfy  the  natural  wants  of  the  human  heart ;  it 
may  please  and  amuse  in  comfort  and  tranquillity,  but  it 
will  not  support  in  distress ;  it  may  be  argued  for,  but 
it  cannot  be  loved  ;  and  it  may  be  the  creed  of  a  philo 
sopher,  but  it  is  not  the  religion  of  man. 

In  this  state  of  the  case  the  Church  has  made  a  wise 
and  just  distinction,  in  its  treatment  of  the  respective 
errors  of  the  Pelagian  and  the  predestinarian  ;  and  while  it 
has  cast  Pelagianism  out  of  its  communion,  as  a  system 
fundamentally  opposed  to  Christian  belief,  it  has  tolerated 
predestinarianism  ;  regarding  it  as  a  system  which  only 
carries  some  religious  ideas  to  an  excess,  and  does  not  err 
in  principle,  or  offend  against  piety  or  morals.  The  seven 
teenth  article  of  our  Church  has  accordingly  allowed  a 
place  for  a  predestinarian  school  among  ourselves ;  and  such 
a  school  has  long  existed,  and  still  exists  among  us.  This 
article  indeed  admits  of  two  interpretations,  and  may  be 
held  and  subscribed  to  in  two  ways,  one  suiting  the  believer 
in  freewill,  the  other  the  predestinarian.  It  may  be  held 
as  containing  one  side  of  the  whole  truth  respecting  grace 
and  freewill— the  side,  viz.,  of  grace  or  the  Divine  Power  ; 
but  not  at  all  as  interfering  with  any  one's  belief  m  a 
counter  truth  of  man's  freewill  and  originality  as  an  agent. 
And  in  this  sense  it  only  excludes  a  Pelagian,  and  not  such 


312  Conclusion.  CHAP.  xi. 

as  are  content  to  hold  a  mystery  on  this  subject,  and  main 
tain  the  Divine  Power  in  conjunction  with  man's  freewill. 
Or,  again,  this  article  may  be  held  as  containing  a  complete 
and  whole  truth;  i.e.  in  a  definitely  predestinarian  sense. 
But  as  it  would  be  unfair  in  the  predestinarian  to  prohibit 
the  qualified,  so  it  would  be  unfair  in  the  advocate  of  free 
will  not  to  allow  the  extreme  mode  of  holding  this  article, 
or  to  disallow  it  as  permitting  and  giving  room  for  a  pure 
predestinarian  school  within  our  Church.  This  wise  and 
just  liberty  has  indeed  at  times  offended  those  whom  the 
excesses  of  this  school  have  roused  to  hostility,  or  whom 
insufficient  reflection  and  the  philosophical  bias  of  the  day 
have  made  too  exclusive  and  dogmatic  in  their  opinions 
concerning  freewill ;  and  at  the  close  of  the  last  century  a 
proposal  was  made  by  a  Divine  who  became  afterwards  a  dis 
tinguished  prelate  of  our  Church,  to  ecclesiastical  authority, 
that  the  terms  of  the  seventeenth  article  should  be  altered 
and  so  framed  as  to  give  no  further  license  to  predesti- 
narianism.1  But  a  wise  caution,  if  not  a  profound  theology, 

1  About  this  time  a  circumstance  Article  on  Predestination  and  Elec- 

occurred.  which  then    excited  con-  tion   more   clear   and    perspicuous, 

siderable  interest,  and  in  which  the  and  less  liable  to  be  wrested  by  our 

part  that  Dr.  Porteous  took  has  been  adversaries  to  a   Oalvinistic  sense, 

much  misinterpreted  and  misunder-  which  has  been  so  unjustly  affixed 

stood.     The  following  statement  in  to  it On  these  grounds  we 

his  own  words  will  place  the  fact  in  applied  in  a  private  and  respectful 
its  true  point  of  view  :  'At  the  close  manner  to  Archbishop  Cornwallis, 
of  the  year  1772,  and  the  beginning  requesting  him  to  signify  our  wishes 
of  the  next,  an  attempt  was  made  (which  we  conceived  to  be  the  wishes 
by  myself,  and  a  few  other  clergy-  of  a  very  large  proportion,  both  of 
men,  among  whom  were  Mr.  Fran-  the  clergy  and  laity)  to  the  rest  of 
cisWollaston,  Dr.  Percy,  now  Bishop  the  bishops,  that  everything  might 
of  Dromore,  and  Dr.  Yorke,  now  be  done  which  could  be  prudently 
Bishop  of  Ely,  to  induce  the  bishops  and  safely  done,  to  promote  these 
to  promote  a  review  of  the  Liturgy  important  and  salutary  purposes.' 
and  Articles  ;  in  order  to  amend  in  '  The  answer  given  by  the  Arch- 
both,  but  particularly  in  the  latter,  bishop,  February  11,  1773,  was  in 
those  parts  which  all  reasonable  these  words :  "I  have  consulted 
persons  agreed  stood  in  need  of  severally  my  brethren  the  bishops, 
amendment.  This  plan  was  meant  and  it  is  the  opinion  of  the  Bench  in 
to  strengthen  and  confirm  the  eccle-  general,  that  nothing  can  in  pru- 
siastical  establishment;  to  repel  the  dence  be  done  in  the  matter  which 
attacks  which  were  at  that  time  has  been  submitted  to  our  considera- 
continually  made  upon  it  by  its  tion.'" — Works  of  Bishop  Porteous, 
avowed  enemies ;  to  render  the  1 7th  vol.  i.  p.  38. 


CHAP.    XI. 


Conclusion.  $  1 3 


in  the  rulers  of  the  Church  at  that  time  rejected  it.  And 
this  liberty  still  remains  a  great  advantage  to  the  Church, 
and  a  signal  proof  at  once  of  judgment  and  discretion,  and 
of  a  correct  and  enlarged  theology.  It  would  indeed  have 
been  a  fatal  mistake  to  have  excluded  from  our  pale  an  as 
pect  of  Christian  truth,  which  simply  erred  in  a  pardonable 
obliquity,  such  as  is  incident  to  minds  of  the  highest  order, 
to  the  strongest  intellect,  to  the  deepest  devotion.  Such 
an  exclusion  would  have  shown  also  great  ignorance  of 
antiquity  and  the  history  of  Christian  doctrine  :  for  with 
out  attaching  more  than  undue  importance  to  a  single 
name,  it  will  be  allowed  perhaps  that  what  S.  Augustine 
held  is  at  any  rate  a  tolerable  opinion,  and  no  sufficient 
ground  for  separation  either  from  the  communion  or  the 
ministry  of  the  Church.  He  is,  however,  only  the  first  of 
a  succession  of  authorities  that  from  his  own  age  to  the 
present  have  maintained  and  taught  predestinarianism 
within  the  Church.  Such  a  proposal  with  respect  to  the 
seventeenth  article,  from  the  person  who  made  it,  only 
shows  how  apt  minds  are  to  be  confined  to  the  prevailing 
notions  of  their  day,  and  to  suppose  that  there  is  no  room 
for  any  other  truth  than  what  happens  to  have  been  familiar 
to  themselves.  And  it  should  operate  as  a  warning  against 
similar  attempts,  showing,  as  it  does,  what  great  mistakes 
may  be  made  when  we  trust  too  confidently  one  apparent 
truth ;  forgetting  how  much  it  might  be  modified,  were  we 
in  possession  of  the  whole  system  to  which  it  belongs ; 
and  how  easily  we  may  be  ignorant  and  uninformed  upon 
those  further  points  upon  which  this  modification  would 
follow. 

The  formularies  of  our  own  Church,  following  Catholic 
precedent,  accordingly  allow  predestinarianism;  and  this  is 
the  decision  of  common  sense  and  common  reason  on  this 
subject.  For,  so  long  as  a  man  thinks  nothing  which  is 
inconsistent  with  piety,  what  great  difference  can  it  make, 
provided  his  actions  are  good,  on  what  particular  rationale 
of  causation  he  supposes  them  to  be  done?  whether  he 
thinks  them  done  wholly  by  Divine  grace,  or  partly  by  an 
original  motion  of  his  own  will  coinciding  with  grace? 


314  Conclusion.  CHAP.  XL 

The  latter  is  the  more  large  and  reasonable  view;  but 
whichever  of  the  two  opinions  he  adopts,  if  he  only  does 
his  duty,  that  is  the  great  thing.  The  object  for  which 
this  present  life  is  given  us,  is  not  philosophy  and  reasoning, 
and  the  arrival  at  speculative  truth  respecting  even  our 
own  wills,  and  how  they  are  moved  ;  but  it  is  self-discipline 
and  moral  action,  growth  in  piety  and  virtue.  So  long  as 
this  practical  object  is  attained,  mistakes  of  mere  specula 
tion  may  well  be  passed  over.  Those  who  give  these  mis 
takes  a  practical  direction,  indeed,  and  from  thinking 
erroneously  proceed  to  act  viciously,  are  responsible  for 
such  an  application  of  a  speculative  tenet ;  but  those  who 
do  not  so  apply  it,  are  not  so  responsible.  Numbers  of 
pious  and  earnest  Christians  who  have  laboured  for  the 
welfare  and  salvation  of  their  brethren,  enduring  thank 
fully  fatigue  and  pain,  and  despising  the  riches  and  honours 
of  the  world,  have  thought  that  they  did  all  this  by  an  irre 
sistible  Divine  influence  in  con  sequence  of  which  they  could 
not  act  otherwise  than  they  did.  And  what  if  they  did 
think  so  ?  They  took  a  one-sided  view ;  but  if  we  wait 
till  men  are  perfectly  fair,  clear,  and  large  in  their  judg 
ment  before  we  acknowledge  them  as  brethren,  in  the 
case  of  the  great  majority  of  mankind  we  may  wait  for 
ever. 

Such  is  the  imperfection  even  of  the  human  mind,  that, 
under  Providence,  a  certain  narrowness  of  judgment  often 
works  for  good,  and  seems  to  favour  practical  energy  and 
zeal.  How  universal  is  that  disposition  in  men  of  religious 
ardour,  enthusiasm,  and  activity,  to  over-value  some  one  or 
two  particular  tenets,  which  are  either  true,  or  which  they 
suppose  to  be  true  ;  appearing  to  think  almost  more  about 
them  than  they  do  about  the  whole  of  the  rest  of  their 
religious  creed,  containing  all  the  broad  and  fundamental 
truths  of  the  religion  they  profess  I  How  do  they  cherish 
and  foster  this  tendency  in  their  minds,  as  if  it  were  the 
most  sacred  and  highest  characteristic  of  their  religious 
life !  How  do  they  idolise  these  special  tenets,  as  if  to 
part  with  them  were  to  bid  farewell  altogether  to  piety 
and  religion !  And  doubtless  in  their  particular  case  this 


CHAP.  xi.  Conclusion.  315 

even  might  be  the  result.  For  if  minds  have  accustomed 
themselves  to  cling  with  this  exclusive  force  to  particular 
points,  and  identify  religion  as  a  whole  with  them,  who  can 
tell  the  effect  of  the  revulsion  which  would  take  place, 
could  they  be  brought  to  doubt  the  truth  of  these  ?  For 
men  go  from  one  extreme  to  another,  and  from  reposing 
the  most  absolute  faith  upon  articles  resting  on  small 
evidence,  rush  into  disbelief  of  those  which  rest  upon  the 
strongest.  And  if  so,  who  would  in  all  cases  wish  to  try 
the  experiment  of  a  change  ?  Who  but  a  philosopher  with 
out  knowledge  of  mankind  would,  for  the  chance  of  a  possible 
advantage,  endeavour  in  all  cases  to  disturb  even  a  cherished 
error  of  the  minor  and  pardonable  class  ?  As  if  minor 
errors  were  not  sometimes  even  a  safeguard  against  greater 
ones;  and  as  if  an  obstinate  propensity  of  the  human  mind, 
checked  in  one  direction,  would  not  run  out  in  another ; 
like  a  stream  which,  if  you  dam  it  up  in  one  part,  breaks 
its  bank  elsewhere,  and  perhaps  floods  a  whole  district. 
Nor  is  this  propensity  to  over-estimate  particular  truths 
or  supposed  truths  confined  to  any  one  communion ;  the 
Eoman  Catholic  and  the  Protestant  shows  it  alike ;  most 
sects  and  divisions  of  the  Christian  world  have  their  favourite 
tenets,  which  individuals  identify  with  religion  as  a  whole, 
and  associate  intimately  and  fundamentally  with  their 
whole  Christian  prospects,  as  if  their  spiritual  life  and 
sanctification  were  essentially  bound  up  with  them.  They 
seem  to  see  in  such  special  tenets  the  source  of  all  their 
strength,  their  stay,  encouragement,  and  consolation. 

The  history  of  the  human  mind,  I  say,  shows  this  great 
imperfection  in  it,  that  it  is  so  much  more  able  to  appre 
ciate  smaller  and  particular  truths,  real  or  supposed,  than 
larger  and  fundamental  ones.  There  is  in  the  first  place  an 
advantage  in  this  respect,  belonging  to  the  former,  in  the 
very  circumstance  that  they  are  smaller ;  they  are  more 
easily  grasped,  and  the  whole  heart  embraces  them,  and 
winds  itself  about  them  more  completely.  There  is  in  the 
next  place  the  stimulus  of  rivalry  and  contradiction,  which 
surrounds  a  peculiar  and  distinctive,  and  as  such,  an  op 
posed  tenet,  with  a  halo  of  its  own,  and  invests  it  with  an 


3 1  ^  Conclusion.  CHAP.  xr. 

interest  which  does  not  attach  to  undisputed  truths.     The 
broad  doctrines  of  revelation  are  defective  in  this  appeal 
to  our  interest,  because  they  are  so  broad  ;  and  truths  which 
all  hold  are  thought  little  of  comparatively,  because  all 
hold  them.     What  merit  is  there  in  believing  what  every 
body  else  believes  ?     We  are  thrown  in  the  case  of  such 
truths  upon  the  intrinsic  gravity  and  importance  of  the 
truths  themselves,  to  the  exclusion  of  that  adventitious 
interest  which  accrues  from  the  really  irrelevant  and  im 
pertinent  consideration  of  who  hold  them — that  we  main 
tain  and  accept  them  in  distinction  to  others  who  do  not. 
Men  thus  glory  in  a  privilege  while  they  pass  over  coldly 
and  slightingly  a  common  benefit.     In  the  case   of  the 
distinctive  tenet  they  feel  themselves  champions ;  the  be- 
frienders  of  truth,  and  not  its  disciples  only;  its  patrons, 
rather  than  its  sons.     Stripped  of  this  foreign,  and  thrown 
back  on  its  own  intrinsic  interest,  truth  is  apt  to  be  a  some 
what  cold  and  insipid  thing  to  the  majority  of  men — at 
least  in  their  average  state  of  mind ;  though  sickness  or 
adversity  will  sometimes  reveal  to  them  this  truth,  this 
solid,  this  really  sublime  and  native  interest  belonging  to 
it.     Ordinarily,  they  are  too  apt  to  be  little  interested  in 
it,   unless   supported  by  some  external  aid  of  this  kind. 
There  is  again  another  and  a  better  reason  than  either  of 
those  which  have  been  given  for  the  disproportionate  esti 
mate  of  particular  tenets  ;  viz.  that  they  really  suit,  assist, 
and  support  particular  mental,  as  strong  medicines  do  par 
ticular  bodily,  constitutions.     But  whatever  be  the  reasons 
for  this  disposition,  all  sects  and  communions  more  or  less 
exhibit  it ;  and  men,  and  serious  and  earnest  men,  come 
forward  and  tell  us,  that  they  could  not  conduct  their 
spiritual  progress  without  the  aid  of  one  or  other  special 
tenet,  which   they  assert,   and   really  imagine  to  be,  the 
spring  of  their  energies,  and  the  mainstay  of  their  hopes. 
And  among  the  rest,  the  predestinarian  comes  forward  and 
says  this.     He  says  that  he  could  not,  as  a  spiritual  being, 
go  on  without  this  doctrine ;  that  he  finds  it  essential  to 
him ;  that  without  it  the  universe  would  be  a  chaos,  and 
the  Divine  dispensations  a  delusion ;  that  he  reposes  in  it 


CHAP.  xi.  Conclusion.  317 

as  the  only  true  mode  of  asserting  the  Divine  Love  and 
Power ;  and,  therefore,  his  only  support  in  this  life,  his 
only  security  for  a  better  life  to  come.  He  says  all  this ; 
he  says  it  from  his  heart  ;  he  feels  it ;  he  believes  it.  Then 
what  are  we  to  say  ?  What,  but  that,  however  such  a  result 
may  be  owing  to  an  imperfection  in  his  mind,  this  doctrine 
is  certainly  to  him,  under  this  imperfection,  a  strength  and 
a  consolation ;  and  that  an  error  and  an  obliquity  is  over 
ruled  by  Providence  for  good  ?  ! 

Whether  the  time,  indeed,  will  ever  come  when  men 
in  general  will  see  that  on  this  and  some  other  questions 
truth  is  twofold,  and  is  not  confined  to  either  side  singly — 
that  our  perceptions  are  indistinct  and  contradictory,  and 
therefore,  do  not  justify  any  one  definite  position — remains 
to  be  seen.  Philosophers  have  from  time  to  time  prophe 
sied  a  day  when  a  better  understanding  would  commence 
of  man  with  himself,  and  of  man  with  man.  They  have 
risen  up  from  the  survey  of  the  past  with  the  idea  that  it 
is  impossible  that  mankind  can  go  on  for  ever  repeating 

1  '  As  the  workings  of  the  heart  am  persuaded  there  are)  who  differ 
of  man,  and  of  the  Spirit  of  God,  are  from  me  more  or  less  in  those  points 
in  general  the  same  in  all  who  are  which  are  called  Calvinistic,  appear 
the  subjects  of  grace,  I  hope  most  desirous  that  the  Calvinists  should, 
of  these  hymns,  being  the  fruit  and  for  their  sakes,  studiously  avoid 
expression  of  my  own  experience,  every  expression  which  they  cannot 
will  coincide  with  the  views  of  real  approve.  Yet  few  of  them,  I  be- 
Christians  of  all  denominations.  lieve,  impose  a  like  restraint  upon 
But  I  cannot  expect  that  every  themselves,  but  think  the  import- 
sentiment  I  have  advanced  will  be  ance  of  what  they  deem  to  be  truth 
universally  approved.  However,  I  justifies  them  in  speaking  their  sen- 
am  not  conscious  of  having  written  timents  plainly  and  strongly.  May 
a  single  line  with  an  intention  either  I  not  plead  for  an  equal  liberty? 
to  flatter  or  offend  any  party  or  The  views  I  have  received  of  the 
person  upon  earth.  I  have  simply  doctrines  of  grace  are  essential  to 
declared  my  own  views  and  feelings.  my  peace  :  I  could  not  live  comfort- 
....  I  am  a  friend  of  peace;  and  ably  a  day  or  an  hour  without  them, 
being  deeply  convinced  that  no  one  I  likewise  believe,  yea,  as  far  as  my 
can  profitably  understand  the  great  poor  attainments  warrant  me  to 
truths  and  doctrines  of  the  Gospel  speak,  I  know  them  to  be  friendly 
any  further  than  he  is  taught  by  God,  to  holiness,  and  to  have  a  direct  in- 
I  have  not  a  wish  to  obtrude  my  own  fluence  in  producing  and  mam- 
tenets  npon  others  in  a  way  of  con-  taining  a  Gospel  conversation  ;  and 
troversy  yet  I  do  not  think  myself  therefore  I  must  not  be  ashamed  of 
bound  to  conceal  them.  Many  them.'— Newton's  Preface  to  the 
gracious  persons  (for  many  such  I  Olney  Hymns. 


Conclusion. 


CHAP.  XT. 


the  same  mistakes  ;  that  they  must  one  day  see  the  limits 
of  human  reason,  distinguish  what  they  know  from  what 
they  do  not  know,  and  draw  the  necessary  conclusion,  that 
on  some  questions  they  cannot  insist  on  any  one  absolute 
truth,  and  condemn  each  other  accordingly.  But  the  vision 
does  not  approach  at  present  any  very  clear  fulfilment. 
The  limits  of  human  reason  are  perhaps  better  understood 
in  the  world  now  than  they  ever  were  before  ;  and  such  a 
knowledge  has  evidently  an  effect  upon  controversy,  to  a 
certain  extent  modifying  and  chastening  it.  Those  who 
remind  men  of  their  ignorance  use  an  argument  which, 
however  it  may  fall  short  of  striking  with  its  full  philoso 
phical  strength,  and  producing  its  due  effect,  appeals  to  an 
undeniable  truth,  before  which  all  human  souls  must  bow. 
And  the  most  ardent  minds,  in  the  very  heat  of  contro 
versy,  have  an  indistinct  suspicion  that  a  strong  ground 
has  been  established  in  this  quarter.  On  the  other  hand, 
this  knowledge  of  the  limits  of  human  reason  is  not,  and 
perhaps  never  will  be,  for  reasons  which  I  have  given,  very 
acute  or  accurate  in  the  minds  of  the  mass  ;  while  the 
tendency  to  one-sided  views  and  to  hasty  assumption  is 
strong,  and  is  aided  by  passion  and  self-love,  as  well  as  by 
better  feeling  misapplied.  On  the  whole,  therefore,  while 
improved  philosophy  has  perhaps  entirely  destroyed  some 
great  false  assumptions  which  have  reigned  in  the  world, 
so  that  these  will  never  rise  up  again,  it  cannot  subdue  the 
temper  and  spirit  which  make  such  assumptions.  It  is 
able  occasionally  to  check  and  qualify,  but  it  cannot  be 
expected  that  it  will  ever  habitually  regulate,  theological 
thought  and  controversy.  It  will  from  time  to  time  step 
in  as  a  monitor,  and  take  advantage  of  a  pause  and  quiet 
interval  to  impress  its  lesson  upon  mankind,  to  bring  them 
back  to  reflection  when  they  have  been  carried  too  far,  and 
convert  for  the  time  a  sense  of  error  into  a  more  cautious 
view  of  truth  ;  but  it  will  never  perhaps  do  more  than  this. 
Unable  to  balance  and  settle,  it  will  give  a  useful  oscillation 
to  the  human  mind,  an  alternation  of  enthusiasm  and  judg 
ment,  of  excitement  and  repose. 

In  the  meantime  it  only  remains  that  those  who  differ 


CHAP.  XT. 


Conclusion. 


from  each  other  on  points  which  can  never  be  settled  abso 
lutely,  in  the  present  state  of  our  capacities,  should  re 
member  that  they  may  differ,  not  in  holding  truth  and 
error,  but  only  in  holding  different  sides  of  the  same  truth. 
And  with  this  reflection  I  will  conclude  the  present  trea 
tise.  After  long  consideration  of  the  subject,  I  must  profess 
myself  unable  to  see  on  what  strictly  argumentative  ground 
the  two  great  parties  in  the  English  Church  can,  on  the 
question  which  has  occupied  this  treatise  —  viz.  the  opera 
tion  of  Divine  grace,  and  on  other  questions  connected 
with  it  —  imagine  themselves  to  be  so  fundamentally  op 
posed  to  each  other.  All  differences  of  opinion,  indeed, 
even  those  which  are  obviously  of  a  secondary  and  not  a 
fundamental  kind,  tend  to  create  division  and  separation  ; 
for  all  difference  in  its  degree  is  apt  to  be  a  sign  of  some 
general  difference  of  mental  mould  and  religious  temper, 
and  men  naturally  consort  together  according  to  their 
general  sympathies  and  turn  of  mind  ;  and  for  men  to 
consort  with  some  as  distinct  from  others,  is  in  itself  a  sort 
of  division  in  the  body  ;  a  division,  too,  which,  when  once 
begun,  is  apt  to  deepen.  Such  an  existence  of  preference 
is  suggestive  of  positive  controversy  ;  and  men  once 
brought  together  upon  such  an  understanding,  and  formed 
into  groups  by  special  sympathies,  are  liable  to  become  by 
this  very  position  antagonistic  parties,  schools,  and  sides. 
Yet  the  differences  of  opinion  in  our  Church,  on  the  ques 
tion  of  grace,  and  on  some  further  questions  connected 
with  it,  do  not  appear  to  be  sufficient  to  justify  either 
party  in  supposing  that  it  differs  from  the  other  funda 
mentally,  or  so  as  to  interfere  with  Christian  fellowship. 
If  the  question  of  grace  is  one  which,  depending  on  irre 
concilable  but  equally  true  tendencies  of  thought  in  man, 
cannot  be  settled  absolutely  either  way,  it  seems  to  follow 
that  a  difference  upon  it  should  not  occasion  a  distance  or 
separation.  And  this  remark  will  apply  to  such  further 
and  more  particular  questions  as  are  connected  with  this 
general  question,  and  are  necessarily  affected  by  the  view 
we  take  upon,  and  the  mode  in  which  we  decide  the  general 
question.  Such,  for  example,  is  the  doctrine  of  baptismal 


32O  Conclusion.  CHAP.  xi. 

regeneration.  A  slight  consideration  will  be  enough  to 
show  how  intimately  this  doctrine  is  connected  with  the 
general  doctrine  of  grace ;  and  that  one  who  holds  an  ex 
treme,  and  one  who  holds  a  modified  doctrine  of  grace  in 
general,  cannot  hold  the  doctrine  of  baptismal  regeneration 
in  the  same  sense.  If  a  latitude  of  opinion,  then,  may  be 
allowed  on  the  general  question,  it  seems  to  follow  that  an 
equal  latitude  may  be  allowed  on  this  further  and  more 
particular  one  ;  and  that  if  an  extreme  predestinarian,  and 
a  maintainer  of  freewill  can  maintain  and  teach  their  re 
spective  doctrines  within  the  same  communion,  they  need 
not  exclude  each  other  when  they  come  to  give  to  their 
respective  doctrines  their  necessary  and  legitimate  appli 
cation  in  a  particular  case.  I  cannot,  therefore,  but  think, 
that  further  reflection  will,  on  this  and  other  questions, 
modify  the  opposition  of  the  two  parties  in  our  Church  to 
each  other,  and  show  that  their  disagreement  is  not  so  great 
as  in  the  heat  of  controversy  they  supposed  it  to  be.  Dif 
ferences  of  opinion  there  will  always  be  in  every  religious 
communion,  so  long  as  the  human  mind  is  as  variously 
constituted  as  it  is,  and  so  long  as  proper  liberty  is  allowed 
it  to  express  and  unfold  this  variety.  But  it  depends  on 
the  discretion  and  temper  of  religious  men  to  what  extent 
they  will  allow  these  differences  to  carry  them  ;  whether 
they  will  retain  them  upon  a  common  basis  of  Christian 
communion  and  fellowship,  or  raise  them  into  an  occasion 
of  separation  and  mutual  exclusion. 


NOTES. 


NOTE  I.  p.  4. 

TOPLADT  says,  '  If  God  had  not  willed  tlie  fall,  He  could 
and  no  doubt  would  have  prevented  it ;  but  He  did  not. 
prevent  it,  ergo  He  willed  it;  and  if  He  willed  it,  He 
certainly  decreed  it.' — Vol.  v.  p.  242.  This  is  a  philoso 
phical  argument  proceeding  upon  the  attribute  of  the 
Divine  Power;  as  is  the  following  appeal  to  our  intellectual 
consistency  as  believers  in  a  (rod  :  '  He  alone  is  entitled 
to  the  name  of  true  (rod  who  governs  all  things,  and 
without  whose  will  (either  efficient  or  permissive)  nothing 
is  or  can  be  done.  And  such  is  the  God  of  the  Scriptures, 
against  whose  will  not  a  sparrow  can  die,  nor  a  hair  fall 
from  our  heads.  Now,  what  is  predestination  but  the 
determining  will  of  God?  I  defy  the  subtlest  Semi- 
Pelagian  in  the  world  to  form  or  convey  a  just  and  worthy 
notion  of  the  Supreme  Being  without  admitting  Him  to 
be  the  Great  Cause  of  all  causes  ;  also  Himself  dependent 
on  none  ;  who  willed  from  eternity  how  He  should  act  in 
time,  and  settled  a  regular,  determinate  scheme  of  what 
He  would  do  and  permit  to  be  done,  from  the  beginning 
to  the  consummation  of  the  world.  A  contrary  view  of 
the  Deity  is  as  inconsistent  with  reason  itself,  and  with 
the  very  religion  of  nature,  as  it  is  with  the  decisions  of 

revelation Without   predestination  to  plan,  and 

without  Providence  to  put  that  plan  in  execution,  what 
becomes  of  God's  omnipotence  ?  It  vanishes  into  air ;  it 
becomes  a  mere  nonentity.  For  what  sort  of  Omnipotence 
is  that  which  is  baffled  or  defeated  by  the  very  creatures 
it  has  m&de.'-^Topladyy  vol.  v.  p.  293. 

Y 


Note  II. 


NOTE  II.  p.  7. 

J  ACKSON  quotes  a  predestinarian  statement,  '  That  Grod's 
irresistible  decree  for  the  absolute  election  of  some,  and 
the  absolute  reprobation  of  others,  is  immediately  termi 
nated  to  the  individual  natures,  substances,  or  entities  of 
men,  without  any  logical  respect  or  reference  to  their 
qualifications  ; '  a  position  to  which  lie  attaches  the  fol 
lowing  consequences:  'This  principle  being  once  granted,, 
what  breach  of  Grod's  moral  law  is  there  whereon  men 
will  not  boldly  adventure,  either  through  desperation  or 
presumption,  either  openly  or  secretly  ?  For  seeing  God's 
will,  which  in  their  divinity  is  the  only  cause  why  the  one 
sort  are  destinated  to  death,  the  other  to  life,  is  most 
immutable  and  most  irresistible, — and  seeing  the  indi 
vidual  entities  or  natures  of  men,  unto  which  this  irresis 
tible  decree  is  respectively  terminated,  are  immutable, — 
let  the  one  sort  do  what  they  can,  pray  for  themselves, 
and  beseech  others  to  pray  for  them,  they  shall  be  damned 
because  their  entities  or  individual  substances  are  unalter 
able  :  let  the  other  sort  live  as  they  list,  they  shall  be 
saved,  because  no  corruption  of  manners,  no  change  of 
morality  finds  any  mutability  or  change  in  their  individual 
natures  or  entities,  unto  which  Grod's  immutable  decree  is 
immediately  terminated.  Whatsoever  becomes  of  good 
life  or  good  manners,  so  the  individual  nature  or  entity 
fail  not,  or  be  not  annihilated,  salvation  is  tied  unto  it  by 
a  necessity  more  indissoluble  than  any  chains  of  adamant/ 
-Vol.  ix.  p.  370. 

This  is  perhaps  a  misinterpretation  of  the  predestinarian 
statement  quoted.  The  Divine  decree,  it  is  true,  is,  ac 
cording  to  that  statement,  '  terminated  to  the  entities  of 
men,'  and  has  '  no  respect  to  their  qualifications,'  as  the 
cause  or  reason  of  such  decree;  but  it  may  still  have 
respect  to  such  qualifications  as  the  effects  of  such  decree. 
But,  whatever  may  be  said  of  this  particular  statement, 
such  an  interpretation  of  it,  if  meant  for  a  representation 
of  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  is  very  incorrect. 


Note  III.  323 

NOTE  III.  p.  10. 

AQUINAS  argues  for  the  righteousness  of  Adam  before  the 
fall  as  supernatural,  or  the  effect  of  grace,  on  this  ground : 
'  Manifestum  est  quod  ilia  subjectio  'corporis  ad  animam, 
et  inferiorum  virium  ad  rationem,  non  erat  naturalis  ; 
alioquin  post  peccatum  mansisset,  cum  etiam  in  doemoni- 
bus  data  naturalia  post  peccatum  permanserint.' — Sum. 
Theol.  lma  Q.  95.  Art.  1. 

This  necessity  of  grace,  however,  before  the  fall  is 
explained  by  Aquinas  with  various  distinctions,  the  sub 
stance  of  which  is,  that  grace  is  wanted  for  supernatural 
virtue  only  by  man  in  his  upright  state,  but  for  natural 
as  well  in  his  corrupt ;  while  the  assistance  of  God  as 
Prime  Mover,  which  he  distinguishes  from  grace,  is  neces 
sary  for  all  acts  in  both  states.  '  Homo  in  statu  nature 
integrae  potest  operari  virtute  suae  naturae  bonum  quod  est 
sibi  connaturale  absque  superadditione  gratuiti  doni,  licet 
nonabsqueauxilio  Dei  moventis.'— lma  2dat'  Q.  109.  Art.  3. 

4  Secundum  utrumque  statum  (corrupt-urn  etintegrum) 
natura  humana  indiget  Divino  auxilio  ad  faciendum  vel 
volendum  quodcunque  bonum,  sicut  primo  movente.  Sed 
in  statu  naturae  integrae  poterat  homo  per  sua  naturalia 
velle  et  operari  bonum  suae  naturae  proportionatum,  quale 
est  bonum  virtutis  acquisitae ;  non  autem  bonum  super- 
excedens,  quale  est  bonum  virtutis  infusae.  Sed  in  statu 
naturae  corruptse  etiam  deficit  homo  ab  hoc  quod  secundum 
suam  naturam  potest,  ut  non  possit  totum  hujusmodi 
bonum  implere  per  sua  naturalia.  Quia  tamen  natura 
humana  per  peccatum  non  est  totaliter  corruptum,  potest 
quidem  etiam  in  statu  naturae  corrupts  per  virtutem  suae 
naturae  aliquod  bonum  particulare  agere,  sicut  aedificare 
domos,'  &c.  . 

6  Virtute  gratuita  superaddita  virtuti  naturae  indige 
homo  in  statu  nature  integrae  quantum  ad  unum,  scilicet 
ad  operandum  et  volendum  bonum  supernaturale ;  sed  m 
statu  naturae  corruptae  quantum  ad  duo  scil.  ut  sanetur, et 
ulterius  ut  bonum  supernaturale  virtutis  operetur.- 

2dae  Q.  109.  Art.  2. 

T  2 


324  Note  IV. 


NOTE  IV.  p.  21. 

LOCKE'S  theory  that  facts,  of  sense  or  reflexion,  are  the 
sole  source  of  our  ideas,  places  him  in  a  difficulty  with 
respect  to  this  indistinct  class  of  ideas.  He  is  committed 
to  the  necessity  of  deriving  them  from  this  source,  and 
tries  in  a  roundabout  way  to  extract  them  from  it.  '  They 
are  ultimately  grounded  on  and  derived  from  ideas  which 
come  in  by  sensation  or  reflexion,  and  so  may  be  said  to 
come  in  by  sensation  or  reflexion.' — First  Letter  to  Bishop 
of  Worcester.  But  though  he  is  in  a  difficulty  as  to  their 
origin,  and  cannot  combine  them  with  his  theory,  he 
acknowledges  as  a  fact  this  class  of  indistinct  ideas.  Thus 
the  idea  of  substance  '  is  the  obscure  and  indistinct  vague 
idea  of  something  which  has  the  relation  of  support  or 
substratum  to  modes  or  accidents.' — Ibid.  'The  idea 
of  substance  is  but  a  supposed  I  know  not  what  to  sup 
port  those  ideas  we  call  accidents.  We  talk  like  chil 
dren  who,  being  questioned  what  such  a  thing  is  which 
they  know  not,  readily  give  this  satisfactory  answer,  that 
it  is  something.' — Essay,  b.  ii.  c.  23.  '  The  being  of 
substance  would  not  be  at  all  shaken  by  my  saying  we  had 
but  an  obscure  imperfect  idea  of  it ;  or  indeed  if  I  should 
say  we  had  no  idea  of  substance  at  all.  For  a  great  many 
things  may  be,  and  are  granted  to  have  being,  and  to  be 
in  nature,  of  which  we  have  no  ideas.  For  example,  it 
cannot  be  doubted  but  there  are  distinct  species  of 
separate  spirits  of  which  yet  we  have  no  distinct  ideas  at 
all.'  And  as  he  acknowledges  an  idea  of  substance  which 
is  yet  no  true  or  adequate  idea,  so  he  does  of  infinity. 
'  The  addition  of  finite  things  suggests  the  idea  of  infinite 
by  a  power  we  find  of  still  increasing  the  same.  But  in 
endeavouring  to  make  it  infinite,  it  being  always  enlarging, 
always  advancing,  the  idea  is  still  imperfect  and  incom 
plete.' — Essay )  b.  ii.  c.  17. 

Though  Stillingfleet  then  presses  him  hard  upon  the 
origin  of  such  ideas,  it  is  evident  that  with  respect  to  the 
nature  of  the  ideas  themselves  Locke  has  greatly  the 


Note  IV.  325 


advantage  in  the  argument ;  that  his  opponent  claims  a 
distinctness  for  them  which  mental  analysis  rejects,  and 
in  his  alarm,  as  if  the  foundations  of  truth  were  shaken 
when  these  great  ideas  were  discovered  to  be  incomplete 
and  obscure,  shows  a  radical  misapprehension  as  to  the 
nature  of  the  fundamental  truths,  on  which  much  of 
philosophy  and  the  whole  of  religion  rests.  No  error  can 
be  greater  than  that  of  supposing  that,  when  ideas  are 
obscure,  they  are  not  rational  ones,  and  then  to  add,  as 
Stillingfleet  does,  'if  we  cannot  come  at  the  rational  idea' 
of  a  thing,  '  we  can  have  no  principle  of  certainty  to  go 
upon.'  Religion  rests  upon  a  set  of  truths  which  exactly 
miss  the  condition  of  rational  truth  here  laid  down.  To 
disprove  this  condition,  then,  to  lay  down  the  consistency 
of  a  rational  character  with  an  obscure  and  indistinct  one 
in  ideas,  is  not  to  overthrow  religion,  but  support  it  on 
the  most  essential  head.  So  surely  do  we  find  that  no 
discoveries  in  philosophy,  metaphysical  or  natural,  really 
turns  out  to  the  injury  of  the  faith. 

Hume,  as  Locke,  acknowledges  virtually  this  class  of 
indistinct  ideas,  though  not  definitely  and  as  a  class. 
Thus,  while  showing  with  such  extreme  acuteness  that  we 
have  no  idea  of  a  cause,  he  allows  the  thing ;  asserting 
strongly  the  necessity  of  attributing  the  existence  of  the 
world  to  a  cause.  'When  our  contemplation  is  so  far 
enlarged  as  to  contemplate  the  first  rise  of  this  visible 
system,  we  must  adopt  with  the  strongest  conviction  the 
idea  of  some  intelligent  cause.' — Natural  History  of 
Religion,  sect.  xv.  But  we  could  not  lay  it  down  that  a 
cause  was  necessary  unless  we  had  some  idea  of  one. 
What  is  this  then  but  to  say,  that  we  have  some  idea,  but 
not  a  true  one,  of  a  cause, — an  obscure,  incipient  idea. 
The  very  acuteness  with  which  the  philosopher  has  proved 
that  we  have  '  no  idea '  of  a  cause  thus  turns  to  the  estab 
lishment  of  this  kind  of  truth  that  I  am  speaking  of, 
obscure,  incipient,  or  mysterious  truth.  Hume  acknow 
ledges  too  the  existence  of  <a  vulgar,  inaccurate  idea  of 
power.'— Enquiry  concerning  the  Human  Understand 
ing,  sect.  vii.  But  what  is  this  vulgar,  inaccurate  idea, 


326  Note  V. 


but  an  idea  which  all  mankind  have,  an  instinct,  or  indis 
tinct  perception  ? 

NOTE  V.  p.  25. 

MR.  MILL'S  argument  in  favour  of  the  doctrine  of  necessity 
consists  of  two  parts :  one  the  proof  of  the  doctrine ;  the 
other  an  answer  to  an  objection  to  it. 

His  proof  of  the  doctrine  is  an  inductive  one.  What 
do  we  mean  by  necessity,  he  asks,  but  causation ;  that,  the 
antecedents  supposed,  a  certain  consequent  will  follow  ? 
Now,  we  observe,  he  says,  this  law  of  causation  in  every 
other  department :  we  must  therefore  suppose  it  to  exist 
in  the  department  of  the  human  will.  For  the  proof  of 
the  existence  of  this  law  in  other  departments  he  refers 
us  to  facts,  and  simply  appeals  to  observation.  '  Between 
the  phenomena  which  exist  at  any  instant,  and  the 
phenomena  which  exist  at  the  succeeding  instant,  there  is 
an  invariable  order  of  succession  ....  To  certain  facts 
certain  facts  always  do,  and,  as  we  believe,  will  continue 
to,  succeed.  The  invariable  antecedent  is  termed  the 
cause;  the  invariable  consequent  the  effect.  And  the 
universality  of  the  law  consists  in  this,  that  every  conse 
quent  is  connected  in  this  manner  with  some  particular 
antecedent  or  set  of  antecedents.  Let  the  fact  be  what 
it  may,  if  it  has  begun  to  exist  it  was  preceded  by  some 
fact  or  facts  with  which  it  is  invariably  connected.  For 
every  event  there  exists  some  combination  of  object  or 
events,  some  given  concurrence  of  circumstances,  positive 
and  negative,  the  occurrence  of  which  is  always  followed 
by  the  phenomenon.  We  may  not  have  found  out  what 
this  concurrence  of  circumstances  may  be ;  but  we  never 
doubt  that  there  is  such  a  one,  and  that  it  never  occurs 
without  having  the  phenomenon  in  question  as  its  effect 
or  consequence.  On  the  universality  of  this  truth  depends 
the  possibility  of  reducing  the  inductive  process  to  rules.' 
—Vol.  i.  p.  338. 

Here  is  an  appeal  to  our  observation  for  a  proof  of  the 
law  of  causation.     Mr.  Mill  does  not  go  to  any  a  priori 


Note  V.  327 


ground  on  this  question,  or  avail  himself  of  the  maxim 
that  every  event  must  have  a  cause.  He  does  not  appeal 
to  any  instinct  of  reason  antecedently  demanding  a  cause 
for  every  event ;  nor  does  he  attach  to  the  term  cause  any 
sense  of  necessary  and  inherent  efficiency  and  productive 
ness  in  relation  to  its  effect  — '  any  such  mysterious  com 
pulsion  now  supposed,  by  the  best  philosophical  authorities, 
to  be  exercised  by  the  cause  over  its  effect.' — Vol.  ii.  p. 
407.  By  cause  and  effect  he  simply  means  antecedent 
and  consequent ;  and  he  appeals  to  our  simple  observation 
for  the  proof  of  the  existence  of  this  order  and  succession 
in  things  around  us. 

Now,  it  would  be  obviously  begging-  the  question  to 
assert  that  we  observe  this  uniform  order  and  succession  in 
the  events  in  which  the  human  will  takes  part ;  this  would 
be  asserting  to  begin  with  what  has  to  be  proved — viz. 
that  this  law  of  causation  exists  in  the  department  of  the 
human  will;  besides,  that  it  would  be  asserting  our  observa 
tion  of  something  which  we  evidently  do  not  observe.  For 
whatever  uniformity  we  may  observe  in  the  conduct  of 
mankind  as  a  mass,  however  like  one  generation  of  men 
may  be  to  another,  and  a  preceding  age  of  the  world  to  a 
succeeding  one,  in  general  moral  features  and  the  prin 
ciples  on  which  the  race  is  governed  and  acts,  we  evidently 
do  not  observe  this  uniformity  in  the  case  of  individuals. 
And  it  is  the  case  of  the  individual  which  tries  the  theory 
of  necessity  or  causation  as  applying  to  the  human  will. 
Upon  the  ordinary  doctrine  of  chances  there  will  be  much 
the  same  amount  of  virtue  and  vice  in  one  generation  that 
there  is  in  others,  and  the  same  general  exhibition  of 
character  will  take  place.  The  doctrine  of  necessity  re 
quires  that  the  individual  will  act  in  the  same  way  under 
the  same  circumstances.  And  this  latter  fact  we  certainly 
do  not  observe.  Mr.  Mill,  then,  in  appealing  to  our  ob 
servation  for  a  proof  of  the  law  of  causation,  must  mean 
to  exclude  from  the  events  in  which  this  is  observed  those 
in  which  the  human  will  takes  part ;  i.e.  to  appeal  to  our 
observation  of  material  nature  only.  And  therefore  his 
argument,  when  he  comes  to  assert  this  law  as  prevailing 


328  Note  V. 


in  the  department  of  will,  is  one  of  induction, — the  com 
mon  argument  from  the  known  to  the  unknown.  We 
know,  he  says,  that  this  is  the  law  upon  which  one  large 
class  of  events  takes  place ;  we  must  therefore  suppose  it  to 
be  the  law  upon  which  another  class  of  events,  with  re 
spect  to  which  we  have  not  this  knowledge,  takes  place ; 
we  observe  this  law  in  the  physical  world,  we  must  there 
fore  presume  that  it  prevails  in  the  moral  as  well. 

Of  such  an  argument  as  this,  then,  it  will,  perhaps,  be 
enough  to  remark,  that  it  appears  to  be  nothing  more  than 
a  presumption  at  the  best.  One  class  of  events  takes  place 
according  to  a  certain  law ;  therefore  another  does.  Is 
this  a  proof  to  satisfy  any  reasonable  mind  ?  Such  an  in 
duction  is,  on  the  first  showing,  in  the  highest  degree  weak 
and  conjectural.  But  when  we  compare  matter  and  will, 
and  distinguish  the  entirely  different  impressions  which  we 
have  with  respect  to  our  actions,  and  events  in  nature,  the 
induction  breaks  down  still  more.  Why  should  we  suppose 
that  events  so  totally  different  in  all  their  characteristics, 
as  those  which  take  place  in  matter  and  will,  should  take 
place  on  the  same  law  ;  and  presume  that,  because  causa 
tion  or  necessity  rules  in  the  physical  world,  it  therefore 
does  in  the  moral  ? 

But  while  I  interpret  Mr.  Mill's  argument  as  an  induc 
tive  one — which  indeed  appears  to  be  the  only  kind  of 
argument  which  observation  enables  him  to  use, — I  must 
at  the  same  time  allow  that  Mr.  Mill  in  other  passages 
does  not  appear  altogether  to  interpret  his  own  argument 
in  this  way ;  and  that  he  seems  to  imagine  that  he  has 
more  than  an  inductive,  i.e.  presumptive,  argument — viz. 
one  of  actual  consciousness  and  experience  in  his  favour, 
on  this  question.  '  Correctly  conceived/  he  says,  '  the 
doctrine  called  Philosophical  Necessity  is  simply  this :  that, 
given  the  motives  which  are  present  to  an  individual  mind, 
and  given  likewise  the  character  and  disposition  of  the 
individual,  the  manner  in  which  he  will  act  may  be  un 
erringly  inferred  ;  that  if  we  know  the  person  thoroughly, 
and  know  all  the  inducements  which  are  acting  upon  him, 
we  could  foretell  his  conduct  with  as  much  certainty  as  we 


Note  V.  329 


can  predict  any  physical  event.  This  proposition  I  take 
to  be  a  mere  interpretation  of  universal  experience,  a 
statement  in  words  of  ivhat  every  one  is  internally  con 
vinced  of.  No  one  who  believed  that  he  knew  thoroughly 
the  circumstances  of  any  case,  and  the  characters  of  the 
different  persons  concerned,  would  hesitate  to  foretell  how 
all  of  them  would  act.  Whatever  degree  of  doubt  he  may 
feel  arises  from  the  uncertainty  whether  he  really  knows 
the  circumstances  or  the  character  of  some  one  or  other  of 
the  persons  with  the  degreee  of  accuracy  required  ;  but  by 
no  means  from  thinking,  that  if  he  did  know  these  things, 
there  would  be  any  uncertainty  what  the  conduct  would  be. 
Nor  does  this  full  assurance  conflict  in  the  smallest  degree 
with  what  is  called  our  feeling  of  freedom.' — Vol.  ii.  p.  40(1. 
I  quote  this  passage  not  for  the  statement  it  contains 
of  the  doctrine  of  necessity  so  much  as  to  call  attention  to 
the  ground  of  that  statement, — the  nature  of  the  argument 
or  evidence  on  which  the  writer  appears  to  suppose  that 
doctrine  of  necessity  rests.  '  This  proposition,'  he  says,  '  1 
take  to  be  a  mere  interpretation  of  universal  experience,  a 
statement  in  words  of  what  every  one  is  internally  con 
vinced  of; ''  the  proposition,  viz.  that  the  inducements 
internal  and  external  to  action  supposed,  the  action  of  an 
individual  may  be  predicted  with  as  much  certainty  as  we 
can  predict  any  physical  event.  Mr.  Mill  then  appeals  to 
actual  experience,  and  to  internal  conviction  or  conscious 
ness,  as  the  evidence  of  the  doctrine  of  necessity.  Now,  if 
Mr.  Mill  were  content  to  mean  by  this  experience  and  in 
ternal  conviction  of  necessity  to  which  he  appeals,  such  an 
indistinct  or  half-perception  of  a  truth  in  this  direction  as 
is  consistent  with  the  same  kind  of  perception  of  the  con 
trary  truth  of  our  originality  as  agents,  I  would  agree  with 
him  ;  and  I  have  in  this  chapter  accepted  the  necessitarian 
maxim,  that  every  event  must  have  a  cause,  as  supplying 
one  side  of  the  truth  on  this  question.  But  it  is  evident 
that  Mr.  Mill  means  something  more  than  this  ;  his  argu 
ment,  as  an  advocate  of  necessity  against  originality, 
requires  a  full  and  distinct  experience  and  conviction  on 
the  side  of  necessity,  not  a  divided  one.  Moreover,  the 


330  Note  V. 


ground  on  which  he  has  placed  the  whole  doctrine  of 
necessity  or  causation  is  a  ground  of  observation — that  we 
see  things,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  taking  placje  in  a  certain 
order  and  succession.  When  he  appeals,  then,  to  an  in 
ternal  experience  and  conviction  on  the  side  of  necessity, 
his  argument  requires  him  to  appeal  to  such  a  full  internal 
conviction  as  is  grounded  on  observation.  But  can  Mr. 
Mill  really  mean  to  assert  that  we  observe  a  law  of  causa 
tion  in  operation  in  our  actions,  as  we  do  in  the  events  of 
the  physical  world  ?  Such  an  assertion  would  be  plainly 
untrue,  and  he  himself  would  be  the  first  to  disown  it ;  for 
he  explains  how  it  is  that  we  cannot  observe  such  a  law  in 
the  case  of  human  actions,  as  we  do  in  nature :  viz.  that 
we  have  not  the  full  antecedents  before  us  in  the  former 
case  as  we  have  in  the  latter ;  that  we  do  not  know  all  the 
inducements,  internal  and  external,  operating  in  a  man, 
and,  therefore,  cannot  predict  with  accuracy  what  his 
action  will  be.  But  then  what  becomes  of  that  experience 
and  internal  conviction  to  which  he  appeals  on  this  ques 
tion  ?  If  we  are  not  able  to  make  the  observation  that  we 
act  by  a  law  of  causation,  how  can  we  have  the  experience 
and  the  internal  conviction  that  we  do  ?  What  sort  of 
conviction,  on  his  own  showing,  must  that  be,  which  has 
positively  no  observation  to  rest  upon  ? 

The  state  of  the  case,  then,  appears  to  be  this :  Mr. 
Mill  begins  with  an  inductive  or  presumptive  argument  on 
this  question,  which,  as  he  proceeds  and  advances  in  his 
explanation  of  it,  becomes  insensibly  from  an  inductive 
argument;  an  appeal  to  4  internal  conviction,'  or  conscious 
ness.  And  instead  of  saying,  the  law  of  causation  exists 
in  the  case  of  physical  events,  therefore  we  may  presume 
it  does  in  the  case  of  moral  ones  or  actions — he  says  at 
once  we  see,  we  know,  we  are  internally  convinced,  we  have 
actual  experience,  that  our  actions  take  place  upon  this 
law. 

Having  established,  however,  whether  by  induction  or 
experience  or  internal  conviction,  necessity  or  the  law  of 
causation,  as  the  law  upon  which  the  acts  of  the  human 
will  proceed,  Mr.  Mill  has  to  meet  an  objection  to  such  a 


Note  V. 


position  which  naturally  and  immediately  arises  from  our 
consciousness  of  freedom  as  agents.  '  To  the  universality 
which  mankind  are  agreed  in  ascribing  to  the  law  of 
causation  there  is  one  claim  of  exception,  one  disputed 
case,  that  of  the  human  will ;  the  determinations  of  whicli 
a  large  class  of  metaphysicians  are  not  willing  to  regard  as 
following  the  causes  called  motives,  according  to  as  strict 
laws  as  those  which  they  suppose  to  exist  in  the  world  of 
mere  matter.  This  controverted  point  will  undergo  a 
special  examination  when  we  come  to  treat  particularly  of 
the  logic  of  the  moral  sciences.  In  the  meantime  I  may 
remark  that  metaphysicians,  who,  it  must  be  observed, 
ground  the  main  part  of  their  objection  on  the  supposed 
repugnance  of  the  doctrine  in  question  to  our  conscious 
ness,  seem  to  me  to  mistake  the  fact  which  consciousness 
testifies  against.  What  is  really  in  contradiction  to  con 
sciousness,  they  would,  I  think,  on  strict  self-examination, 
find  to  be  the  application  to  human  actions  and  volitions 
of  the  ideas  involved  in  the  common  use  of  the  term 
necessity,  which  I  agree  with  them  in  objecting  to.  But 
if  they  would  consider  that  by  saying  that  a  person's 
actions  necessarily  follow  from  his  character,  all  that  is 
really  meant  (for  no  more  is  meant  in  any  case  whatever 
of  causation)  is  that  he  invariably  does  act  in  conformity 
to  his  character,  and  that  any  one  who  thoroughly  knew 
his  character  could  certainly  predict  how  he  would  act  in 
any  supposable  case,  they  probably  would  not  find  this 
doctrine  either  contrary  to  their  experience  or  revolting  to 
their  feelings.'— Vol.  i.  p.  358. 

I  will  stop,  in  the  first  place,  to  ask,  what  is  meant  by 
the  word  'character,'  in  the  assertion  that  |  a^  person's 
actions  necessarily  follow  from  his  "  character  "  ?'  If  the 
term  character  here  includes  a  man's  whole  conduct  and 
action,  this  assertion  amounts  to  nothing.  If  the  term 
means  simply  a  certain  general  disposition  and  bias  of 
mind,  then  the  assertion  is  without  proof;  the  assertion, 
I  mean,  that  from  this  general  disposition  a  particular 
act  will  follow.  The  main  object  of  this  passage,  how- 
,ever,  is  to  meet  the  objection  to  the  doctrine  of  necessity 


33  2  Note  V. 


proceeding  from  our  consciousness  of  freedom  as  agents ; 
an  objection  which  Mr.  Mill  meets  with  a  distinction  be 
tween  necessity  in  the  sense  of  causation,  and  necessity  in 
the  '  common  use  of  the  term,'  viz.  as  coaction  or  force ; 
necessity  in  the  former  sense  not  being  opposed  to  our  con 
sciousness.  The  same  answer  is  contained  in  the  follow 
ing  passage  :  '  The  metaphysical  theory  of  freewill  as  held 
by  philosophers  (for  the  practical  feeling  of  it,  common  in 
a  greater  or  less  degree  to  all  mankind,  is  in  no  way  in 
consistent  with  the  contrary  theory)  was  invented  because 
the  supposed  alternative  of  admitting  human  actions  to  be 
necessary  was  deemed  inconsistent  with  every  one's  instinc 
tive  consciousness,  as  well  as  humiliating  to  the  pride  and 
degrading  to  the  moral  nature  of  man.  Nor  do  I  deny 
that  the  doctrine,  as  sometimes  held,  is  open  to  these  im 
putations  ;  for  the  misapprehension  in  which  I  shall  be 
able  to  show  that  they  originate,  unfortunately  is  not  con 
fined  to  the  opponents  of  the  doctrine,  but  participated  in 
by  many,  perhaps  we  might  say  by  most,  of  its  sup 
porters.' — Vol.  ii.  p.  405. 

Now,  it  must  be  admitted  that  the  doctrine  of  neces 
sity  is  not  opposed  to  any  express  and  distinct  conscious 
ness  on  our  part,  for  all  that  we  are  distinctly  anxious  of 
is  our  willing  itself ;  we  have  no  positive  apprehension  or 
perception  of  anything  beyond  that  fact,  i.e.  of  the  source 
of  such  willing,  whether  this  is  in  ourselves,  or  beyond  and 
outside  of  us.  But  though  we  have  no  distinct  apprehen 
sion  of  our  own  originality  as  agents,  is  there  not  an  in 
stinctive  perception  in  that  direction  ?  Does  not  the 
whole  manner  in  which  we  find  ourselves,  willing  and 
choosing,  debating  between  conflicting  lines  of  action,  and 
then  deciding  on  one  or  other  of  them,  lead  us  towards  an 
idea  of  our  own  originality  as  agents,  and  produce  that 
impression  upon  us  ?  Would  not  any  person,  holding  to 
his  natural  impression  on  this  head,  be  disappointed  by 
any  explanation  of  these  characteristics  of  human  action, 
which  accounted  for  them  on  any  rationale  short  of 
originality  ?  Would  he  not  feel  that  there  was  something 
passed  over,  not  duly  acknowledged,  and  recognised,  in 


Note  V.  333 


any  rationale  which  stopped  short  of  this  ?  You  might 
explain  to  him  that  his  will  being  caused  from  without 
did  not  imply  any  force  or  coaction,  but  that  he  might 
have  all  the  sensations  of  voluntary  agency  while  lie  was 
still  really  acting  from  causes  ultimately  beyond  his  own 
control ;  but  such  an  explanation  would  not  satisfy  him. 
The  feeling  he  has  that  he  can  decide  either  way  in  the 
case  of  any  proposed  action,  and  the  regret  or  pleasure 
that  he  feels  afterwards,  according  to  the  use  which  he  has 
made  of  this  apparent  power,  will  make  him  think  himself 
an  original  agent,  and  he  will  be  dissatisfied  with  any 
rationale  of  his  action  which  stops  short  of  this. 

Mr.  Mill  is  indeed  sufficiently  aware  of  the  strength 
of  this  natural  conviction  of  originality  in  the  human 
mind,  to  be  induced  to  meet  and  satisfy  its  demands  as 
far  as  he  can  in  consistency  with  his  theory ;  but  he  can 
not,  because  his  theory  prevents  him,  really  satisfy  them. 
He  admits,  however,  for  the  purpose  of  satisfying  this 
claim,  that  a  man  can  in  a  certain  sense  form  his  own 
character,  and  is  an  agent  acting  upon  himself,  and  he 
draws  a  distinction  on  this  head  between  the  necessarian 
and  the  fatalist ;  the  former  of  whom,  according  to  him, 
allows,  in  keeping  with  true  philosophy,  this  agency  upon 
self,  while  the  latter,  carried  away  by  the  fallacy  that  the 
certainty  of  the  end  supersedes  the  necessity  of  the  means 
or  subordinate  agencies,  denies  it.  "  A  fatalist  believes, 
or  half  believes  (for  nobody  is  a  consistent  fatalist),  not 
only  that  whatever  is  about  to  happen  will  be  an  infallible 
result  of  the  causes  which  produce  it  (which  is  the  true 
necessarian  doctrine),  but,  moreover,  that  there  is  no  use 
struggling  against  it;  that  it  will  happen  however  we 
may  strive  to  prevent  it.  Now,  a  necessarian  believing 
that  our  actions  follow  from  our  characters,  and  that  our 
characters  follow  from  our  organisation,  our  education, 
and  our  circumstances,  is  apt  to  be,  with  more  or  less  of 
consciousness  on  his  part,  a  fatalist  as  to  his  actions,  and 
to  believe  that  his  nature  is  such,  or  that  his  education 
and  circumstances  have  so  moulded  his  character,  that 
nothing  can  now  prevent  him  from  feeling  and  acting 


334  Note  V. 


in  a  particular  way,  or  at  least  that  no  effort  of  his  own 
can  hinder  it.  In  the  words  of  the  sect  (Owenite)  which 
in  our  own  day  has  most  perniciously  inculcated  and  most 
perversely  misunderstood  this  great  doctrine,  his  character 
is  formed  for  him,  and  not  by  him  ;  therefore  his  wishing 
that  it  had  been  formed  differently  is  of  no  use,  he  has  no 
power  to  alter  it.  But  this  is  a  grand  error.  He  has  to 
a  certain  extent  a  power  to  alter  Ids  character.  Its 
being  in  the  ultimate  resort  formed  for  him  is  not  in 
consistent  with  its  being  in  part  formed  by  him  as  one 
of  the  intermediate  agents.  His  character  is  formed  by 
his  circumstances  (including  among  these  his  particular 
organisation) ;  but  his  own  desire  to  mould  it  in  a  par 
ticular  way  is  one  of  those  circumstances,  and  by  no  means 
one  of  the  least  influential.  We  cannot,  indeed,  directly 
will  to  be  different  from  what  we  are ;  but  neither  did 
those  who  are  supposed  to  have  formed  our  characters 
directly  will  that  we  should  be  what  we  are.  .  .  .  We  are 
exactly  as  capable  of  making  our  own  character,  if  we 
willy  as  others  are  of  making  it  for  us.' — Vol.  ii.  p.  410. 

Here  is  an  attempt,  then,  to  represent  the  necessarian 
system  in  such  an  aspect  as  to  reconcile  it  with  all  those 
sensations  of  power  over  ourselves  and  over  our  conduct, 
which  are  part  of  our  internal  experience.  But  the 
attempt  fails,  because  it  will  not  go  the  proper  length  of 
acknowledging  such  power  as  an  original  one.  A  man  '  has, 
to  a  certain  extent,  a  power  to  alter  his  own  character.' 
To  what  extent,  or  in  what  sense?  While  it  is  cin  the 
ultimate  resort  formed  for  him,  it  is  formed  by  him  as 
one  of  the  intermediate  agents.''  But  does  this  conces 
sion  of  an  intermediate  agency  satisfy  the  demands  of 
natural  feeling  and  instinct  on  this  head  ?  Would  any 
person  naturally  regard  that  power  of  choice,  of  which  he 
is  conscious,  as  a  power  which  he  exerts  in  obedience  and 
subordination  to  some  deeper  cause  working  underneath  it, 
and  obliging  it  to  be  exerted  in  a  particular  way  ?  Would 
not  a  certain  instinctive  view  he  takes  of  this  agency  in 
him  be  contradicted  by  this  view  of  it  as  intermediate- 


Note  V.  335 


agency,  only  apparently  original,  and  really  produced  by  a 
cause  beyond  itself?  Would  not  his  internal  sensations 
appear  upon  such  a  view  to  him  a  spurious  outside,  a  kind 
of  semblance  and  sham,  pretending  something  which  was 
not  really  true,  and  deluding  him  into  thinking  that  he 
was  an  original  agent  when  he  really  was  not  ? 

While,  then,  I  fully  admit,  in  addition  to  these  ideas 
and  sensations  of  originality  and  free  agency,  other  ideas 
counter  to  them — another  side  of  the  human  mind  to 
which  philosophy  and  theology  have  alike  legitimately 
appealed,  and  without  which  neither  necessarianism  nor 
the  doctrine  of  original  sin  would  have  arisen — I  cannot 
think  that  Mr.  Mill  does  justice  to  these  ideas — these 
true  perceptions,  it  appears  to  me,  as  far  as  they  go — of 
our  originality  as  agents. 

Hume's  argument  on  Liberty  and  Necessity  is  a  very 
summary  one.  He  does  not,  as  Mr.  Mill,  in  the  first 
instance,  appears  to  do,  from  the  observed  fact  of  causa 
tion  or  necessity  in  the  physical  world,  presume  the  same 
thing  in  the  moral ;  he  boldly  appeals  at  once  to  what 
he  considers  to  be  an  obvious  and  plain  fact  of  observa 
tion.  He  considers  necessity,  or  the  law  of  antecedent 
and  consequent,  to  be  as  plain  and  obvious  in  the  case  of 
human  actions  as  it  is  in  the  events  of  material  nature. 
'  Our  idea,'  he  says,  '  of  necessity  or  causation  arises  en 
tirely  from  the  uniformity  observable  in  the  operations  of 
nature.  Where  similar  objects  are  constantly  conjoined 
together,  and  the  mind  is  determined  by  custom  to  infer 
the  one  from  the  appearance  of  the  other,  these  two  cir 
cumstances  form  the  whole  of  that  necessity  which  we 
ascribe  to  matter.  Beyond  the  constant  conjunction  of 
similar  objects,  and  the  consequent  inference  from  one  to 
the  other,  we  have  no  idea  of  any  necessity  of  connexion. 
If  it  appear,  therefore,  that  all  mankind  have  ever  allowed, 
without  any  doubt  or  hesitation,  that  these  two  circum 
stances  take  place  in  the  voluntary  actions  of  men,  and  in 
the  operations  of  mind,  it  must  follow  that  all  mankind 
have  ever  agreed  in  the  doctrine  of  necessity,  and  that 


336  Note  V. 


they  have  hitherto  disputed  merely  from  not  understanding- 
one  another.' 

'  As  to  the  first  circumstance,  the  constant  and  regular 
conj  unction  of  similar  events,  we  may  perfectly  satisfy  our 
selves  by  the  following  considerations.  It  is  universally 
acknowledged  that  there  is  a  great  uniformity  among  the 
actions  of  men,  in  all  nations  and  ages,  and  that  human 
nature  remains  still  the  same  in  its  principles  and  opera 
tions.  The  same  motives  always  produce  the  same  actions  ; 
the  same  events  follow  the  same  causes.  Ambition,  avarice, 
self-love, vanity,  friendship,  generosity, public  spirit;  these 
passions,  mixed  in  various  degrees,  and  distributed  through 
out  society,  have  been  from  the  beginning  of  the  world, 
and  still  are,  the  sources  of  all  the  actions  and  enterprises 
which  have  ever  been  observed  among  mankind.  Would 
you  know  the  sentiments,  inclinations,  and  course  of  life 
of  the  Greeks  and  Eomans,  study  well  the  temper  and 
actions  of  the  French  and  English.  You  cannot  be  much 
mistaken  in  transferring  to  the  former  most  of  the  obser 
vations  you  have  made  with  regard  to  the  latter.  Mankind 
are  so  much  the  same,  in  all  times  and  places,  that  history 
informs  us  of  nothing  new  or  strange  in  this  particular. 
Its  chief  use  is  only  to  discover  the  constant  and  universal 
principles  of  human  nature,  by  showing  man  in  all  varieties 
of  circumstances  and  situations,  and  furnishing  us  with 
materials  from  which  we  may  form  our  observations,  and 
become  acquainted  with  the  regular  springs  of  human  action 
and  behaviour.  These  records  of  war,  intrigues,  factions, 
and  revolutions  are  so  many  collections  of  experiments  by 
which  the  politician  or  moral  philosopher  fixes  the  prin 
ciples  of  his  science,  in  the  same  manner  as  the  physician 
or  natural  philosopher  becomes  acquainted  with  the  nature 
of  plants,  minerals,  and  other  external  objects  by  the  ex 
periments  which  he  forms  concerning  them.  Nor  are  the 
earth,  water,  and  other  elements  examined  by  Aristotle  and 
Hippocrates  more  like  to  those  which  at  present  lie  under 
our  observation,  than  the  men  described  by  Polybius  or 
Tacitus  are  to  those  who  now  govern  the  world.' — Section 
viii.  On  Liberty  and  Necessity,  v.  iv.  p.  98. 


Note  V.  337 


No  argument  on  the  side  of  necessity  in  human  actions 
can  be  simpler  than  this ;  and  if  there  is  any  weight  in  it, 
the  question  is  decided  beyond  controversy  ;  for  it  is  simply 
an  appeal  to  our  observation  that  such  is  the  case,  an  asser 
tion  that  necessity  is  as  visible  in  human  actions  as  it  is 
in  the  events  of  nature.  But  any  reader  of  common  intel 
ligence  must  see  at  once  a  fundamental  error  underlying 
this  whole  argument,  which  entirely  deprives  it  of  force. 
The  uniformity  which  the  writer  observes  in  human  life 
and  conduct  applies  to  mankind  as  a  whole ;  while  the 
principle  of  necessity  can  only  be  properly  tested  by  the 
conduct  of  men  as  individuals.  On  the  common  doctrine 
of  chances,  mankind  as  a  whole  will  be  much  the  same  in 
one  generation  and  age  of  the  world  that  it  is  in  another ; 
i.e.  there  will  be  the  same  proportion  of  good  to  bad  men, 
the  same  relative  amount  of  selfish  and  disinterested,  gene 
rous  and  mean,  courageous  and  cowardly,  independent  and 
servile  characters.  But  the  doctrine  of  necessity  is  con 
cerned  with  the  individual  cases  which  compose  this  general 
average  of  human  character  ;  and  the  question  upon  which 
that  doctrine  turns  is,  whether  individuals  with  the  same 
antecedents — i.e.  the  same  inducements,  external  and  in 
ternal,  to  particular  conduct — have  uniformly  acted  in  the 
same  way.  The  sum  total  may  be  the  same,  but  the  ques 
tion  of  necessity  is  concerned  with  the  units  which  compose 
that  sum.  Have  the  individuals  who  have  been  bad  and 
good,  selfish  and  disinterested,  been  so  in  conjunction  with 
different  respective  sets  of  antecedents ;  i.e.  different  cir 
cumstances,  education  and  natural  temperament  ?  Or,  have 
not  persons  under  apparently  the  same  circumstances, 
education,  and  natural  temperament,  turned  out  very 
differently  ?  The  latter  is  certainly  the  more  natural  ob 
servation  of  the  two.  But  if  we  are  forbidden  to  make  it, 
and  reminded  that  we  do  not  know  all  the  antecedents, 
circumstances,  and  motives,  internal  and  external,  to  con 
duct,  in  the  case  of  individuals  ;  then  at  any  rate  nobody 
can  pretend  to  have  made  the  contrary  observation,  or  pro 
fess  to  have  noted  a  uniform  conjunction  of  antecedents 
and  consequents  in  the  case  of  human  action.  And  with 


,38  Note  VI. 


the  absence  of  this  observation  the  whole  of  this  argument 
falls  to  the  ground. 

NOTE  VI.  p.  32. 

FUIT  Adam  et  in  illo  fuimus  omnes. — Ambrose,  Lib.  7.  in 
Luc.  c.  15,  24.  n.  234.  In  lumbis  Adam  fuimus. — Aug. 
Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  48.  Unusquisque  homo  cum  primo 
nascitur. — De  Gen.  Contr.  Man.  1.  1.  c.  23.  Sic  autem 
aliena  sunt  originalia  peccata  propter  nullum  in  eis  nostee 
voluntatis  arbitrium,  ut  tamen  propter  originis  contagium 
esse  inveniantur  ut  nostra. —  Op.  Imp.  1.  1.  c.  57. 

Inobedientia  quidem  unius  hominis  non  absurde  utique 
delictum  dicitur  alienum,  quia  nondum  nati  nondum 
egeramus  aliquid  proprium,  sive  bonurn  sive  malum :  sed 
quia  in  illo  qui  hoc  fecit,  quando  id  agit,  omnes  eramus 
....  hoc  delictum  alienum  obnoxia  successione  fit  nos 
trum.—  Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  163. 

Ipsos  quoque  hoc  in  parente  fecisse,  quoniain  quando 
ipse  fecit,  in  illo  fuerunt,  ac  sic  ipsi  atque  ille  adhuc  unus 
fuerunt.— Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  177. 

Disce,  si  potes,  quemadmodum  peccata  originalia,  et 
aliena  intelligantur  et  nostra ;  non  eadem  causa  aliena  qua 
nostra :  aliena  enim,  quia  non  ea  in  sua  vita  quisque  com- 
misit,  nostra  vero  quia  fecit  Adam,  et  in  illo  fuimus  omnes. 
— Op.  Imp.  1.  3.  c.  25. 

Malum  est  de  peccato  veniens  originis  vitium,  cum  quo 
nascitur  homo  .  .  .  cujus  mali  reatus  non  innocentibus, 
ut  dicis,  sed  reis  imputatur.  .  .  .  Sic  enim  fuerunt  omnes 
ratione  seminis  in  lumbis  Adam,  quando  damnatus  est,  et 
ideo  sine  illis  damnatus  non  est ;  quemadmodum  fuerunt 
Israelite  in  lumbis  Abrahse  quando  decimatus  est,  et  ideo 
sine  illis  decimatus  non  est. — Op.  Imp.  1.  5.  c.  12. 

Per  unius  illius  voluntatem  malam  omnes  in  eo  pecca- 
verunt,  quando  omnes  ille  unus  fuerunt. — De  Nupt.  et 
Cone.  1.  2.  n.  15. 

S.  Anselm  regards  that  corruption  of  nature  which  is 
in  the  infant  at  its  birth  as  sin  then  and  at  the  time  in 
the  infant — cum  debito  satisfadendi ;  so  that  it  is  his 


Note  VI.  339 


own  sin  and  not  another's  for  which  he  is  responsible  in  his 
responsibility  for  original  sin  (De  Pec.  Oriy.  c.  2.) ;  a  posi 
tion  to  which  he  proceeds  to  give  further,  and  very  strong 
and  exact  expression  :  '  Originale  peccatum  esse  injustitiam 
dubitari  non  debet.  Narn  si  omne  peccatum  injustitia,  et 
originale  peccatum  utique  est  et  injustitia.  Sed  si  dicit 
aliquis  :  non  est  omne  peccatum  injustitia,  dicat  posse 
simul  in  aliquo  et  esse  peccatum,  et  nullam  esse  injusti 
tiam  :  quod  videtur  incredibile.  Si  vero  dicitur  originale 
peccatum  non  esse  absolute  dicendum  peccatum,  sed  cum 
additamento,  originale  peccatum,  sicut  pictus  homo  non 
vere  homo  est,  sed  vere  est  pictus  homo,  profecto  sequitur 
quia  infans  qui  nullum  habet  peccatum  nisi  originale 

mundus  est  a  peccato Quare  omne  peccatum  est 

injustitia,  et  originale  peccatum  est  absolute  peccatum.' 
-C.  3. 

Aquinas  is  against  the  imputation  of  another's  act  for 
the  purpose  of  guilt,  though  he  allows  it  for  that  of  satis 
faction  :  6  Dicendum  quod  si  loquamur  de  pnena  satisfac- 
toria,  qua3  vomntarie  assumitur,  contingit  quod  cum  unus 
portet  poenam  alterius,  in  quantum  sunt  quodammodo 
unum.  Si  autem  loquimur  de  poana  pro  peccato  inflicta, 
in  quantum  habet  rationem  poenre,  sic  solum  unusquisque 
pro  peccato  suo  punitur,  quia  actus  peccati  aliquid  pcr- 
sonale  eat.9— Sum.  Tlieol.  lma  2dae  Q.  87.  Art.  8. 

The  disputes  at  the  Council  of  Trent  on  the  subject  of 
original  sin  touched  more  on  the  extent  of  the  effects  of  it 
than  on  the  rationale  of  its  transmission.  But  the  view 
of  imputation  was  maintained  by  Catarinus  against  the 
Dominicans,  who  followed  the  Augustinian  idea  of  original 
sin  as  real  sin  in  the  individual.  « He  oppugned  the  trans 
mission  of  sin  by  means  of  the  seed  and  generation  ;  saying 
that,  as,  if  Adam  had  not  sinned,  righteousness  would  have 
been  infused  not  by  virtue  of  the  generation,  but  only  by 
the  will  of  Grod,  so  it  is  fit  to  find  another  means  to  trans 
fuse  sin The  action  of  Adam  is  actual  sin  in  him, 

and  imputed  to  others  is  original ;  because  when  he  sinned 
all  men  did  (i.e.  by  imputation)  sin  with  him.  Catarinus 
grounded  himself  principally,  for  that  a  true  and  proper  sin 

z  2 


34-O  Note  VII. 


must  be  a  voluntary  act,  and  no  other  thing  can  be  volun 
tary  but  the  transgression  of  Adam  imputed  unto  all.  .  .  . 
The  opinion  of  Catarinus  was  expressed  by  a  political  con 
ceit  of  a  bargain  made  by  one  for  his  posterity,  which,  being 
transgressed,  they  are  all  undoubtedly  bound.' — PauVs 
History  of  Council  of  Trent  (Brent),  pp.  165.  168. 

NOTE  VII.  p.  33. 

JEREMY  TAYLOR'S  argument  on  original  sin  is  directed 
throughout  against  the  received  and  Catholic  interpreta 
tion  of  that  sin,  as  involving  desert  of  eternal  punishment, 
which  he  rejects  as  being  opposed  to  our  natural  idea  of 
justice.  '  Was  it  just  in  Grod  to  damn  all  mankind  to  the 
eternal  pains  of  hell  for  Adam's  sin  committed  before  they 
had  any  being,  or  could  consent  to  it  or  know  of  it  ?  If  it 
could  be  just,  then  anything  in  the  world  can  be  just ;  and 
it  is  no  matter  who  is  innocent,  or  who  is  criminal,  directly 
or  by  choice,  since  they  may  turn  devils  in  their  mother's 
bellies ;  and  it  matters  not  whether  there  be  any  laws  or 
no,  since  it  is  all  one  that  there  be  no  laws,  and  that  we 
do  not  know  whether  there  be  or  no ;  and  it  matters  not 
whether  there  be  any  judicial  proofs,  for  we  may  as  well  be 
damned  without  judgment,  as  be  guilty  without  action.' — 
Vol.  ix.  p.  332.  '  And  truly,  my  Lord,  to  say  that  for 
Adam's  sin  it  is  just  in  Grod  to  condemn  infants  to  the 
eternal  flames  of  hell,  and  to  say  that  concupiscence  or 
natural  inclinations  before  they  pass  into  any  act  would 
bring  eternal  condemnation  from  Grod's  presence  into  the 
eternal  portion  of  devils,  are  two  such  horrid  propositions, 
that  if  any  church  in  the  world  should  expressly  affirm 
them,  I,  for  my  part,  should  think  it  unlawful  to  commu 
nicate  with  her  in  the  defence  or  profession  of  either,  and 
to  think  it  would  be  the  greatest  temptation  in  the  world 
to  make  men  not  to  love  Grod,  of  whom  men  so  easily  speak 
such  horrid  things.' — p.  373.  'Is  hell  so  easy  a  pain, 
or  are  the  souls  of  children  of  so  cheap,  so  contemptible 
,-a  price,  that  Grod  should  so  easily  throw  them  into  hell  ? 
£r<pd's  goodness,  which  pardons  many  sins  that  we  could 


Note  VII.  34 


avoid,  will  not  so  easily  throw  them  into  hell  for  what  they 
could  not  avoid.' — p.  14.  'To  condemn  infants  to  hell  for 
the  fault  of  another,  is  to  deal  worse  with  them  than  God 
did  to  the  very  devils,  who  did  not  perish  but  by  an  act  of 
their  own  most  perfect  choice.  This,  besides  the  formality 
of  injustice  or  cruelty,  does  add  and  suppose  a  circumstance 
of  a  strange,  ungentle  contrivance.  For,  because  it  cannot 
be  supposed  that  God  should  damn  infants  or  innocents 
without  cause,  it  finds  out  this  way,  that  God,  to  bring 
His  purposes  to  pass,  should  create  a  guilt  for  them,  or 
bring  them  into  an  inevitable  condition  of  being  guilty  by 
a  way  of  His  own  inventing.  For,  if  He  did  not  make 
such  an  agreement  with  Adam,  He  beforehand  knew  that 
Adam  would  forfeit  all,  and  therefore  that  unavoidably  all 
his  posterity  would  be  surprised.  This  is  to  make  pretences, 
and  to  invent  justifications  and  reasons  of  His  proceedings, 
which  are  indeed  all  one  as  if  they  were  not.' — p.  l(i. 
'  Abraham  was  confident  with  God,  "  Wilt  Thou  slay  the 
righteous  with  the  wicked  ?  shall  not  the  Judge  of  all 
the  earth  do  right  ?  "  And  if  it  be  unrighteous  to  slay  the 
righteous  with  the  wicked,  it  is  also  unjust  to  slay  the 
righteous  for  the  wicked.  "  Ferretne  ulla  civitas  laborem 
istiusmodi  legis,  ut  condemneturfilius  aut  nepos,  si  pater 
aut  avus  deliquissent ; — It  were  an  intolerable  law,  and 
no  community  would  be  governed  by  it,  that  the  father  or 
grandfather  should  sin,  and  the  son  or  nephew  should  be 
punished."' — p.  39. 

No  one  can,  of  course,  deny  the  force  of  these  argu 
ments,  resting,  as  they  do,  upon  the  simple  maxim  of 
common  sense  and  common  justice,  that  no  man  is  respon 
sible  for  another's  sins.  The  mistake  in  Jeremy  Taylor's 
mind  lies  in  his  conception  of  the  doctrine  which  he  is  at 
tacking.  He  supposes  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  to  assert 
mankind's  desert  of  eternal  punishment  for  Adam's  sin,  in 
an  ordinary  and  matter-of-fact  sense  ;  and  he  treats  all  the 
consequences  of  this  doctrine— the  Divine  anger  with  infants 
and  the  like— as  if  they  took  place  in  the  literal  sense  m 
which  they  would  take  place,  supposing  a  present  visible 
execution  of  this  sentence,  in  this  present  and  visible  state 


342  Note  VII. 


of  things.  But  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  professes  to  be 
concerned  with  a  mystery,  not  with  a  matter  of  fact,  and 
to  be  an  incomprehensible,  and  not  an  intelligible  truth. 
For  all  this  vivid  picture,  then,  of  injustice,  and  monstrous 
cruelty  which  Jeremy  Taylor  raises  as  a  representation  of 
this  doctrine,  there  is  no  warrant ;  because  the  doctrine 
does  not  profess  to  assert  anything  whatever  that  we  can 
understand.  He  argues  as  if  human  analogies  gave  us  a 
sufficient  and  true  idea  of  the  truth  asserted  in  this  doc 
trine,  whereas  the  doctrine  takes  us  out  of  all  human 
analogies.  His  whole  argument  thus  beats  the  air,  and 
he  refutes  what  no  sound-minded  and  reasonable  person 
asserts. 

His  argument  against  the  assertion  of  the  impotence 
and  slavery  of  the  will,  involved  in  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin,  is  open  to  the  same  remark  ;  i.e.  that  he  takes  it  as 
an  absolute  assertion,  whereas  it  is  only  maintained  in  this 
doctrine  as  one  side  of  a  whole  truth  on  this  subject,  which 
is  beyond  our  knowledge.  '  To  deny  to  the  will  of  man 
powers  of  choice  and  election,  or  the  use  of  it  in  the  actions 
of  our  life,  destroys  the  immortality  of  the  soul.  Human 
nature  is  in  danger  to  be  lost  if  it  diverts  to  that  which  is 
against  nature  !  For  if  it  be  immortal  it  can  never  die  in 
its  noblest  faculty.  But  if  the  will  be  destroyed,  that  is, 
disabled  from  choosing  (which  is  all  the  work  the  will  hath 
to  do),  then  it  is  dead.  For  to  live  and  to  be  able  to 
operate  in  philosophy  are  all  one.  If  the  will,  therefore, 
cannot  operate,  how  is  it  immortal  ?  And  we  may  as  well 
suppose  an  understanding  that  can  never  understand,  and 
passions  that  can  never  desire  or  refuse,  and  a  memory 
that  can  never  remember,  as  a  will  that  cannot  choose.' — 
Vol.  ix.  p.  47.  '  When  it  is  affirmed  in  the  writings  of 
some  doctors  that  the  will  of  man  is  depraved,  men  pre 
sently  suppose  that  depravation  is  a  natural  or  physical 
effect,  and  means  a  diminution  of  power,  whereas  it  signi 
fies  nothing  but  a  being  in  love  with,  or  having  chosen  an 
evil  object,  and  not  an  impossibility  or  weakness  to  the 
contrary,  but  only  because  it  will  not ;  for  the  power  of 
the  will  cannot  be  lessened  by  any  act  of  the  same  faculty, 


Note  VIL  343 


for  the  act  is  not  contrary  to   the  faculty,  and  therefore 
can  do  nothing  towards  its  destruction.     As  a  consequent, 
of  this  I  infer  that  there  is  no  natural  necessity  of  sinning, 
— that  there  is  no  sinful  action  to  which  naturally  we  are 
determined  ;  but  it  is  our  own  choice  that  we  sin.' — p.  88. 
This  is  the  Pelagian  argument  for  freewill  which  we 
meet  with  in  8.  Augustine  ;  and  it  has  the  one-sidcdness 
of  that  argument.     Nobody,  of  course,  can  d  ny  what  is 
asserted  here,  if  considered  as  one  side  of  the  truth  ;  it  is 
true  that  the  will  must  have  the  power  of  choosing  ;  that 
we  are  conscious  of  this  power;  that  there  is  'no  natural 
necessity  for  sinning  ; '  that  '  there  is  no  sinful  action   to 
which  we  are  naturally  determined.'     All  this  enters  into 
our  meaning  of  the  term  will,  and  our  consciousness  of  its 
operations.     But  there  is  another  side  of  the  whole  truth 
respecting  the  will  to  which  S.  Augustine   appeals :  '  To 
will  is  present  with  me,  but  how  to  perform  that  which   is 
good  I  know  not.     For  the  good  that  I  would  [  do  not, 
but  the  evil  that  I  would  not  that  I  do.     Jeremy   Taylor 
appeals,  as  the  Pelagians  did,  to  a  certain  sense  of  bare 
ability  to  do  right  which  we  retain  under  all  circumstances 
and  states  of  mind,  as  if  it  were  the  whole  truth  on  this 
subject ;  he  relies  absolutely  upon  it.    He  goes  even  to  the 
length  to  which  the  Pelagians  went,  of  saying  '  that  the 
power  of  the  will  cannot  be  lessened  by  any  act  of  the 
same  faculty,'  so  that  however  long  a  man  may  continue  in 
a  course  of  sin,  and  however  inveterate  the  habit  he  may 
contract,  he  has  still  as  much  freewill  as  ever,  and  on  the 
very  next  occasion  of  acting  is  as  able  to  act  aright  as  ever. 
But  this  is  evidently,  and  on  principles  of  common  sense, 
untrue.     Jeremy  Taylor  sees  only  that  side  of  the  human 
will  which  favours  his  own  argument ;  he  sees  in  it  a  simple 
unity,  a  pure  undivided  faculty,  a  power  of  doing  anything 
to  which  there  is  no  physical  hindrance ;  but  the  will  is  a 
mixed  and  complex  thing,  exhibiting  oppositions  and  in 
congruities.    He  proceeds  upon  an  abstract  idea  of  treewil 
— '  there  cannot  be  a  will  that  cannot  choose ;    but  the 
question  is,  what  is  the  actual  and  real  will  of  which  we 
,  find  ourselves  possessed  ? 


344  Note  VII. 


Taylor  sees  in  the  doctrine  of  original  sin,  according'  to 
the  received  strict  interpretation  of  it,  a  basis  of  the  doc 
trine  of  predestination  (p.  319),  and  argues  against  them 
as  virtually  one  and  the  same  doctrine;  in  doing  which  he 
is  right.  But  if  the  ground  is  only  true  in  a  mysterious 
sense,  that  which  is  raised  upon  it  is  only  true  in  the  same 
sense,  and  is  so  deprived  of  its  definiteness,  and  conse 
quently  of  its  harshness  ;  for  a  doctrine  to  be  harsh  must 
positively  state  something.  As  a  mystery  it  disowns  such 
a  charge. 

The  received  interpretation  of  original  sin  being  thus 
rejected,  Jeremy  Taylor  substitutes  for  it  the  more  lenient 
interpretation  put  forward  by  the  early  fathers  of  this  sin, 
as  a  deprivation,  viz.  of  certain  higher  and  supernatural 
gifts  conferred  upon  man  at  his  creation  ;  an  absence  of 
perfection,  as  distinguished  from  a  positive  state  of  sin. 
'  This  sin  brought  upon  Adam  all  that  God  threatened — 
but  no  more.  A  certainty  of  dying,  together  with  the 
proper  effects  and  affections  of  mortality,  were  inflicted  on 
him,  and  he  was  reduced  to  the  condition  of  his  own  nature, 
and  then  begat  sons  and  daughters  in  his  own  likeness, 
that  is,  in  the  proper  temper  and  constitution  of  mortal 
men.  For  as  (rod  was  not  bound  to  give  what  He  never 
promised — viz.,  an  immortal  duration  and  abode  in  this 
life, — so  neither  does  it  appear,  in  that  angry  intercourse 
that  God  had  with  Adam,  that  he  took  from  him  or  us  any 
of  our  natural  perfections,  but  his  graces  only.  Man  being 
left  in  this  state  of  pure  naturals,  could  not  by  his  own 
strength  arrive  to  a  supernatural  end,  which  was  typified 
in  his  being  cast  out  of  Paradise,  and  the  guarding  of  it 
with  the  flaming  sword  of  a  cherub.  For  eternal  life  being 
an  end  above  our  natural  proportions,  cannot  be  acquired 
by  any  natural  means.' — Vol.  ix.  p.  1.  f  God  gives  his 
gifts  as  He  pleases,  and  is  unjust  to  no  man  by  giving  or 
not  giving  any  certain  proportion  of  good  things;  and 
supposing  this  loss  was  brought  first  upon  Adam,  and  so 
descended  upon  us,  yet  we  have  no  cause  to  complain,  for 
we  lost  nothing  that  was  ours.' — p.  56. 

When  he  comes,  however,  to  reconcile  this  modification 


Note  VII.  345 


of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  with  Scripture,  and  to  prove 
'  that  in  Scripture  there  is  no  signification  of  any  corruj)- 
tion  or  deprivation  of  our  souls  by  Adam's  sin,'  he  has  to 
explain  away  texts.  The  text  Rom.  v.  18.  '  By  the  offence 
of  one  judgment  came  upon  all  men  to  condemnation,' 
asserts  the  condemnation,  KaTaKpi/Jia,  of  all  mankind  as  the 
consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam.  Taylor  explains  '  damna 
tion  '  first  as  poena  damni,  a  loss  of  a  higher  state  ;  and, 
secondly,  of  temporal  death — which  was  '  the  whole  event, 
for  it  names  no  other — according  to  that  saying  of  S.  Paul, 
"  In  Adam  we  all  die." '  But  this  is  an  artificial  explana 
tion  of  Scripture.  It  is  true,  as  he  observes,  that  'the 
KarcLKpifjia  passed  upon  all  men,  sfi  a>  Travrzs  tf/jLaprov' 
(p.  380);  but  this  can  only  show  that  the  natural  truth  is 
maintained  in  Scripture  together  with  the  mysterious  one, 
not  that  the  mysterious  one  is  not  maintained.  So  of  the 
text  '  Death  passed  upon  all  men  ;  for  that  all  have  sinned,' 
he  says, '  all  men,  that  is,  the  generality  of  mankind,  all  that 
lived  till  they  could  sin ;  the  others  that  died  before,  died 
j.n  their  nature,  not  in  their  sin.1 — p.  381.  He  owns, 
however,  at  last,  that  the  language  of  Scripture  is  against 
him,  by  falling  back  upon  the  ground  of  justice  as  over 
ruling  the  natural  meaning  of  such  language.  «  How  can 
it  be  just  that  the  "  condemnation  "  should  pass  upon  us 
for  Adam's  sin  ?  '—p.  380. 

So  upon  the  text,  '  Behold  I  was  shapen  in  wickedness, 
and  in  sin  hath  my  mother  conceived  me,'  he  says,  4 1 
answer,  that  the  words  are  a  Hebraism,  and  signify  nothing 
but  an  aggrandation  of  his  sinfulness,  and  are  intended  for 
a  high  expression,  meaning  that "  I  am  wholly  and  entirely 
wicked."  For  the  verification  of  which  exposition  there 
are  divers  parallel  places  in  the  Holy  Scriptures :  "  Thou 
wast  my  hope,  when  I  hanged  yet  upon  my  mother's 
breast ;"  and  "  The  ungodly  as  soon  as  they  be  born,  they  go 
astray  and  speak  lies,"  which,  because  it  cannot  be  true  in 
the  letter,  must  be  an  idiotism  or  propriety  of  phrase,  apt 
to  explicate  the  other,  and  signify  only  a  ready,  a  prompt, 
a  great,  and  universal  wickedness.  The  like  to  this  is  that 
saying  of  the  Pharisees,  "  Thou  wert  altogether  born  in  sin, 


346  Note  VII. 


and  dost  thou  teach  us  ? "  which  phrase  and  manner  of 
speaking  being  plainly  a  reproach  of  the  poor  blind  man 
and  a  disparagement  of  him,  did  mean  only  to  call  him  a 
very  wicked  person,  not  that  he  had  derived  his  sin  origin 
ally  and  from  his  birth.' — p.  27.  But  even  were  the  text, 
'  In  sin  hath  my  mother  conceived  me,'  only  a  phrase 
to  express  the  depth  and  strength  of  sin  in  the  character 
of  the  person  using  it,  why  should  that  depth  and  strength 
of  sin  be  expressed  in  that  form  ?  Why  does  David,  on 
the  first  deep  perception  of  his  own  guilt,  and  the  hold 
which  sin  has  had  over  him,  go  back  to  his  birth  ?  Is  it 
not  because  he  cannot  see  how  he  can  stop  short  of  it  ? 
The  more  he  considers  the  sinfulness  of  his  character  the 
more  rooted  it  seems,  and  the  further  it  appears  to  go  back, 
till  at  last  he  cannot  but  say,  that  it  is  actually  coeval  with 
his  existence.  The  phrase,  then,  though  it  may  not  be  a 
dogmatic  assertion  of  original  sin,  is  an  assertion  of  a 
certain  depth  and  radical  position  of  sin  in  the  human 
soul ;  upon  which,  when  realised,  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin  naturally  arises.  Such  phrases  as  this,  and  the  others 
in  Scripture  referred  to  by  Taylor,  show  that  there  was 
a  truth  felt  respecting  sin,  which  was  expressed  in  this 
form  as  the  most  appropriate  one  for  it,  and  that  whenever 
men  perceived  the  strength  of  the  hold  which  sin  had  had 
upon  them,  they  went  to  the  idea  of  its  originality,  as  an 
idea  nothing  short  of  which  would  do  justice  to  that  truth 
which  they  felt  respecting  sin,  and  which  the  fuller  con 
sciousness  of  their  own  sins  had  revealed  to  them. 

So  on  the  text,  6  By  nature  we  were  children  of  wrath,' 
Taylor  remarks  :  '  True,  we  were  so  when  we  were  dead  in 
sins,  and  before  we  were  quickened  by  the  Spirit  of  life 
and  grace.  We  ivere  so  ;  now  we  are  not.  We  were  so 
by  our  own  unworthiness  and  filthy  conversation ;  now  we 
being  regenerated  by  the  Spirit  of  holiness,  we  are  heirs 
unto  Grod,  and  no  longer  heirs  of  wrath.  This,  therefore, 
as  appears  by  the  discourse  of  S.  Paul,  relates  not  to  our 
original  sin,  but  to  the  actual;  and  of  this  sense  of  the 
word  "  nature,"  in  the  matter  of  sinning,  we  have  Justin 
Martyr,  or  whoever  is  the  author  of  the  questions  and 


Note  VII. 


347 


.answers  Ad  Orthodoxos,  to  be  witness.  For  answering 
those  words  of  Scripture,  "  There  is  not  any  one  clean  who  is 
born  of  a  woman,"  and  there  is  none  begotten  who  hath  not 
committed  sin ;  he  says,  their  meaning1  cannot  extend  to 
Christ,  for  He  was  not  "  TTS^UKMS  d^apravsiv — born  to 
sin ;"  but  he  is  '  natura  ad  peccandum  natus — TTS^VKWS 
d/jLapravsiv,"  who,  by  the  choice  of  his  own  will,  is  author 
to  himself  to  do  what  he  list,  whether  it  be  good  or  evil,  6 
KCLTO,  tr)v  avOaipBTOv  irpoalpsa'LV  ciywv  savrov  sis  TO  Trpdr- 
TSLV  a  (BovKzrai  sirs  dyaOa  SITS  </>at)Xa.' — p.  29.  One  who 
can  sin,  then,  is  born  to  sin,  in  Taylor's  sense  of  the 
phrase ;  a  man  being  born  to  sin  means  that  he  can  sin, 
and  no  more.  But  such  a  meaning  is  inconsistent  with 
his  own  previous  meaning  of  the  similar  phrase, '  By  nature 
children  of  wrath,'  which  he  understands  to  mean  great 
and  habitual  actual  sin,  or  a  bad  and  corrupt  course  of  life  ; 
for  the  power  to  sin  and  the  fact  of  sin  are  not  the  same 
thing.  Either  meaning,  however  plainly,  falls  short  of  the 
Apostle's.  Why  should  S.  Paul  say  '  by  nature,"1  if  actual 
sin  was  all  that  he  meant?  The  term  evidently  intro 
duces  another  idea  beyond  and  in  addition  to  an  actual 
bad  course  of  life. 

The  modification  which  Taylor  has  hitherto  proposed 
of  the  doctrine  of  original  sin  has  been  rather  concerned 
with  its  effects  than  with  itself.  The  particular  view  of 
the  sin  itself  which  he  proposes  to  substitute  for  the  re 
ceived  one  is,  that  it  is  imputed  sin,  as  distinguished  from 
real  sin  in  us.  He  objects  to  the  idea  of  our  being  parties 
to  Adam's  sin  as  absurd  ;  but  has  no  objection  to  a  certain 
imputation  of  that  sin,  considered  to  be  his  and  his  only, 
to  us.  '  Indeed,  my  Lord,  that  I  may  speak  freely  in  this 
great  question :  when  one  man  hath  sinned,  his  descendants 
and  relations  cannot  possibly  by  him,  or  for  him,  or  in 
him  be  made  sinners  really  and  properly.  For  in  sin  there 
are  but  two  things  imaginable,  the  irregular  action  and  the 
guilt  or  obligation  to  punishment.  Now,  we  cannot  be 
said  in  any  sense  to  have  done  the  action  which  another 
did,  and  not  we  ;  the  action  is  as  individual  as  the  person  ; 
and  Titius  may  as  well  be  Caius,  and  the  son  be  his  own 


348  Note  VII. 


father,  as  he  can  be  said  to  have  done  the  father's  action  ; 
and  therefore  we  cannot  possibly  be  guilty  for  it,  for  guilt 
is  an  obligation  to  punishment  for  having  done  it ;  the 
action  and  the  guilt  are  relatives — one  cannot  be  done 
without  the  other, — something  must  be  done  inwardly  or 
outwardly,  or  there  can  be  no  guilt.  But  then  for  the  evil 
of  punishment,  that  may  pass  further  than  the  action.  If 
it  passes  upon  the  innocent  it  is  not  a  punishment  to  them, 
but  an  evil  inflicted  in  right  of  dominion ;  but  yet  by 
reason  of  the  relation  of  the  afflicted  to  him  that  hath 
sinned,  to  him  it  is  a  punishment.  But  if  it  passes  upon 
others  that  are  not  innocent,  then  it  is  a  punishment  to 
both  ;  to  the  first  principally  ;  to  the  descendants  or  rela 
tives  for  the  other's  sake,  his  sin  being  imputed  so  far,' — 
p.  379.  '  There  is  no  necessity  to  affirm  that  we  are 
sinners  in  Adam  any  more  than  by  imputation.' — p.  378. 

Taylor  considers  this  view  of  imputation  as  a  middle 
one  between  the  received  and  the  Pelagian  view  of  original 
sin.  '  I  do  not  approve  of  that  gloss  of  the  Pelagians 
that  in  Adam  we  are  made  sinners  by  imitation,  and  much 
less  of  that  which  affirms  that  we  are  made  so  properly 
and  formally.  But  made  sinners  signifies  used  like  sinners, 
so  as  justified  signifies  treated  like  just  persons  ;  in  which 
interpretation  I  follow  S.  Paul,  not  the  Pelagians.' — p. 
383. 

But  what  is  gained  toward  reconciling  the  doctrine 
of  original  sin  with  our  natural  ideas,  by  substituting  the 
imputation  of  Adam's  sin  for  sin  in  Adam  ?  If  it  is 
contrary  to  reason  that  a  man  should  be  a  party  to  sin 
committed  before  he  was  born,  it  is  contrary  to  justice 
that  a  sin  in  which  he  was  no  partaker  should  be  imputed 
to  him,  and  that  he  should  be  punished  for  it.  It  is  true, 
he  says,  l  If  the  evil  of  punishment  passes  upon  the 
innocent,  it  is  not  a  punishment  to  them,  but  an  evil 
inflicted  by  right  of  dominion,  and  therefore  Eabbi 
Simeon  Barsema  said  well,  that  "  When  God  visits  the 
vices  of  the  fathers  upon  the  children — jure  Dominii, 
-non  pcence  utitur — He  uses  the  right  of  empire  not  of 


Note  VII.  349 


justice." '  The  result  of  this  distinction  is,  that  God,  in 
cases  of  punishment  for  imputed  sin,  inflicts  no  more 
evil  than  He  has  a  right  to  inflict  where  there  is  no  sin 
in  the  case.  But  if  on  such  a  ground  the  imputation  of 
sin  is  reconciled  with  our  idea  of  justice,  what  becomes 
of  the  idea  itself  of  imputation  ?  There  is  evidently  no 
real  imputation  of,  no  punishment  for,  another's  sin,  and 
therefore  this  whole  mode  of  representing  original  sin 
falls  to  the  ground.  Taylor  says,  '  By  reason  of  the  rela 
tion  of  the  afflicted  to  him  that  sinned,  to  him  it  is  a 
punishment.'  Why  so  ?  Whether  a  certain  evil  is  a 
punishment  depends  on  the  ground  on  which  it  is  inflicted. 
If  it  is  inflicted  on  the  ground  of  guilt,  actual  or  imputed, 
it  is  punishment;  if  it  is  inflicted  simply  jure  Domini /, 
on  the  ground  of  that  right  which  the  Maker  of  the 
world  has  over  the  lives  and  fortunes  of  His  creatures,  it 
is  not  punishment,  but  Providence.  But  Taylor  is  still 
unwilling  to  abandon  the  idea  of  punishment,  and  lie 
suggests  a  form  of  punishment  which,  he  thinks,  is  not 
liable  to  any  charge  of  injustice.  '  In  Adam  we  are  made 
sinners,  that  is,  treated  ill  or  afflicted,  though  ourselves 
be  innocent  of  that  sin,  ivhich  was  the  occasion  of  our 
being  used  so  severely  for  other  sins,  of  which  we  were, 
not  innocent'— ]).  4.  God  inflicts  pain  upon  us,  then  ; 
•which  pain  is  punishment,  because  such  pain  is  greater 
than  it  would  have  been  but  for  Adam's  sin ;  we  are  not 
punished  for  Adam's  sin,  but  we  are,  in  consequence  of 
Adam's  sin,  punished  worse  for  our  own  sins.  But  the 
difficulty  of  punishment  is  not  at  all  lessened  by  this 
artifice  of  attaching  the  punishment  to  our  own  actual 
sins  in  the  first  place,  and  only  charging  upon  Adam's  sin 
the  increase  of  this  punishment.  Increase  of  punishment 
is  fresh  punishment.  Taylor  thus  oscillates  between 
acknowledging  and  disowning  punishment  for  Adam's 
sin.  He  disowns  it  as  inconsistent  with  justice ;  he 
acknowledges  it  because  he  cannot  wholly  deny  that  some 
thing  very  like  it  is  maintained  in  Scripture,  and  he 
shrinks  from  wholly  giving  up  the  received  doctrine.  He 


350  Note  VIIL 


thus  constructs  a  kind  of  indirect  vicarious  punishment, 
which  is  inflicted  for  our  own  personal  sins,  but  inflicted 
more  severely  on  account  of  Adam's  sin. 

Jeremy  Taylor  falls  into  all  these  forced  and  incon 
sistent  modes  of  explanation,  in  consequence  of  the  funda 
mental  misapprehension  with  which  he  starts  as  to  the 
sense  and  mode  in  which  the  truth  of  original  sin  is  held. 
Had  he  perceived  properly  that  it  was  and  professed  to  be 
a  mysterious  as  distinguished  from  an  intelligible  truth, 
he  would  have  seen  that  all  these  charges  of  injustice 
against  the  doctrine  were  erroneous,  and  these  consequent 
attempts  at  a  modification  of  it  superfluous  and  unneces 
sary.  The  profession  of  a  mystery  disarms  the  opposition 
of  reason  ;  for  what  has  reason  to  object  to  in  that  which 
it  does  not  understand  ?  What  has  reason  before  it  in 
such  a  case  ?  One  who  holds  the  doctrine  in  this  sense 
can  hold  it  in  its  greatest  strictness,  without  the  slightest 
collision  with  reason  or  justice,  and  is  spared  this  vain 
struggle  with  Scripture. 

NOTE  VIIL  p.  35. 

THE  doctrine  of  predestination  in  Scripture  is  not  uncom 
monly  interpreted  in  such  a  way  as  to  represent  that  doc 
trine,  not  as  opposed  to  any  counter  truth  of  freewill,  but 
as  itself  harmonising  and  coinciding  with  it.  Predesti 
nation  and  election  are  interpreted  to  mean  predestination 
and  election  to  privileges  or  means  of  grace,  which  depend 
on  freewill  for  their  cultivation.  But  this  is  certainly  not 
the  natural  sense  of  the  words  in  Scripture.  In  the  text 
Matt.  xx.  1 6,  '  Many  are  called  but  few  chosen,'  or  elect ; 
4  elect '  evidently  means  elect  to  eternal  life  itself,  and  not 
merely  to  the  opportunity  of  attaining  it.  The  same  may 
be  said  of  Matt.  xxiv.  22  :  '  For  the  elect's  sake  those  days 
shall  be  shortened,'  the  elect  being  evidently  here  the 
saints,  the  good,  those  who  will  be  saved,  not  those  who 
have  merely  been  admitted  into  the  Christian  Church 
and  the  means  of  obtaining  salvation,  many  of  whom 
being  wicked  men  and  enemies  of  God,  Grod  would  not 
'  for  their  sakes '  perform  this  special  act  of  mercy.  On 


Note_  VIII.  35 1 

Acts  xiii.  48,  '  As  many  as  were  ordained  to  eternal  life  be 
lieved,'  the  remark  is  obvious  that  that  to  which  men  are 
said  to  be  '  ordained '  (which  is  the  same  as  elect  or  pre 
destinated)  is  expressly  '  eternal  life.'  In  Eph.  i.  4, 
'  According '  as  He  hath  chosen  us  in  Him,  before  the 
foundation  of  the  world,  that  we  should  be  holy,'  the 
election  is  not  to  the  power  but  to  the  fact  of  holiness. 
And  the  next  verse  sustains  this  obvious  sense  :  '  Having 
predestinated  us  unto  the  adoption  of  children  by  Jesus 
Christ  to  Himself,'  adoption  always  implying  in  the  epistles 
sanctity.  So  2  Tim.  i.  9  :  '  Who  hath  saved  us  and  called 
us  with  an  holy  calling,  not  according  to  our  works,  but 
according  to  His  own  purpose  and  grace  which  was  given 
us  in  Christ  before  the  world  began,'  obviously  speaks  of 
actual  holiness  and  actual  salvation,  not  the  mere  oppor 
tunity  of  them,  as  the  eti'ect  of  predestination.  And 
generally  it  is  evident  that  the  terms  elect,  predestinated, 
adopted,  justified,  saints,  all  refer  to  the  same  state  and 
the  same  class  ;  and  that  plainly  the  state  and  the  class  of 
actually  holy  men  who  will  certainly  be  saved,  as  the 
necessary  consequence  and  reward  of  such  holiness. 

The  8th  and  9th  chapters,  however,  of  the  Epistle  to 
the  Eomans,  furnish  the  most  powerful,  and  because  the 
most  powerful  the  most  controverted,  evidence  for  the 
meaning  of  predestination  as  being  predestination  to 
eternal  life  itself,  and  not  merely  certain  means  of  grace 
enabling  men  to  obtain  it.  In  the  8th  is  the  passage  : 
'  We  know  that  all  things  work  together  for  good  to  them 
that  love  Grod,  to  them  who  are  the  called  according  to  His 
purpose.  For  whom  He  did  foreknow  (know  before  as 
His  own  with  determination  to  be  for  ever  merciful  unto 
them— Hooker,  Appendix  to  bk.  v.  vol.  ii.  p.  751).  He 
also  predestinated  to  be  conformed  to  the  image  of  His  Son, 
that  He  might  be  the  first  born  among  many  brethren. 
Moreover,  whom  He  did  predestinate,  them  He  also  called, 
and  whom  He  called,  them  He  also  justified,  and  whom 
He  justified  them  He  also  glorified.'  Here  it  is  expressly 
said  that  those  who  are  predestinated  are  predestinated, 
not  to  the  opportunity  of  conformation  to  the  image  of 


,52  Note  VIII. 


Christ,  but  to  that  conformation  itself,  to  actual  justifica 
tion,  and  to  actual  glory  in  the  world  to  come. 

The  9th  chapter  has  the  passage  :  '  For  the  children 
being  not  yet  born,  neither  having  done  any  good  or  evil, 
that  the  purpose  of  Grod  according  to  election  might  stand, 
not  of  works,  but  of  Him  that  calleth,  it  was  said  unto 
her,  the  elder  shall  serve  the  younger.  As  it  is  written, 
Jacob  have  I  loved,  but  Esau  have  I  hated.  What  shall 
we  say  then  ?  Is  there  unrighteousness  with  (rod  ?  (rod 
forbid.  For  He  saith  to  Moses,  I  will  have  mercy  on 
whom  I  will  have  mercy,  and  I  will  have  compassion  on 
whom  I  will  have  compassion.  So  then  it  is  not  of  him 
that  willeth,  nor  of  him  that  runneth,  but  of  Grod  that 
sheweth  mercy.  For  the  Scripture  saith  unto  Pharaoh, 
even  for  this  same  purpose  have  I  raised  thee  up,  that  I 
might  show  My  power  in  thee,  and  that  My  name  might 
be  declared  throughout  all  the  earth.  Therefore  hath 
He  mercy  on  whom  He  will  have  mercy,  and  whom  He 
will  He  hardeneth.  Thou  wilt  say  then  unto  me,  Why 
doth  He  yet  find  fault  ?  for  who  hath  resisted  His  will  ? 
Nay,  but,  0  man,  who  art  thou  that  repliest  against  God  ? 
Shall  the  thing  formed  say  unto  him  that  formed  it,  Why 
hast  thou  made  me  thus  ?  Hath  not  the  potter  power 
over  the  clay,  of  the  same  lump  to  make  one  vessel  unto 
honour,  and  another  unto  dishonour?  What  if  Grod, 
willing  to  shew  His  wrath,  and  to  make  His  power  known, 
endured  with  much  long-suffering  the  vessels  of  wrath 
fitted  to  destruction.  And  that  He  might  make  known 
the  riches  of  His  glory  on  the  vessels  of  mercy,  which  He 
had  afore  prepared  unto  glory.' 

Here  it  is  expressly  said  that  some  persons  are  from 
all  eternity  objects  respectively  of  the  Divine  love  and 
the  Divine  wrath,  which  love  and  which  wrath  involve 
respectively  eternal  'glory,'  and  'destruction'  (v.  22,  23). 
All  the  attempts  to  explain  this  passage  as  meaning  only 
that  some  persons  are  predestined  to  higher  and  others 
to  lower  means  of  grace,  appear  to  violate  its  plain  and 
natural  meaning.  It  is  not  indeed  necessary  to  suppose 
that  the  contrast  between  Jacob  and  Esau,  as  individual 


Note  VIII.  353 


men,  is  that  of  one  finally  saved  to  another  finally  con 
demned;  but  it  is  no  less  clear  that  the  Apostle  uses  them 
as  types  of  these  two  respective  classes,  and  that  the 
argument  of  the  passage  has  reference  to  man's  eternal 
end,  good  or  bad ;  for  '  glory  '  and  '  destruction  '  cannot 
mean  only  higher  and  lower  spiritual  advantages. 

Archbishop  Whately  indeed  raises  an  ingenious  objec 
tion  to  the  predestinarian  interpretation  of  the  image  of 
the  potter  and  the  clay,  and  remarks,  '  We  are  in  His 
hands,  say  these  predestinarians,  as  clay  in  the  potters', 
"  who  hath  power  of  the  same  lump  to  make  one  vessel  to 
honour  and  another  to  dishonour,"  not  observing  in  their 
party  eagerness  to  seize  an  easy  apparent  confirmation  of 
their  system,  that  this  similitude,  as  far  as  it  goes,  rather 
makes  against  them,  since  the  potter  never  makes  any 
vessel  for  the  express  purpose  of  being  broken  and  destroyed. 
This  comparison  accordingly  agrees  much  better  with  the 
view  here  taken.  The  potter  according  to  his  arbitrary 
choice  makes  of  the  same  lump  one  vessel  to  honour  and 
another  to  dishonour — i.e.  some  to  nobler  and  others  to 
meaner  uses,  but  all  to  some  use  ;  none  with  a  design 
that  it  should  be  cast  away  and  dashed  in  pieces.  Even 
so  the  Almighty,  of  His  own  arbitrary  choice,  causes  some 
to  be  born  to  wealth  or  rank,  others  to  poverty  or 
obscurity,  some  in  a  heathen,  and  others  in  a  Christian 
country  ;  the  advantages  and  privileges  bestowed  on  each 
are  various.' — Essay  3,  On  Election.  But  to  extract  thus 
an  argument  from  the  general  nature  of  an  image  used  in 
Scripture  is  to  forget  that  Scripture,  in  making  use  of 
images,  only  adopts  them  in  such  respects  as  it  uses  them, 
such  respects  as  answer  the  particular  purpose  in  hand  ; 
it  does  not  necessarily  adopt  the  whole  image.  What  we 
have  to  do  with,  then,  is  not  the  image  itself,  but  the 
image  as  used  by  Scripture.  Now,  it  is  true  that  a  potter 
never  makes  a  vessel  for  destruction  ;  but  some  vessels  are 
certainly  in  this  passage  spoken  of  as  '  fitted  to  destruc 
tion,'  others  as  < prepared  unto  glory;'  of  which  destruc 
tion  and  glory  the  cause  is  plainly  put  further  back  than 
their  own  personal  conduct,— viz.  in  a  certain  Divire  love 

A  A 


354  Note  VIII. 


and  wrath,  before  either  side  had  done  any  actual  good  or 
evil, — '  The  children  being  not  yet  born,  neither  having 
done  any  good  or  evil,  it  is  written,  Jacob  have  I  loved, 
but  Esau  have  I  hated.'  And  were  a  predestination  to 
privileges  all  that  was  meant  by  the  passage — that  some 
are  born  to  wealth  or  rank,  others  to  poverty  or  obscurity, 
some  in  a  heathen  and  others  in  a  Christian  country,  what 
ground  would  there  be  for  raising  the  objection  ?  '  Thou 
wilt  say  then  unto  me,  Why  doth  He  yet  find  fault,  for 
who  hath  resisted  His  will  ?  '  It  is  evident  that  this  is  a 
complaint  against  the  Divine  justice,  or  an  objection  to 
the  Apostle's  doctrine  just  before  laid  down,  on  the  ground 
that  it  contradicts  that  Divine  attribute.  But  how  could 
a  mere  inequality  in  the  dispensing  of  religious  privileges 
provoke  such  a  charge,  except  from  a  positive  infidel? 
Inequality  is  a  plain  feet  of  God's  visible  providence,  and 
could  never  support  a  charge  of  injustice,  except  the 
objector  were  willing  to  go  the  further  step  of  denying  a 
Divine  creation  and  providence  altogether  on  account  of 
this  fact.  The  objector  here  plainly  means  to  say  this : 
How  can  it  be  just  that  a  man  should  be  the  object  of 
Divine  wrath  before  he  has  done  anything  to  deserve  it  ? 
That  he  should  be  incapacitated  for  obtaining  the  qualifi 
cations  necessary  for  eternal  life,  and  then  blamed  because 
he  has  not  got  them  ?  '  Why  doth  he  find  fault,  for  who 
hath  resisted  His  will  ? '  Why  does  God  condemn  the 
sinner,  when  His  own  arbitrary  will  has  incapacitated  him 
for  being  anything  else  but  a  sinner  ? 

At  the  same  time  I  am  ready  to  admit,  that  there  is 
ground  for  saying  that  a  milder  sense  of  reprobation  does 
come  in,  in  this  passage,  along  with  the  stronger  one ;  and 
that  language  is  used  expressive  rather  of  the  modified 
than  of  the  extreme  doctrine  of  predestination.  It 
is  at  any  rate  doubtful  whether  '  honour '  and  '  dishonour ' 
do  not  mean  higher  and  inferior  good  rather  than  positive 
good  and  evil.  The  use  of  the  words  in  2  Tim.  ii.  20. — 
'  In  a  great  house  there  are  not  only  vessels  of  gold  and 
silver,  but  also  of  wood  and  earth,  and  some  to  honour 
and  some  to  dishonour  ' — would  seem  to  attach  the  former 


Note  VIII.  355 


meaning  to  them.  And  if  so,  so  far  as  this  language  goes, 
the  Apostle  expresses  a  modified  doctrine  of  predestination 
rather  than  an  extreme  one,  or  predestination  to  unequal 
advantages,  rather  than  to  positive  good  and  evil.  But 
whether  this  is  so  or  not,  such  a  sense  of  predestination 
only  obtains  so  far  as  the  language  which  expresses  it  goes. 
The  stronger  sense  of  predestination,  as  predestination  to 
positive  good  and  evil,  is  the  main  and  pervading  one  in 
the  passage;  and  this  sense  must  not  be  lost  sight  of 
because  there  may  be  a  milder  sense  too  in  which  the  doc 
trine  is  asserted.  It  is  characteristic  of  S.  Paul  to  slide 
from  one  meaning  to  another  ;  and  just  as  a  counter  doc 
trine  altogether  to  that  of  predestination  is  put  forth  in 
other  passages  of  Scripture,  so  the  same  passage  may  be 
more  or  less  contradictory,  and  contain  its  own  balance. 
But  if  the  milder  meaning  of  predestination  is  there, 
it  must  not  be  thought  that  the  stronger  meaning  is 
therefore  not  there  too;  or  supposed  that  all  that  this 
passage  means  is  a  predestination  to  unequal  privileges 
and  advantages. 

There  is  another  mode  of  interpreting  predestination  in 
Scripture,  so  as  to  make  the  doctrine  agree  with  the  truth 
of  freewill;  viz.  that  of  allowing  predestination  to  be  to 
eternal  salvation  itself,  but  with  the  qualification  that  it  is 
caused  by  the  Divine  foresight  of  the  future  good  life  of 
the  individual.  But  this  qualification  is  opposed  to  the 
plain  meaning  of  those  passages  of  Scripture  in  which  this 
doctrine  is  set  forth.  These  passages  obviously  represent 
predestination  as  a  predestination  of  the  individual  to  a 
good  life,  as  well  as  to  the  reward  of  one,  to  the  means  as 
well  as  to  the  end ;  thus  making  a  good  life  the  effect  of 
predestination,  and  not  the  cause  or  reason  of  it.  '  He  hath 
chosen  us  before  the  foundation  of  the  world  that  we 
should  be  holy  '....•'  predestinated  us  to  be  conformed 
to  the  image  of  His  Son.' 

But  the  ninth  chapter  of  Romans,  just  quoted,  supplies 
the  most  decisive  answer  to  this  qualification  of  the  doc 
trine  of  predestination  ;  it  being  expressly  said  there  that 
the  purpose  of  Grod  according  to  election  is  antecedent  to 

AA2 


356  Note  VIII. 


any  differences  of  life  and  conduct  between  one  man  and 
another  ;  that  it  is  formed  while  the  children  are  yet 
unborn,  and  have  done  neither  good  nor  evil ;  that  it  is 
not  of  works,  but  of  Him  that  calleth ;  and  that  it  is  not 
of  him  that  willeth  or  of  him  that  runneth,  but  of  (rod 
that  showeth  mercy;  that  it  is  clay  of  the,  same  lump 
of  which  some  vessels  are  made  to  honour,  and  others  to 
dishonour. 

Jackson,  among  other  commentators,  interprets  the 
predestination  maintained  in  this  passage  in  this  way,  viz. 
as  predestination  in  consequence  of  foreseen  good  works. 
But  in  thus  interpreting  it  he  endeavours  at  the  same  time 
by  an  argument  more  ingenious  than  substantial,  to  ex 
plain  his  own  interpretation  as  not  being  such  an  inter 
pretation  as  this ;  and  tries  to  show  that  he  does  not  base 
predestination  upon  foreseen  good  works.  He  says,  predes 
tination  is  in  consequence  not  of  any  foreseen  works  of 
the  law,  but  the  foreseen  work  of  faith ;  which  work  of 
faith  being  a  renunciation  of  the  works  of  the  law  cannot 
tself  be  called  a  work.  He  interprets  the  Apostle's  asser 
tion  that  election  is  not  in  consequence  of  any  '  willing  or 
running '  of  the  man  himself,  in  this  way,  viz.  that  this 
expression  applies  to  works  of  the  Jewish  law  only,  and  not 
to  works  of  faith  ;  to  the  self-willed  and  self-dependent 
kind  of  good  works,  which  are  not  really  good  as  not  pro 
ceeding  from  a  spiritual  state  of  mind ;  not  to  the  true 
spiritual  temper.  The  work  of  faith,  he  says,  is  '  an  opus 
quo  renunciamus,  the  formal  act  by  which  all  works  must 
be  renounced,'  and  so  not  properly  a  work  :  'fides  justificat 
non  qua  opus  sed  relative — is  essentially  included  in  the 
act  of  justification ;  not  included  in  the  universality  of 
works,  which  are  excluded  from  justification.'  And  the 
'  fallacy '  of  calling  such  an  act  a  work  he  expresses  thus  : 
6  If  such  divines  as  urge  it  most  should  come  into  our  per- 
vices  and  apply  it  to  matters  there  discussed,  thus — 

'  Omne  visibile  est  coloratum  : 
Omnis  color  est  visibilis  :  ergo 
Omnis  color  est  coloratus, — 

I  hope  a  meaner  artist  than  this  nursery  (God  be  praised  !) 


Note  VIII.  357 


hath  any,  would  quickly  cut  off  their  progress  with  a  dis 
tinction  of  visibile  ut  quod,  et  visibile  ut  quo,  and  show 
that  the  major,  though  universally  true  of  every  subject  or 
body  that  may  be  seen,  did  not  nor  could  not  comprehend 
colour  by  which  they  are  made  visible,  and  by  whose 
formal  act  they  are  denominated  colorata.  The  fallacy  of 
the  former  objection  drawn  into  mood  and  figure  is  the 
same,  but  more  apparent. 

'  Every  will  or  work  of  man  must  be  utterly  renounced 
from  the  act  of  justification  or  conversion  : 

'  But  to  deny  ourselves  and  renounce  all  works  is  a  work : 

'  Ergo,  This  work  must  be  excluded  from  the  suit  of 
mercy,  as  no  way  available.' — Vol.  ix.  p.  442. 

But  such  a  distinction  as  this  applied  to  works  as  a 
ground  of  the  Divine  election  is  inadmissible.  The  work  of 
faith  is  a  work ;  not  in  such  an  ambiguous  sense  as  that  in 
which  colour  is  a  visible  thing,  but  substantially  and  cor 
rectly.  It  is  a  humble,  self-renouncing  act.  It  is  the 
fundamental  act  of  the  Christian  life.  If  election,  then,  is 
in  consequence  of  this  foreseen  work  of  faith,  it  is  in  con 
sequence  of  good  works,  which  it  is  plainly  said  by  S.  Paul 
not  to  be. 

Jackson  borrows  his  explanation  from  Origen,  who  im 
plies  the  same  distinction  between  'carnal  works'  and 
other  works,  as  the  ground  of  Jacob's  election.  '  Quod  si 
vel  Isaac  vel  Jacob  pro  his  meritis  electi  fuissent  a  Deo 
quce  in  came  positi  acquisierant,  et  per  opera  carnis 
justificari  meruissent,  posset  utique  meriti  eorum  gratia  ad 
posteritatem  carnis  quoque  pertinere.  Nunc  vero  cum 
electio  eorum  non  ex  operibus  facta  sit,  sed  ex  proposito 
Dei,  et  ex  vocantis  arbitrio,  promissionum  gratia  non  in 
filiis  carnis  impletur,  sed  in  filiis  Dei.'— In  Rom.  ix.  11. 
vol.  iv.  p.  613.  Thus  Jackson :  '  Had  not  this  purpose  of 
God  been  revealed  before  the  children  had  been  born, 
Jacob's  posterity  would  have  boasted  that  either  their  father 
Jacob  or  his  mother  Eebecca  had  better  observed  those 
rites  and  customs  wherein  they  placed  righteousness  than 
Isaac  or  Esau  had  done ;  and  that  God  upon  these  motives 
had  bestowed  the  birthright  or  blessing  upon  Jacob  before 


358  Note  VIII. 

Esau.' — Vol.  ix.  p.  436.  There  is  considerable  confusion 
here,  and  Origen  seems  to  slide  from  works  not  carnal  to 
no  works  at  all  as  the  ground  of  election  ;  though  the 
former  idea  in  the  main  prevails.  Origen's  main  view  of 
the  ground  of  election  is  foreseen  good  character. — Vol.  iv. 
p.  616. 

Jackson  explains  the  similitude  of  the  potter  and  the 
clay  on  the  same  principle :  '  That  it  was  marred  in  the 
first  making  was  the  fault  of  the  clay.' — Vol.  ix.  p.  462. 
But  is  this  said  in  Scripture  ?  On  the  contrary,  it  is  said 
that  all  the  clay  was  of  the  same  lump,  and  therefore  the 
difference  of  the  Divine  design  did  not  arise  from  any  dif 
ference  in  the  clay.  Origen  makes  in  the  same  way  a 
difference  in  the  clay,  though  the  very  phrase  eadem 
massa,  which  he  accepts,  as  he  is  obliged  to  do,  from  the 
Apostle,  refutes  it.  '  Videns  Deus  puritatern  ejus,  et 
potestatem  habens  ex  eadem  massa  facere  aliud  vas  ad 
honorem  aliud  ad  contumeliam,  Jacob  quidem  qui  emun- 
daverat  seipsum  fecit  vas  ad  honorem ;  Esau  vero  eujus 
an  imam  non  ita  pur  am  nee  ita  simplicein  videbat,  ex 
eadem  massa  fecit  ad  contumeliam.' — In  Rom.  ix.  vol. 
iv.  p.  616. 

With  the  explanation  of  foreseen  goodness,  however,  as 
the  ground  of  election,  Jackson  couples  the  other  mode  of 
reconciling  the  passage  with  freewill ;  viz.  that  of  election 
to  means  and  opportunities.  '  The  Apostle  imagineth 
such  a  potter  as  the  wise  man  did,  that  knows  a  reason 
why  he  makes  one  vessel  of  this  fashion,  another  of  that, 
why  he  appoints  this  to  a  base  use,  that  to  a  better.1 — 
P.  462. 

Hooker's  explanation  of  the  passage  (given  in  a  recently 
discovered  and  edited  writing,  made  an  appendix  to  Ec 
clesiastical  Polity,  bk.  v.)  makes,  like  Origen's  and  Jack 
son's,  a  difference  in  the  clay,  though  he  will  not  at  the 
same  time  allow  that  the  Divine  Justice  requires  this 
reason  for  its  own  defence.  '  Suppose  (which  is  yet  false) 
that  there  were  nothing  in  it,  but  only  so  Grod  will  have 
it, — suppose  Grod  did  harden  and  soften,  choose  and  cast 
off,  make  honourable  and  detestable,  whom  Himself  will, 


Note  VIII.  359 


and  that  without  any  cause  moving  Him  one  way  or  other, 
— are  we  not  all  in  His  hands  as  clay  ?  If  thus  God  did 
deal,  what  injury  were  it  ?  How  much  less  now,  when  they 
on  whom  His  severity  worketh  are  not  found  like  the  day 
without  form,  as  apt  to  receive  the  best  shape  as  any  other, 
but  are  in  themselves  and  by  their  own  disposition 
fashioned  for  destruction  and  for  wrath.' — Keble's  Ed.  vol. 
ii.  p.  748.  Now,  of  this  explanation  the  first  part  un 
doubtedly  adheres  to  the  natural  meaning  of  the  passage 
in  S.  Paul  more  faithfully  than  the  latter,  which  diverges 
from  it ;  mankind  being  plainly  represented  by  S.  Paul  as 
being  like  clay  of  the  same  lump,  previous  to  election,  and 
any  difference  of  disposition  in  them,  in  this  previous  state, 
so  far  from  being  asserted,  being  expressly  denied.  Indeed, 
as  Jansen  says,  if  S.  Paul  meant  foreseen  goodness  as  the 
ground  of  election,  he  would  not  have  silenced  the  com- 
plainer  by  a  reference  to  God's  inscrutable  will,  but  would 
have  given  this  simple  and  intelligible  answer  to  his 
objection.  But  non  isto  nititur  cardine. — De  Graf. 
Christi^  p.  347. 

On  the  whole,  that  which  is  commonly  called  the  Cal- 
vinistic  sense,  appears  to  be  the  natural  sense  of  these 
passages  of  Scripture ;  and  the  Calvin istic  use  of  them 
should  be  met,  not  by  denying  this  sense,  and  explaining 
away  the  natural  meaning  of  the  language,  but  by  opposing 
to  them  other  passages  of  Scripture  which  speak  equally 
plainly  of  man's  freewill.  I  may  add,  that  perhaps  more 
has  been  made  by  many  of  the  text  in  S.  James  than  it 
will  exactly  bear,  and  that,  though  proving  difficulty,  this 
text  does  not  prove  so  much  difficulty  in  those,  parts  of 
S.  Paul's  Epistles  as  many  would  maintain.  These  epistles 
were  certainly  addressed  to  the  whole  Church,  and  were 
meant  to  be  understood  by  men  of  average  intelligence 
who  applied  their  attention  properly.  Their  predestinarian 
meaning  in  parts  is,  on  the  whole,  clear  and  decided ;  and 
the  reason  why  their  meaning  is  thought  by  many  to  be  so 
very  obscure  and  difficult  to  get  at,  is  that  they  will  not 
acknowledge  this  predestinarian  meaning  to  be  the  true 
ojie.  These  interpreters  create  difficulties  for  themselves 


360  Note  IX. 


by  rejecting  the  natural  meaning  of  passages,  and  then  lay 
the  difficulty  on  the  passages. 

NOTE  IX.  p.  46. 

THE  first  work  of  Pelagius  referred  to  in  the  controversy, 
is  his  letter  to  Paulinus,  which  appears  to  have  been 
written  about  A.D.  405,  during  his  stay  at  Rome. — Benedic 
tine  Editors  Preface^  c.  1.  But  Augustine's  doctrinal 
bias  had  clearly  asserted  itself  some  years  before,  in  the 
book  De  Diversis  Qucestionibus  ad  Simplicianum,  which 
came  out  A.D.  397  ;  and  had  evidently  commenced  as  early 
as  the  book  De  Libero  Arbitrio,  which  he  began  to  write 
A.D.  388.  In  his  Retractations  ( 1.  1.  c.  9.)  he  refers  to  this 
early  treatise,  with  which  the  Pelagians  taunted  him  as 
contradicting  his  later  ones  on  the  subject  of  freewill,  and 
shows  that,  though  not  consistently  brought  out,  the  germ 
of  his  ultimate  system  was  to  be  found  in  parts  of  that 
treatise.  He  refers  particularly  to  the  scheme  of  the  two 
kinds  of  Divine  gifts  laid  down  in  1.  2.  cc.  18,  19 ;  accord 
ing  to  which  both  those  which  did  and  those  which  did  not 
admit  of  a  bad  use  (virtutes  and  potentice]  were  alike  gifts 
of  God.  The  explanation  which  he  gives  in  the  Retracta 
tions  of  some  of  the  statements  favourable  to  freewill  in 
the  other  treatise  may  be  far-fetched ;  but  such  a  view  as 
this  is  evidently  agreeable  to  his  later  doctrine.  Nor  is 
Augustine  at  all  a  pertinacious  interpreter  of  his  early 
writings  in  the  sense  of  his  later  ones.  Consistency  has 
less  charm  for  him  than  development  as  a  writer  and 
thinker ;  and  he  dwells  on  the  changes  he  has  gone  through 
with  the  satisfaction  of  one  who  believes  his  later  notions 
to  be  a  great  improvement  in  depth  and  acuteness  upon 
his  earlier  ones. 

To  these  two  earlier  treatises  may  be  added  the  Confes 
sions,  written  A.D.  400.  A  celebrated  dictum  in  this  book 
— da  quod  jubes,  et  jube  quod  vis — was  the  first  apparent 
stimulus  to  the  speculations  of  Pelagius,  whom  it  greatly 
irritated.  'Pelagius  ferre  non  potuit,  et  contradicens 
aliquanto  commotius,  pene  cum  illo  qui  ilia  commemora- 


Note  X.  361 


verat  litigavit.'— De  Dono  Perseveranticv,  n.  53.  Neander 
says  :  '  Since  Augustine  had  completed  his  doctrinal  system 
on  this  particular  side  more  than  ten  years  before  the  opin 
ions  of  Pelagius  excited  any  public  controversy,  it  is  clear 
that  opposition  to  Pelagius  could  not  have  influenced  him 
in  forming  it.  With  more  propriety  may  it  be  said  that 
opposition  to  such  doctrines  as  those  of  Augustine,  or  to 
the  practical  consequences  which,  through  misconstruction 
or  abuse,  were  derived  from  such  doctrines,  had  no  small 
share  in  leading  Pelagius  to  form  such  a  system  as  he  did." 
—Church  History,  vol.  iv.  p.  312. 

NOTE  X.  p.  52. 

SUNT  alii  [Pelagiani]  tarn  validis  testimoniis  non  audentes 
resistere  ;  ideoque  dant  Deo  primitias  extrinsecas  gratia'  et 
fidei,  ac  bonorum  similium,  sed  hominibus  gratiam  ipsam 
et  fidem  cum  caeteris  bonis  hujusmodi.  Dicunt  enim  Deum 
semper  praevenire  pulsando,  et  excitando  ad  gratiam,  fidem, 
etad  bona  similia,  et  hominem  subsequi  aperiendo  et  con- 
sentiendo,  et  hoc  ex  propriis  viribus  per  seipsum,  juxta  illud 
Apoc.  3  :  '  Ecce  sto  ad  ostium,  et  pulso  :  si  quis  audierit 
vocem  meam,  et  aperuerit  mihi  januam,  introibo  ad  ilium, 
et  coenabo  cum  illo,  et  ipse  mecum.'  Hi  autem  faciunt 
Deum  suse  gratiae  publicum  venditorem,  hominesque  emp- 
tores.  Dicunt  enim  eum  sicut  mercatorem  pauperculum 
clamare,  et  pulsare  ad  januas,  et  ad  ostia  singulorum ; 
aperienti  vero  pro  sua  apertione  gratiam  suam  dare,  quod 
tamen  verius  commutare,  sen  vendere  diceretur.  Faciunt 
quoque  Deum  scriptorem  pauperculum  et  conductitium 
suam  operam  publicantem,  et  pro  pretio  parvulo,  pro 
apertione  et  ccena,  aperientium  nomina  in  libro  vitae  scri- 
bentem ;  sicque  gratia  ex  praecedentibus  operibus  nostris 
erit.  .  .  .  Homo  non  potest  aperire  nee  consentire  in 
talibus  ex  seipso,  sed  voluntate  Divina,  quod  et  probant 
auctoritates  superius  allegata?.  Nemo  potest  venire  ad 
me,  nisi  Pater  meus  traxerit  ilium.  Secundum  istos 
tamen  homo  licet  pulsatus  a  Deo,  non  habens  adhuc  pa- 
trem,  aperiendo  pulsanti,  verius  traheret  ad  se  Patrem.  .  . 


;62  Note  X. 


Et  licet  sic  pulsat  nihil  dat  nobis,  sed  nos  aperientes 
damus  sibi  consensum,  contra  illud  Apostoli,  Quis  prior 
dedit  illi,  et  retribuetur  ei  ?  Itane  hsec  positio  tribuit 
nobis  quod  melius  est  et  majus,  Deo  vero  quod  deterius 
est  et  minus :  quis  enim  dubitaverit  aperire  melius  et 
utilius  nobis  esse  quam  pulsare,  cum  pulsare  sine  aper- 
tione,  non  prosit  sed  obsit. — Bradwardine,  De  Causa 
Dei,l.  1.  c.  38. 

Sentiebant  ergo  Pelagiani  uno  omnes  consensu,  tantas 
esse  vires  in  naturali  libertate,  bonique  et  mali  possibilitate 
constitutas,  ut  qusecunque  tandem  a  rebus  sive  extrinsecus 
irruentibus,  sive  intrinsecus  se  commoventibus,  vel  cogita- 
tiones  phantasiseque  moverentur  vel  animi  desideria  mo- 
tusque  cierentur,  quicquid  tandem  sive  homines,  sive 
Angeli,  sive  Dsemones,  adeoque  Spiritus  ipse  sanctus 
suaderet,  et  suggereret,  quicunque  vel  pietatis  vel  iniqui- 
tatis  motus  inciderent,  quibuscunque  passionum  bonarum 
auris  animus  propelleretur,  vel  malarum  fluctibus  procel- 
lisque  turbaretur,  nihil  de  suo  imperii  principatu  domina 
ilia  libertas  amitteret ;  sed  plenissima  discernendi  potes- 
tate  penes  vim  rationis  ac  voluntatis  permanente,  sola 
fieret  ad  malum  bonumque  suasio  ac  provocatio ;  nutus 
vero  probandi  vel  improbandi,  utendi  et  repellendi,  in  ilia 
naturalis  indifferentise  libertate  ac  naturali  possibilitate 
persist eret. — Jansen,  De  Hcer.  Pel.  1.  2.  c.  3. 

Nihil  verius  de  tali  possibilitate  divino  adjutorio 
munita  dici  potuit,  quam  id  quod  Pelagius  dixit :  '  Quod 
possumus  omne  bonum  facere,  dicere,  cogitare,  illius  est 
qui  hoc  posse  donavit,  qui  hoc  posse  adjuvat :  quod  vero 
bene  vel  agimus  vel  loquimur  vel  cogitamus  nostrum  est 
quia  ha3c  omnia  vertere  in  malum  possumus.'  Quibus 
verbis  adjutorium  possibilitatis  explicuit.  Vigilantissime 
quippe  et  perspicacissime  vidit  (quod  ego  saepius  supra 
modum  admiratus  sum  Scholasticos  eruditissimos  acutissi- 
mosque  viros  non  agnoscere)  quod  sicut  usus  cujuslibet 
facultatis  sive  oculi  externorumque  sensuum,  sive  facultatis 
progressive,  sive  intellectus,  sive  voluntatis,  noster  est,  hoc 
est,  ad  nostrse  voluntatis  indifferentem  flexum  et  nutum 
referri  debet,  non  ad  Deum,  quatenus  solam  facultatem 


Note  X.  363 


dedit;  ita  quoque  cujuslibet  adjutorii  concursus,  sive  natu- 
ralis  sive  gratuiti,  etiamsi  esset  tanta?  prastantia?  adjuto- 
rium  quantam  vel  angelica  cogitatio  comminisci  posset, 
imo  etiamsi  esset  vel  ipsa  essentia  Dei  per  moduin  speciei 
ad  sui  visionem,  vel  per  modum  gratias  ad  sui  amorem 
concurrentis,  similiter  prorsus  noster  sit ;  si  videlicet  sic 
solam  possibilitatem  adjuvet,  et  usus  ejus  et  non  usus  in 
libero  relinquatur  arbitrio. — Jansen,  De  Gratia  Christi, 
1.  2.  c.  9. 

Hanc  ergo  mentem  Pelagianorum  cum  prospectara 
haberet  Augustinus,  quod  quicquid  motuum  vel  Dens  vel 
Diabolus  in  voluntate  suscitaret,  isti  dominativa*  vohmtatis 
potestati  subderent,  non  fuit  sollicitus  iitrum  gratiam  Irgis 
atque  doctrinse,  sive  revelationem  sapientijv.  sive  cxemplum 
Christi,  sive  remissionem  peccatorum,  sive  habitus  bonos, 
sive  succensiones  ac  desideria  volimtatis  assererent ;  sod 
generalissime  prophanum  eorum  dogma  quo  solum  possi 
bilitatem  adjuvari  gratia  censebant,  ubicunque  vel  qualem- 
cunque  ponerent  gratiam,  velut  exploratum  errorem 
Scripturisque  contrarium  jugulat.  .  .  .  Quamvis  enim  in 
gratiam  legis  plerumque  magis  propendere  videretur,  non 
satis  tamen  certum  erat  Augustino  quam  gratiam  tarn 
vario  magnificorum  verborum  strepitu  Pelagius  tune  de- 
fenderet,  cum  nunc  legem,  mine  doctrinam,  mine  sapiential 
revelationem,  nunc  exemplum  Christi,  mine  peccati  remis 
sionem,  nunc  voluntatum  succensionem,  nunc  desideria 
a  Deo  suscitata  celebraret.  Fatetur  hanc  suam  incerti- 
tudinem  passim  toto  libro  Augustinus.  .  .  .  Itaque  ut 
omnis  erroribus  istis  latebra  clauderetur,  sub  quatibet,  et 
qualilibet,  et  ubicumque  constituta  gratia  sua  in  eos  tela 
dirigit.  .  .  .  Nimirum  quia  utrobique  Augustinus  quam- 
libet,  qualemlibet,  ubilibet  constitutam  gratiam  quisque 
tueatur,  si  solam  possibilitatem  voluntatis  et  actioms 
adjuvet,  eum  sanse  et  Apostolicaa  et  Evangelic®  doctrinae 
violataB  reum  facit.— Jansen,  De  Gratia  Christi,  1.  2.  c.  10. 


364  Note  XL 


NOTE  XL  p.  54. 

AUGUSTINE'S  view  on  this  subject  is  comprehended  under 
the  following  heads  : — 

1.  No  one  of  the  human  race  can  be  without  sin  abso 
lutely  or  from  the  first,  all  being  born  in  sin.  '  Qui  omnino 
nullum  peccatum  habuerit,  habiturusve    sit,  prorsus  nisi 
unum  Mediatorem  Dei  et  hominum  Jesum  Christum,  nul 
lum  vel  esse  vel  fuisse  vel  futurum  esse  certissimum  est.' 
— De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  2.  n.  34.     '  Non  legitur 
sine  peccato  esse  nisi  Filius  hominis.' — De  Perfect.  Just. 
n.  29.     See  too  De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  1.  n.  56,  57. 

2.  Though  all  men  are  in  sin  to  begin  with,  there  is 
the  possibility  of  attaining  to  a  sinless  state  in  this  life ; 
but  this  possibility  is  through  the  Divine  grace  or  power, 
and  by  a  miraculous  exertion  of  that  power.     '  Et  ideo 
ejus  perfectionem  etiam  in  hac  vita  esse  possibilem,  negare 
non  possumus,  quia  omnia  possibilia   sunt  Deo,  sive  quae 
faoit   sola  sua  voluntate,  sive  quae  cooperantibus  creaturae 
suse  voluntatibus  a  se  fieri  posse   constituit.     Ac  per  hoc 
quicquid  eorum  non  facit,  sine  exemplo  est  quidem  in  ejus 
operibus  factis  ;  sed  apud  Deum  et  in  ejus  virtute  habet 
causam   qua  fieri  possit,  et  in  ejus   sapientia  quare  non 
factum  sit.' — De  Spiritu  et  Liter 'a,  n.  7.     '  Ecce  quemad- 
modum  sine  exernplo  est  in  hominibus  perfecta  justitia,  et 
tamen  impossibilis  non  est.     Fieret  enim  si  tanta  voluntas 
adhiberetur  quanta  sufficit  tantae  rei.     Esset  autem  tanta, 
si  et  nihil  eorum  quse  pertinent  ad  justitiamnos  lateret,  et 
ea  sic  delectarent  animum,  ut  quicquid  aliud  voluptatis 
dolorisve  impedit,  delectatio  ilia  superaret :  quod  ut  non 
sit,  non  ad  impossibilitatem,  sed  ad  judicium  Dei  pertinet.' 
— Ibid.  n.  63.     '  Sed  inveniant  isti,  si  possunt,  aliquem 
sub  onere  corruptionis  hujus  viventem,  cui  jam  non  habeat 

Deus   quod   ignoscat Sane   quemquam   talem,    si 

testimonia  ilia  divina  competenter  accipiant,  prorsus  inve- 
nire  non  possunt ;  nullo  modo  tamen  dicendum,  Deo  deesse 
possibilitatem,  qua  voluntas  sic  adjuvetur  humana,  ut  non 
solum  justitia  ista  quae  ex  fide  est,  omni  ex  parte  modo 


Note  XL  365 


perficiatur  in  homine,  verum  etiam  ilia  secundiim  quam 
postea  in  seternum  in  ipsa  ejus  contemplatione  vivendum 
est.  Quandoquidem,  si  nunc  velit  in  quoquam  etiam  lioc 
corruptibili  induere  incorruptionem,  atque  hie  inter 
homines  morituros  eum  jubere  vivere  minime  moritunim, 
ut  tota  penitus  vetustate  consumpta  nulla  lex  in  membris 
ejus  repugnet  legi  mentis,  Deumque  ubique  pra^sentem 
ita  cognoscat,  sicut  sancti  postea  cognituri  sunt ;  quis 
demum  audeat  affirmare,  non  posse  ?  Sed  quare  non  faciat 
qua3runt  homines,  nee  qui  quaBrunt  se  attendant  esse 
homines.' — Ibid.  n.  66. 

3.  While  he  thus  admits  the  possibility,  he  denies  the 
fact  that  any  man  has  attained  to  a  sinless  state  in  this 
life  :  '  Si  autem  qua3ratur  utrum  sit,  esse  non  credo.  Magis 
enim  credo  Scripttirae  dicenti.  Ne  intres  in  judicium,' 
&c. — De  Pecc.  Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  2.  n.  8.  '  Hie  fortasse 
respondeas,  ista  qua3  commemoravi  facta  non  esse  et  fieri 
potuisse,  opera  esse  divina ;  ut  autem  sit  homo  sine  peccato, 
ad  opus  ipsius  hominis  pertinere,  idque  opus  esse  optimum, 
quo  fiat  plena  et  perfecta  et  ex  omni  parte  absoluta  justitia  : 
et  ideo  non  esse  credendum,  neminem  vel  fuisse,  vel  esse, 
vel  fore  in  hac  vita  qui  hoc  opus  impleverit,  si  ab  homine 
impleri  potest.  Sed  cogitare  debes  quam  vis  ad  homines  id 
agere  pertineat,  hoc  quoque  munus  esse  divinum,  atque 
ideo  non  dubitare  opus  esse  divinum.' — De  Spir.  et  Lit. 
n.  2.  '  Si  omnes  illos  sanctos  et  sanctas,  cum  hie  vixerunt, 
congregare  possemus,  et  interrogare  utrum  essent  sine  pec 
cato,  quid  fuisse  responsuros  putamus  ?  Utrum  hoc  quod 
iste  dicit,  an  quod  Joannes  Apostolus.  Rogo  vos,  quanta- 
Tibet  fuerit  in  hoc  corpore  excellentia  sanctitatis,  si  hoc 
interrogari  potuissent,  nonne  una  voce  clamassent,  ' 
diximus  quia  peccatum  non  habemus  nos  ipsos  decipimus, 
et  veritas  in  nobis  non  est."  An  illud  humilius  responde- 
rent  fortasse  quam  verius?  Sed  huicjam  placet,  et  recte 
placet,  "  laudem  humilitatis  in  parte  non  ponere  falsitatis. 
Itaque  hoc  si  verum  dicerent,  haberent  peccatum,  quod, 
humiliter  quia  faterentur  veritas  in  eis  esset :  si  autem 
hoc  mentirentur,  nihilominus  haberent  peccatum,  quia 
veritas  in  eis  non  esset,'— De  Nat.  et  Grot.  n.  42. 


366  Note  XL 


reserves,  however,  the  liberty  to  except  the  Virgin  Mary 
from  this  general  assertion :  '  De  qua,  propter  honorem 
Domini,  nullam  prorsus,  cum  de  peccatis  agitur,  haberi 
volo  qusestionem.' 

4.  To  assert  that  there  have  been  persons  in  this  life 
who  have  attained  to  the  sinless  state,  though  an  error,  is 
an  error  as  to  a  fact  rather  than  a  doctrine,  and  a  venial 
one.     '  Quinetiam   si  nemo  est  aut  fuit,   aut  erit,  quod 
magis  credo,  tali  puritate  perfectus  ;  et  tamen  esse  aut 
fuisse  aut  fore  defenditur  et  putatur,  non  multum  erratur, 
nee  perniciose  cum  quadam  quisque  benevolentia  fallitur : 
si  tamen  qui  hoc  putat  seipsum  talem  esse  non  putet,  nisi 
revera  ac  liquido  talem  se  esse  perspexerit.' — De  Spir.  et 
Lit.  n.  3.     '  Utrum  in  hoc  seculo  fuerit,  vel  sit,  vel  possit 
esse  aliquis  ita  juste  vivens,  ut  nullum  habeat  omnino 
peccatum,  potest  esse  aliqua   quaestio  inter  veros  piosque 
Christianos.     Posse  tamen  esse  certe  post  hanc  vitam  quis- 
quis  ambigit  desipit.     Sed  ego  nee   de  ista  vita  volo  con- 
tendere.      Quanquam    enim    mihi    non    videatur    aliter 
intelligendum  quod  scriptum  est,  "Non  justificabitur  in 
conspectu  tuo   omnis  vivens,"   et   siqua   similia:   utinam 
tamen  possit  ostendi  hsec  testimonia  melius  aliter  intelligi.' 
— De  Nat.  et  Grat.  n.  70. 

5.  Augustine  thinks  that  the  subjection  of  mankind  to 
the  law  of  sin  works   mysteriously  in  the  Divine  scheme 
for  good.     '  Idcirco  etiam  sanctos  et  tideles  suos  in  aliqui- 
bus  vitiis  tardius  sanat,  ut  in  his  eos  minus,  quam  implendse 
ex  omni  parte  justitise  sufficit,  delectet  bonum.  .  .  .  Nee 
in  eo  ipso  vult  nos  damnabiles  esse  sed  humiles.' — De  Pecc. 
Merit,  et  Remiss.  1.  2.  n.  33.     This  very  imperfection  is 
in  a  sense,  he  thinks,  as  leading  to  humility,  part  of  the 
perfection  of  human  virtue.     '  Ex  hoc  facturn  est,  virtutem 
quse  nunc  est  in  homine  justo,  perfectam  hactenus  nominari, 
ut  ad  ejus  perfectionem  pertineat  etiam  ipsius  imperfec- 
tionis  et  in  veritate  cognitio,  et  in  humilitate  confessio. 
Tune  enim  est  secundum  hanc  infirmitatem  pro  suo  modulo 
perfecta  ista  parva  justitia,  quando  etiam  quid  sibi  desit 
intelligit.     Ideoque  Apostolus  et  imperfectum  et  perfec- 
tum  se  dicit.' — Contra  Duas,  Ep.  1.  3.  n.  19.     'Deserit 


Note  XII.  367 


aliquando  Deus  ut  discas  superbus  non  esse.  Quidam 
traduntur  SatanaB  ut  discant  non  blasphernare.'-  -De  Nat. 
et  Grat.  n.  32.  Pelagius  ridicules  the  idea  that  peccatis 
peccata  curantur. 

NOTE  XII.  p.  79. 

ME.  COLERIDGE,  in  his  Aids  to  Reflection,  p.  272,  strongly 
objects  to  the  received  doctrine  of  original  sin,  as  involv 
ing  the  injustice  of  punishing  one  man  on  account  of  the 
sin  of  another  ;  in  the  place  of  which,  he  substitutes 
(p.  278)  a  rationale  of  original  sin,  in  which  he  rests  that 
doctrine,  upon  the  principle  of  cause  and  effect ;  asserting 
that  all  evil  action  implies  an  evil  in  the  will  as  the  cause 
of  it,  which  anterior  evil,  when  pushed  backward  and  back 
ward  indefinitely,  becomes  original  evil  in  the  will,  or 
original  sin.  '  Whatever  resists  and,  as  a  positive  power, 
opposes  this  (the  moral  law)  in  the  will,  is  evil.  But  an 
evil  in  the  will  is  an  evil  will ;  and  as  all  moral  evil  is  of 
the  will,  this  evil  will  must  have  its  source  in  the  will. 
And  thus  we  might  go  back  from  act  to  act,  from  evil  to 
evil,  ad  infinitum,  without  advancing  a  step.'  This  an 
terior  evil  in  the  will,  then,  regarded  as  mysterious,  inde 
pendent  of  time  and  intelligible  succession,  is,  he  argues, 
original  sin.  '  Let  the  evil  be  supposed  such  as  to  imply 
the  impossibility  of  an  individual  referring  it  to  any  par 
ticular  time  at  which  it  might  be  conceived  to  have  com 
menced,  or  to  any  period  of  his  existence  at  which  it  was 
not  existing.  Let  it  be  supposed,  in  short,  that  the  subject 
stands  in  no  relation  whatever  to  time,  can  neither  be 
called  in  time  or  out  of  time,  but  that  all  relations  to 
time  are  as  alien  and  heterogeneous  in  this  question  as  the 
relations  and  attributes  of  space  (north  or  south,  round  or 
square,  thick  or  thin)  are  to  our  affections  and  moral  feel 
ings.  Let  the  reader  suppose  this,  and  he  will  have  before 
him  the  precise  import  of  the  scriptural  doctrine  of  original 
si  YI 

"it  is  evident  that,  according  to  this  rationale,  Adam 
as  first  created  had  original  sin,  and  had  a  corrupt  nature 
as  truly  as  any  of  his  posterity.  For  the  first  sinful  act 


368  Note  XII. 


man  is  as  open  as  any  other  to  this  reasoning  from  effect 
to  cause,  from  an  evil  act  to  an  evil  will,  and  from  an  evil 
will  to  a  source  of  evil  in  the  will  or  original  sin :  so  that 
Adam's  sin  in  Paradise  was  the  effect  of  original  sin  in 
him,  or  a  corrupt  nature,  only  differing  from  other  sins  in 
being  the  first  effect.  '  The  corruption  of  my  will  may 
very  warrantably  be  spoken  of  as  a  consequence  of  Adam's 
fall,  even  as  my  birth  of  Adam's  existence ;  as  a  conse 
quence,  a  link  in  the  historic  chain  of  instances,  ivhereof 
Adam  was  the  first.  But  that  it  is  on  account  of  Adam, 
or  that  this  evil  principle  was  a  priori  inserted  or  infused 
into  my  will  by  the  will  of  another — which  is  indeed  a 
contradiction  in  terms,  my  will  in  such  a  case  being  no 
will, — this  is  nowhere  asserted  in  Scripture  explicitly  or 
by  implication.  It  belongs  to  the  very  essence  of  the 
doctrine,  that  in  respect  of  original  sin  every  man  is  the 
adequate  representative  of  all  men.  What  wonder,  then, 
that  where  no  outward  ground  of  preference  existed,  the 
choice  should  be  determined  by  outward  relation,  and 
that  the  first  in  time  should  be  taken  as  the  diagram  ? ' 
p.  283. 

Such  being  the  rationale  of  original  sin  substituted  by 
Mr.  Coleridge  for  the  received  doctrine  of  original  sin  as 
the  consequence  of  the  sin  of  Adam,  which  he  rejects  on 
the  ground  of  its  opposition  to  reason,  my  remark  is  this 
—that  T  cannot  think  it  philosophical  in  any  writer  to 
overthrow  a  whole  received  language,  professing  to  ex 
press  an  incomprehensible  mystery,  on  such  a  ground. 
Contradictory  language,  or  language  opposed  to  reason,  is 
the  only  one  in  which  mysteries  and  incomprehensible 
truths  can  be  expressed  ;  if  they  could  be  expressed  in 
consistent  language,  they  would  not  be  mysteries.  More 
over,  the  writer  professes  that  he  can  only  substitute  other 
inconsistent  language  for  that  which  he  rejects.  Mr.  Cole 
ridge  admits  the  absolute  inconsistency  of  an  original  evil 
in  the  will  with  the  will's  self-determination ;  yet,  because 
he  thinks  both  of  these  to  be  truths,  he  adopts  a  language 
which  contains  them  both,  as  the  only  mode  of  expressing 
'  an  acknowledged  mystery,  and  one  which,  by  the  nature  of 


Note  XII.  369 


the  subject,  must  ever  remain  such.'— p.  277.  What  is 
the  improvement,  then,  in  consistency,  in  his  language 
upon  the  received  language?  While,' on  the  other  hand, 
the  received  language,  by  attributing  the  fall  to  an  act  of 
freewill  only,  which  no  evil  in  the  will  preceded,  expresses 
an  important  truth  that  sin  is  not  fundamental  in,  but 
only  accidental  to,  human  nature ;  a,  truth  which  Mr. 
Coleridge's  language  of  original  evil  in  the  will,  so  fai 
from  expressing,  rather  contradicts. 

The  same  remark  may  be  made  on  Mr.  Coleridge's 
objection  to  the  received  doctrine  of  the  atonement  as  a 
satisfaction  for  sin ;  which  he  rejects  on  the  same  ground 
as  he  does  the  received  doctrine  of  original  sin,  viz.,  its 
opposition  to  our  natural  idea  of  justice.  '  Let  us  suppose, 
with  certain  divines,  that  the  varied  expressions  of  S.  Paul 
are  to  be  literally  interpreted :  ex.  gr.  that  sin  is,  or  in 
volves,  an  infinite  debt  (in  the  proper  and  law-court  sense 
of  the  word  debt), — a  debt  owing  by  us  to  the  vindictive 
justice  of  Grod  the  Father,  which  can  only  be  liquidated 
by  the  everlasting  misery  of  Adam  and  all  his  posterity,  01 
by  a  sum  of  suffering  equal  to  this.  Likewise,  that  God 
the  Father,  by  His  absolute  decree,  or  (as  some  divines 
teach)  through  the  necessity  of  His  unchangeable  justice, 
had  determined  to  exact  the  full  sum,  which  must  there 
fore  be  paid  either  by  ourselves  or  by  some  other  in  our 
own  name  and  behalf.  But,  besides  the  debt  which  all 
mankind  contracted,  in  and  through  Adam,  as  a  homo 
publicus,  even  as  a  nation  is  bound  by  the  acts  of  its  head 
or  its  plenipotentiary,  every  man  (say  these  divines)  is  an 
insolvent  debtor  on  his  own  score.  In  this  fearful  predi 
cament  the  Son  of  (rod  took  compassion  on  mankind,  and 
resolved  to  pay  the  debt  for  us,  and  to  satisfy  the  Divine 
justice  by  a  perfect  equivalent 

4  Now,  as  your  whole  theory  is  grounded  on  a  notion  of 
justice,  I  ask  you,  Is  this  justice  a  moral  attribute  ?^  But 
morality  commences  with,  and  begins  in  the  sacred  distinc 
tion  between  thing  and  person :  on  this  distinction  all  law 
human  and  divine  is  grounded;  consequently,  the  law  of 
justice.  If  you  attach  any  meaning  to  the  term  justice, 

B  B 


370  Note  XII. 


as  applied  to  Grod,  it  must  be  the  same  to  which  you  refer 
when  you  affirm  or  deny  it  of  any  other  personal  agent — 
save  only,  that  in  its  attribution  to  (rod  you  speak  of  it  as 
unmixed  and  perfect.  For  if  not,  what  do  you  mean  ?  And 
why  do  you  call  it  by  the  same  name  ?  I  may,  therefore, 
with  all  right  and  reason,  put  the  case  as  between  man 
and  man.  For  should  it  be  found  irreconcilable  with  the 
justice,  which  the  light  of  reason,  made  law  in  the  con 
science,  dictates  to  man,  how  much  more  must  it  be  in 
congruous  with  the  all-perfect  justice  of  Grod !  .  .  .  . 

'  A  sum  of  1 ,000£.  is  owing  from  James  to  Peter,  for 
which  James  has  given  a  bond.  He  is  insolvent,  and  the 
bond  is  on  the  point  of  being  put  in  suit  against  him,  to 
James's  utter  ruin.  At  this  moment  Matthew  steps  in, 
pays  Peter  the  thousand  pounds  and  discharges  the  bond. 
In  this  case,  no  man  would  hesitate  to  admit,  that  a  com 
plete  satisfaction  had  been  made  to  Peter.  Matthew's 
1,000£.  is  a  perfect  equivalent  for  the  sum  which  James 
was  bound  to  have  paid,  and  which  Peter  had  lent.  It  is 
the  same  thing :  and  this  is  altogether  a  question  of  things. 
Now,  instead  of  James's  being  indebted  to  Peter  for  a  sum 
of  money,  which  (he  having  become  insolvent)  Matthew 
pays  for  him,  we  will  put  the  case,  that  James  had  been 
guilty  of  the  basest  and  most  hard-hearted  ingratitude  to 
a  most  worthy  and  affectionate  mother,  who  had  not  only 
performed  all  the  duties  and  tender  offices  of  a  mother,  but 
whose  whole  heart  was  bound  up  in  this  her  only  child — 
who  had  foregone  all  the  pleasures  and  amusements  of  life 
in  watching  over  his  sickly  childhood,  had  sacrificed  her 
health  and  the  far  greater  part  of  her  resources  to  rescue 
him  from  the  consequences  of  his  follies  and  excesses  during 
his  youth  and  early  manhood,  and  to  procure  for  him  the 
means  of  his  present  rank  and  affluence — all  which  he  had 
repaid  by  neglect,  desertion,  and  open  profligacy.  Here  the 
mother  stands  in  the  relation  of  the  creditor :  and  here  too 
we  will  suppose  the  same  generous  friend  to  interfere,  and 
to  perform  with  the  greatest  tenderness  and  constancy  all 
those  duties  of  a  grateful  and  affectionate  son,  which  James 
ought  to  have  performed.  Will  this  satisfy  the  mother's 


Note  XII.  37 r 


claims  on  James,  or  entitle  him  to  her  esteem,  approba 
tion,  and  blessing?  Or  what  if  Matthew,  vicarious  son, 
should  at  length  address  her  in  words  to  this  purpose  : 
"  Now,  I  trust,  you  are  appeased,  and  will  be  henceforward 


oil 


reconciled  to  James.  I  have  satisfied  all  your  claims 
him.  I  have  paid  his  debt  in  full :  and  you  are  too  just 
to  require  the  same  debt  to  be  paid  twice  over.  You  will 
therefore  regard  him  with  the  same  complacency,  and 
receive  him  into  your  presence  with  the  same  love,  as  if 
there  had  been  no  difference  between  him  and  you.  For  I 
have  made  it  up"  What  other  reply  could  the  swelling 
heart  of  the  mother  dictate  than  this  ?  "0  misery  !  and 
is  it  possible  that  you  are  in  league  with  my  unnatural 
child  to  insult  me  ?  Must  not  the  very  necessity  of  your 
abandonment  of  your  proper  sphere  form  an  additional  evi 
dence  of  his  guilt  ?  Must  not  the  sense  of  your  goodness 
teach  me  more  fully  to  comprehend,  more  vividly  to  feel 
the  evil  in  him  ?  Must  not  the  contrast  of  your  merits 
magnify  his  demerit  in  his  mother's  eye,  and  at  once  recall 
and  embitter  the  conviction  of  the  canker-worm  in  his 
soul  ?  " 

'  If  indeed  by  the  force  of  Matthew's  example,  by  per 
suasion,  or  by  additional  and  more  mysterious  influences, 
or  by  an  inward  co-agency,  compatible  with  the  existence  of 
a  personal  will,  James  should  be  led  to  repent ;  if  through 
admiration  and  love  of  this  great  goodness  gradually  assimi 
lating  his  mind  to  the  mind  of  his  benefactor,  he  should 
in  his  own  person  become  a  grateful  and  dutiful  child— 
then  doubtless  the  mother  would  be  wholly  satisfied  !  But 
then  the  case  is  no  longer  a  question  of  things,  or  a  matter 
of  debt  payable  by  another.' — Aids  to  Reflection,  p.  322. 

But  is  not  Mr.  Coleridge  righting  the  air,  when  he 
objects,  on  these  grounds,  to  the  received  doctrine  of  the 
atonement  as  a  satisfaction  for  sin  ?  It  is  quite  true  that 
such  a  doctrine  is  opposed  to  our  natural  idea  of  justice,  as 
well  as  to  the  truth  of  common  reason,  that  one  person 
cannot  be  a  substitute  for  another  in  moral  action.  But 
who  does  not  acknowledge  this  contrariety  ?  Does  not  the 
most  devout  believer  profess  to  hold  this  doctrine  as  » 

BB  2 


372  Note  XI II. 


mystery,  and  not  as  a  truth  of  reason,  or  an  intelligible 
truth  ?  And  if  he  holds  it  as  such,  how  can  he  be  charged 
with  holding  anything  unreasonable  ?  How  can  an  asser 
tion  be  called  contrary  to  reason,  when  we  do  not  know 
what  its  meaning,  i.e.  the  thing  asserted  in  it,  is?  And 
how,  therefore,  can  the  maintaining  of  such  an  unknown 
truth  be  unreasonable  ?  The  Christian  only  believes  that 
there  is  a  truth  connected  with  this  subject,  which  in  the 
present  state  of  his  capacities  he  cannot  understand,  but 
which,  on  the  principle  of  accommodation,  is  expressed  in 
revelation  in  this  form,  as  that  mode  of  expressing  it  which 
is  practically  nearest  to  the  truth. 

NOTE  XIII.  p.  84. 

THE  connection  of  this  present  state  of  sin  and  suffering 
with  some  great  original  transgression  was  too  deeply  laid 
down  in  Scripture  to  offer  an  easy  explanation  to  the  Pela 
gians.  One  main  solution,  however,  of  such  passages  was 
given  ;  viz.  that  they  referred  to  a  connection  not  of  descent, 
but  example,  that  the  sin  of  Adam  was  fatal  as  an  imitated, 
not  as  a  transmitted  sin.  But  such  an  interpretation  ob 
viously  fell  short  of  the  meaning  of  Scripture,  nor  was  it 
improved  by  the  details  of  the  application.  The  Pelagian 
comment  on  the  great  passage  in  the  Epistle  to  the  Eomans, 
that  4  by  one  man  sin  entered  into  the  world,  and  death  by 
sin ;  and  so  death  passed  upon  all  men,  for  that  all  have 
sinned,'  opposed  to  the  received  doctrine  of  transmitted 
sin  ;  first,  the  expression  '  one  man,'  which  sufficed,  it  was 
said,  for  the  view  of  example,  whereas  both  the  man  and 
the  woman  were  necessary  for  transmission ; ]  secondly,  the 
distinction  that  '  death  passed  upon  all  men,'  not  sin  ;  and, 
thirdly,  the  ground  of  actual  sin,  as  distinguished  from 
original,  '  for  that  all  have  sinned.'  But  the  first  of  these 
objections  was  futile ;  the  second  was  overruled  by  other 
texts  of  Scripture  which  made  death  the  consequence  of 
sin ;  and  the  third  can  only  at  most  be  allowed  a  balanc 
ing,  not  a  disproving  weight.  The  Pelagian  was,  indeed, 

1  Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  47.  64. ;  1.  3.  c.  85. 


Note  XI I  I.  373 


the  better  construer  of  the  Greek  words,  which  our  trans 
lation  with  him  renders  into  'for  that,'  and  not  with 
S.  Augustine  into  '  in  whom.' l  But  though  this  particular 
clause,  thus  translated,  refers  to  a  ground  of  actual  sin, 
not  of  original,  or  sin  '  in  Adam,'  as  S.  Augustine  under 
stood  it;  the  reference  to  actual  sin  does  not  destroy  tlie 
previous  reference  to  original,  at  the  beginning  of  th-' 
verse.  The  previous  assertion  is  plain  and  decisive,  that 
'by  one  man  sin  entered  into  the  world;'  though  tl«- 
mystery  of  original  sin  must  still  be  held  together  witli 
the  truth  of  nature  that  (rod  only  punishes  men  'for  that  ' 
they  themselves  '  have  sinned.' 

It  was  equally  vain  in  a  comment  on  the  text  that 
'the  judgment  was  from  one  offence  to  condemnation, but 
the  free  gift  was  of  many  offences  unto  justification,'  to 
attempt  to  negative  the  unity  of  the  sin  mentioned  in  the 
preceding  clause  by  the  plurality  in  the  next ;  and  to  argue, 
that  if  one  sin  had  been  the  source  of  the  general  sinful- 
ness  of  mankind,  it  would  have  been  written  'from  o,>e 
offence,'  not  '  from  many  offences  unto  justification.'  - 
The  unity  of  the  source  is  not  inconsistent  with  pluralii y 
in  the  proceeds  from  it.  To  interpret  '  many '  again  to 
mean  many  offences  of  one  and  the  same  person  was  gra 
tuitous,3  though  convenient  for  a  coveted  inference,  that 
the  state  out  of  which  a  man  was  raised  at  justification 
was  contemplated  here  only  as  a  state  of  personal,  not 
of  original  sin. 

No  candid  interpreter,  again,  of  the  text,  '  As  by  t 
offence  of  one  judgment  came  upon  all  men  to  condemna 
tion  ;  even  so  by  the  righteousness  of  One  the  free  jni 
came  upon  all  men  unto  justification  of  life,'  would  allow 
its  obvious  force  to  be  negatived  by  the  remark  that,  as ; 
mankind  do  not  attain  to  justification,  the  universality 
ascribed  to  the  effect  of  Adam's  sin  in  the  first  clause 
destroyed  by  the  necessarily  limited  sense  of  universality 
as  applied  to  justification,  in  the  next.4   \\  here  the  weigh 

'  Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  63.  Adam    quoque    universis    nocuUso 

2  Ibid  c  105  fingatur.'—  Op.   Imp.  1.  2.   c.    1 

3  t  ^  parvulos  multis  obnoxios  Augustine  answers,  '  Qui  pp^ten-a 
'  esse  crimin'ibus.'-Ibid.  c.  114.  omnes  liberate,  dictus  eat  etia 

«  «  Si  Christus  salvarit  universes,      quoniam  non  hberat  quenquam  HIM 


374  Note  XIII. 


of  Scripture  goes  plainly  in  one  direction,  these  minute 
verbal  criticisms  on  dependent  and  subordinate  clauses, 
ought  not  to  be  allowed  to  interfere  with  it. 

From  the  passage  in  the  Epistle  to  the  Romans  the 
Pelagian  passed  to  that  in  the  First  Epistle  to  the  Corin 
thians,  '  As  in  Adam  all  die,  even  so  in  Christ  shall  all  be 
made  alive'  (1  Cor.  xv.  22.);  and  his  interpretation  was 
the  same,  that  whether  death  was  understood  here  of 
natural  or  of  moral  death,  i.e.,  sin,  Adam  was  only  put 
forth  as  the  sample,  not  as  the  root  of  it ;  an  interpreta 
tion  which  he  confirmed  by  a  reference  to  the  succeeding 
text,  '  As  we  have  borne  the  image  of  the  earthly  we  shall 
also  bear  the  image  of  the  heavenly  ; '  as  if  this  explained 
the  preceding  one  in  the  sense  of  an  actual  imitation  of 
Adam,  not  of  any  transmitted  guilt  or  penalty  from 
him.' l 

The  curse,  at  the  commencement  of  the  book  of  Gene 
sis,  received  a  double  explanation  ;  first,  as  imposing  no 
new  suffering  on  man  ;  and,  secondly,  as  imposing  it,  if  it 
did  impose  it,  only  for  the  warning,  and  not  for  the  punish 
ment  of  posterity.2  The  Pelagian  observed  that  sorrows 
were  '  multiplied '  on  the  woman,  as  if  they  had  existed 
before ; 3  and  that  Adam,  again,  on  whom  the  curse  im 
posed  labour,  had  laboured  before  in  the  Garden  of  Eden  ;4 
and  that  as  a  matter  of  fact  labour  was  not  the  universal 
penalty,  because  it  was  not  the  universal  lot  of  man.  The 
sentence  of  death  was  even  more  boldly  dealt  with ;  and 
when  the  Pelagian  had  inferred  from  the  text, '  For  dust  thou 
art,  and  unto  dust  shalt  thou  return, 'that  this  event  rested 
upon  a  physical  ground  anterior  to  man's  transgression,  he 
proceeded  to  observe  that  the  announcement  of  it  at  that 
time  was  not  intended  as  a  severe,  but  as  a  consolatory 

ipse.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  2.  c.  136.  indicet  cautionem.' — Ibid.  c.  27. 

1  '  Sicut  omnes,  i.  e.   multi  Adse          8  Augustine :  '  Multiplicabo,  mul- 
imitatione  moriuntur,  ita  omnes,  i.e.  tas  eas  esse  faciam.     Poterat  mul- 
multi  Christi  imitatione  salvantur.'  tiplicare  quse  non  erant.' — Op.  Imp. 
—Ibid.  1.  6.  c.  31.  1.  6.  c.  26. 

2  '  Ut     commemoratione     primi  *  '  Quid  ei  novum  accidisse  credi- 
peccati,  afflictio  succedanea  his,  quos  mus,  si    sentiret   sudorem.' — Ibid. 
reos  non  fecerat,  imitationis  malse  c.  27. 


Note  XIV.  375 


one — a  promise  of  relief  from  the  trials  and  pains  of  life.1 
But  S.  Augustine  appealed  to  the  evident  meaning  of  the 
curse  as  a  judicial  sentence,  inflicting  a  punishment  in 
consequence  of  man's  sin  which  did  not  exist  before  it  ;- 
he  appealed  to  a  larger  sense  of  labour  than  the  narrow 
one  of  his  opponent  ;3  and  he  showed  to  the  Pelagian  the 
unavoidable  inference  from  his  explanation  of  the  sentence 
of  death,  that  man  was  wiser  after  his  transgression  than 
he  was  before  it.  For  if  death  awaited  him  before  his  sin, 
as  the  lot  of  nature,  the  only  difference  which  the  curse,  in 
announcing  the  event  to  him,  made  was,  that  it  gave  him 
the  knowledge  of  it.' 4 

NOTE    XIV.  p.  85. 

JULIAN  the  Pelagian  interprets  Adam  being  created  good 
as  meaning  merely  that  he  was  created  with  freewill,  or 
'  the  power  to  do  good ;  Augustine  interprets  it  as  meaning 
that  Adam  was  created  with  a  good  disposition  or  formed 
habit,  and  rejects  the  Pelagian  meaning  as  a  false  one,  for 
the' plain  reason  that  to  be  able  to  be  good  is  not  the  same 
as  to  be  good  ;  whereas,  Adam  was  made  (food.  He  admits, 
indeed,  that  in  a  certain  sense,  a  nature  which  is  able  not 
to  sin  is  a  good  nature  :  '  Bonum  conditum  Adam  non  ego 
tantum  nee  tu,  sed  ambo  dicimus.  Ambo  enim  dicimus 
bonam  esse  naturam  quae  possit  non  peccare.'— Op.  Imp . 
16  c  16.  But  this  sense  is  put  aside  as  insufficient. 
<Quid  est  ergo  quod  mine  dicis ;  «  Bonus  Deiis  bonum 
fecit  hominem,"  si  nee  bonus  nee  mains  est,  habendo  lib 
rum  arbitrium  quod  in  eo  Deus  fecit?  .  .  .  Et  qnomodo 
verum  est,  "  Fecit  Deus  hominem  rectum.  --Eccl.  vn.  m. 
An  rectus  erat  non  habens  voluntatem  bonam,  sed  qut 
possibilitatem  *  Ergo  et  pravus  erat  non  habens  volunfc 
tern  pravam,  sed  ejus  possibilitatem.  .  .  .  Ita  fit,  u 
tuam  mirabilem  sapientiam,  nee  Deus  fecerit  rectum 
hominem;  sed  qui  rectus  posset  esse  si  vellet.—L.  5. 
c.  57. 

>  Op.  Imp.  1.  6.  c.  27.  tenew  difficile  cst.'-L.  6.  c.  27. 

«  •  Imo,  inquis  et  damnatus  est,  s  L.  L  c.  M. 

^et  nihil  ei  accidit  novi.    Hie  risum  L.  6.  c.  n. 


376  Note  XIV. 


Adam  being  created  good,  then,  meant  that  he  way 
created  with  a  positive  goodness,  or  a  good  habit  of  mind. 
Such  a  habit  S.  Augustine  expresses  by  the  term  bona 
voluntas,  voluntas  meaning  an  established  bias  or  inclina 
tion,  or  what  we  call  character.  '  Sed,  inquis,  u  Ideo 
potuit  oriri  voluntas  mala,  ut  oriri  posset  et  bona."  Quasi 
non  cum  bona  voluntate  factus  sit  vel  angelus  vel  homo. 
Factus  est  rectus,  sicut  dixit  Scriptura. — Eccl.  vii.  29. 
Non  ergo  quasritur  unde  in  illo  potuerit  oriri  bona  volun 
tas,  cum  qua  factus  est ;  sed  unde  mala  cum  qua  factus 
non  est.  Et  tu  dicis,  non  attendens  quid  dicas  "  Ideo- 
potuit  oriri  voluntas  mala,  ut  oriri  posset  et  bona :  "  et 
hoc  putas  ad  naturam  liberi  arbitrii  pertinere,  ut  possit 
utrumque  et  peccare  scilicet  et  non  peccare ;  et  in  hoc 
existimas  hominem  factum  ad  imaginem  Dei,  cum  Deus 
ipse  non  possit  utrumque.' — L.  5.  c.  38.  '  Quis  enim  ferat, 
si  dicatur  talis  factus,  quales  nascuntur  infantes?  Ilia 
itaque  perfectio  naturse  quam  non  dabant  anni,  sed  sola 
manus  Dei,  non  potuit  nisi  habere  voluntatem  aliquaru, 
eamque  non  malam.  Bonse  igitur  voluntatis  factus  est 
homo  .  .  .  neque  enim  nisi  recta  volens  rectus  est  quis- 
quam? — L.  5.  c.  61. 

Julian  objects  to  this  implanted  voluntas  on  the  free 
will  ground,  pronouncing  it  absurd  that  a  man  can  be 
made  good ;  on  the  ground  that  goodness  implied,  in  its 
very  nature,  choice  and  exertion  of  the  will.  '  Est  natura 
humana  bonum  opus  Dei :  est  libertas  arbitrii,  id  est,  pos- 
sibilitas  vel  delinquendi  vel  recte  faciendi,  bonum  seque 
opus  Dei.  Utrumque  hoc  homini  de  necessario  venit.  Sed 
voluntas  in  his  exoritur  non  de  his.  Capacia  voluntatis 
sunt  quippe,  non  plena.' — Op.  Imp.  1.  5,  c.  56.  '  Est  ergo 
ista  possibilitas,  quse  nomine  libertatis  ostenditur,  ita  a 
sapientissimo  constituta  Deo,  ut  sine  ipsa  non  sit,  quod 
per  ipsam  esse  non  cogitur.' — c.  57.  Augustine  replies  : 
6  Ut  video,  nee  bonam  voluntatem  vis  tribuere  naturae, 
quando  est  homo  primitus  conditus :  quasi  non  potuerit 
Deus  hominem  facere  voluntatis  bonse.' — c.  61. 

Augustine's  bona  voluntas  only  seems  to  express  in  a 
different  form  the  traditional  view  of  the  Church  from  the 


_  _  Note  XIV.  377 

first,  as  contained  in  the  writings  of  the  earlier  fathers. 
Bishop  Bull,  in  his  discourse  on  the  State  of  Man  before 
the  Fall,  quotes  their  principal  statements  on  the  subject. 
They  all  take  for  their  basis  the  scriptural  truth,  that 
Adam  was  made  in  the  image  of  God  ;  and  they  commonly 
interpret  this  to  mean  that  the  soul  of  Adam  had  a  certain 
indwelling  of  the  Holy  Spirit  in  it.  Tatian,  the  pupil  of 
Justin  Martyr,  speaks  of  ;the  familiarity  and  friendship' 
of  the  Spirit  with  Adam  in  his  created  state  :  rf/s  vvv 
avro)  Stam/s  —  rov  TrvsvjJLcnos  rov  BwaTwrepov^  whom  lie 
also  calls  77  Aoyov  Bvva/jLLs.—  Contra  6rrctms,  c.  7.  Irena'iis 
says:  '  Spiritus  cornmixtus  animae  unitur  plasmati'd.  .5. 
c.  6.)  ;  and  also  speaks  of  the  robe  of  sanctity  which  Adam 
had  from  the  Spirit  :  '  quam  habuit  a  Spirit  u  sanctitatis 
stolarn.'  —  L.  3.  c.  23.  Tertullian  speaks  of  the  Spirit  of 
God  which  Adam  received  by  inspiration  :  '  Spiritum  quern 
tune  de  afflatu  ejus  acceperat.'  —  De  Baptismo,  c.  o. 
Clemens  Alexandrinus  speaks  of  '  the  characteristical  pro 
priety  of  the  Holy  Spirit  superadded  '  to  the  nature  of 
Adam  :  Trpoo-yivo/nsvov  dylov  Trvsv/jLaros  ^apaKT^pi^TtKov 
.  —  Strom.  1.  6.  c.  16.  Athanasius  speaks  of  God  im 


parting  to  our  first  parents  the  power  of  His  own  Word  : 
avTols  KOL  -rf}9  rov  IBiov  Aoyov  Swdpscos.  —  De 


Incar.  Verb.  torn.  i.  c.  3.  Basil  speaks  of  the  '  assessiou 
of  God,  and  conjunction  with  him  (Adam)  by  lovi  —  77 
irpoasSpsla  -rov  0sov,  /cal  rj  &t,a  Tr)S  dydinis  trvvdipeia.'— 
Homil.  quod  non  Deus  est  Auctor  Peccat.  Cyril  speaks  of 
6  that  Spirit  which  formed  him  (Adam)  after  the  Divine 
image,  and  was,  as  a  seal,  secretly  impressed  on  his  soul- 
TO  TT/OOS  0s  lav  sUova  Siapopfovv  avrb,  Kal  a^dvrpov  Slicny 
airopMrvs  ivre0sif^vov:—  7.  Dialog,  de  Trin.  This  fami 
liar  abode  of  the  Spirit  in  the  first  man,  and  the  character 
and  seal  stamped  by  the  Spirit  upon  him,  evidently  imply 
a  certain  disposition  of  mind  or  holy  habit  which  was 
formed  in  him,  as  Cyprian  (De  Bono  Patientm)  actually 
expresses  it,  interpreting  the  Divine  image  as  involving 
virtues  —  virtutes. 


37*  Note  XV. 


NOTE   XV.  p.  102. 

THUS  Justin  Martyr  says  of  the  human  race  :  o  dirb  rov 
'ASa//,  VTTO  Bdvarov  ical  7r\dvrjv  rrjv  rov  o<f>sa)s  srrsrrr^KSL, 
rrapa  rr)v  ISlav  alrlav  s/cdarov  avrwv  rrov^psvaa^svov. — 
Dial,  cum  Try  ph.  c.  88.  rrapa  here  signifying  not  besides 
(prceter)  but  by  reason  of  sua  propria  cujusque  culpa, 
the  latter  half  of  this  sentence  gives  the  natural  truth — 
viz.,  that  the  individual  sins  by  the  exercise  of  his  own 
freewill ;  as  the  former  gives  the  revealed,  that  the  indi 
vidual  sins  in  consequence  of  the  sinfulness  of  the  race. 
One  sentence  of  Tatian's  joins  the  two  in  the  same  way : 
£r)0i  TCO  0sq)  rr)V  rra\aiav  ysvsa'Lv  rrapanovLJiSvos  OVK  sysvo- 

JjieOa  TTpOS  TO  drroOvrjcrtCSlV,  drr00V)j(7KO/jLev    $£   6Y  SdVTOVS. — 

Contra  Grcec.  c.  1 1 .  The  *  old  birth  '  is  the  mysterious, 
the  '  SL  eavTovsJ  the  obvious  and  conscious  cause  of  sin. 
So  far  the  fathers  only  follow  the  precedent  of  Scripture, 
which  puts  the  two  grounds  together,  as  in  Rom.  v.  12., 
4  As  by  one  man  sin  entered  into  the  world  and  death  by 
sin ;  and  so  death  passed  upon  all  men,  for  that  all  have 
sinned  ; '  death  being  referred  in  the  first  part  of  the 
sentence  to  the  sin  of  Adam,  in  the  last  to  each  man's  actual 
sins.  Again,  several  fathers  speak  of  infants  as  innocent 
beings  :  '  Quid  festinat  innocens  a3tas  ad  remissionem  pec- 
catorum.' — Tertullian  De  Bapt.  c.  1 8.  '  'EA,#<Wes  sis 
rdvSs  rov  tcoa/jiov  dvafjidpr'rjroL.' — Cyril  of  Jerusalem,  Cat. 
iv.  13.  'To  aTTSipoica/cov  vrJTriov  .  .  fjurj  Sso/jusvov  rrjs  sic  rov 
KaOapOrjvcu  vyisia?,  cm  /JLTJ&S  rr]v  dp%f]v  rrjv  vocrov  TTJ  ifrvxfj 
TrapsBs^aro  ...  TO  fjuiJTS  sv  dydOq),  /JLIJTS  sv  /cd/cq)  svpicricb- 
jusvovS — Gregory  Nyss.  (De  iis  qui  praemature  abripiun- 
tur).  But  Hagenbach  is  precipitate  in  concluding  from 
the  passage  in  Cyril,  that  '  Cyril  of  Jerusalem  assumed 
that  men  are  born  in  a  state  of  innocence '  (History  of 
Doctrines,  v.  i.  p.  315.) ;  i.e.  if  he  means  by  this  that 
Cyril  denied  original  sin.  It  is  a  truth  of  reason  and 
nature,  that  infants  are  innocent  beings,  which  may  be 
asserted,  as  it  must  be  by  every  rational  person,  without 
prejudice  to  the  mysterious  truth  of  their  guilt  as  descen- 


Note  XV.  379 


dants  of  Adam.  Tertullian,  who  asserts  it,  is  at  the  same 
time  acknowledged  as  one  of  those  fathers  who  have  most 
strongly  asserted  the  doctrine  of  original  sin ;  and  Scripture 
itself  asserts  both,  saying  of  children,  that  '  of  such  is  the 
kingdom  of  heaven,'  while  at  the  same  time  it  declares, 
that  '  in  Adam  all  die.'  Chrysostom  again  denies  that  one 
man  can  be  responsible  for  another  man's  sin  :  TO  [lev  yap 
srspov  St'  STSpov  KoKaCpaQai  ov  a(f)p6&pa  &OKSL  \6yov  s^siv. 
— Horn.  X.  in  Rom.  But  this  is  a  simple  truth  of  reason 
which  nobody  can  deny,  and  the  assertion  of  it  is  quite 
consistent  with  holding  the  mystery  of  our  guilt  in  Adam. 
All  the  early  fathers,  moreover,  assert  strongly  the  freewill 
of  even  fallen  man,  his  irpoaipso-^  e\£vOspa,  avr strove LOV. 
But  this  runs  side  by  side  with  their  assertion  of  his 
6  captivity '  and  '  corruption,'  as  another  part  of  the  whole 
truth. 

The  case  of  Clement  of  Alexandria  is  perhaps  peculiar, 
though  too  much  should  not  be  made  of  particular  ex 
pressions,  like  the  ones  just  quoted,  found  in  him.  In 
combating,  indeed,  the  Gnostic  doctrine  of  our  evil 
nature,  he  uses  arguments  which  would  equally  tell 
against  the  doctrine  of  original  sin.  He  denies  that  any 
one  can  be  evil  but  by  his  own  personal  act :  Xsyerwo-av 

^/jLLV    7TOV    ETTOpVSVCTSV    TO  pSWyOsV  TTaiOlOV,  Tf   7TWS    VTTO  TT)V 

ToO'ASa/z,  {JTTOTTSTTTWKSV  dpav  TO  ^sv  hspy^av',— Strom . 
1.  3.  c.  16.     He  describes,  again,  sin  after  the  fall,  as  if  it 
were  only  a  repetition,  and  not  an  effect  of  sin  at  the  fall  : 
sit  yap  6  d7raT£a)v  avvOsv  psv  TVV  Evai>,  vvv  oe  rjBri   Kai 
TOVS    a\\ovs     dvOpUTTovs     its     dava-rov     v-rro^spwv.—Ad 
Gentes,vol.    1.  p.   7.     But   Hagenbach  is  precipitate   in 
concluding  that  Clement  '  rejects  the  doctrine  of  original 
sin,  properly  so  called,'  simply  on  the  strength  of  such 
passages  as  these.— History   of  Doctrine,  v.   1.  p-   173. 
Augustine  himself  has  a  similar  passage  exactly  to  the  one 
iust  quoted  :  <  Etiam  nunc  in  unoquoque  nostrum  mh 
aliud  agitur,  cum  ad  peccatum  quisque  delabitur,  quar 
tune  actum  est  in  illis  tribus,  serpente,  muliere,  et  viro. 
-De  Genesi  contra  Man.  1.  2.  c.  14.     Such  expressio 
are  no  more  than  what  common  sense  justifies  and  obliges, 


380  Note  XVI. 


and  are  quite  consistent  with  belief  in  the  other  truth. 
But  Clement,  though  he  asserts  sin  to  be  '  natural,'  TO 
yap  s^a/jLapTavsiv  TTCLGIV  s/jt,(f)VTOv  KOI  K.OLVOV  (Peed.  1.  3.  c. 
1  2),  (his  language,  however,  seeming  to  express  here  uni 
versal  rather  than  original  sin),  certainly  seems  to  explain 
away  the  passage  in  the  Psalms,  4  in  sin  hath  my  mother 
conceived  me,'  interpreting  it  to  refer  to  sinful  custom  or 
habit,  not  to  sinful  nature  (Strom.  1.  3.  c.  16.),  though  at 
the  same  time  it  must  be  remarked,  that  he  is  relieving 
the  passage  of  a  Gnostic  meaning,  according  to  which  sin 
was  inherent  in  natural  generation  as  such,  and  not 
opposing  the  Catholic.  Jeremy  Taylor  gives  a  somewhat 
similar  explanation  with  less  excuse.  '  The  words  are  a 
Hebraism,  and  signify  nothing  but  an  aggrandation  of  his 
sinfulness,  and  are  intended  for  a  high  expression,  mean 
ing  that  '  I  am  wholly  and  entirely  wicked.' — Vol.  ix. 
p.  27.  On  the  whole,  though  Clement,  in  common  with 
all  the  early  fathers,  is  a  lenient  interpreter  of  the  doc 
trine  of  original  sin,  and  though  such  passages  as  these 
have  not  such  counterbalancing  ones  in  his  writings  as 
they  have  in  those  of  other  fathers,  these  passages  are  no 
test  of  his  belief  on  the  subject. 

NOTE  XVI.  p.  114. 

Tous-  Bs  (unbaptised  infants,  or  those  who  by  accident 
died  without  baptism)  fjuijrs  Sogao-OrjcrsvOai,,  /JLTJTS  tcoXa- 
crQr)<j£aQai  Trspl  rov  Si/calov  Kpt-rov,  a>s  dor<ppafylcrrovs  [isv 
dTrovijpovs  BE,  d\\d  iraQovras  (jiaXkov  TTJV  ty/jblav  rj  opd- 
o-avras.  ov  yap  OCTTLS  ov  tco\do~sw$  a£io$  77877  KOI  TifMfjs* 
wcrTrsp  OCTTIS  ov  Tt/jLTjs  ?j$7}  KOI  Ko\dascos. — Gregory  Naz. 
Orat.  40.  v.  i.  p.  653.  Gregory  of  Nyssa  formally  dis 
cusses  the  question  of  the  future  condition  of  those  who 
die  as  infants,  without  reference  to  their  being  or  not  bap 
tised  (v.  ii.  p.  749) ;  which,  in  distinction  to  the  ground 
taken  by  some,  that  they  do  not  deserve  so  much  happi 
ness  as  the  mature  good,  he  maintains  to  turn,  not  so 
much  upon  any  difference  of  claim,  as  of  natural  aptitude 
and  capacity  for  happiness.  OVK  SO-TLV  elirslv  tcvplcas  aim- 


NoteXVL 


Socriv  TWV  svfttftiVKOiwv  ysvsffOai  rr/i/   rr}s-  fo»)y 
teal  Tipwpiav  TO  s^Trakiv.     "AXV  o/zotof  ecru  rco  /cara 
<x$6a\fjiovs  VTroSsiy/jiaTi  TO  \sy6fjisvov.      OuSe  ^ya 
Qappsvw  TCLS   otysis  ETra6\6v   11  $apev  flvai  KCLI 
Tr]v    TWV    opdrcov   KuravoTjcnv,  rj  TW  voaovvTi  TO 
TLVCL    TO   fJis    ^TS^SLV  rijs   oparifcijs  e 
avayKaiass  STTSTCU  TO>  Kara  tyvcrtv  SuiKSifji^vu)  TO 

TO>  TS     CL7TO    TTaOoVS    rrrap£l'£%6sVT I    TT/S    (£ucr£&>y.  TO 

pr)  Ivspysiv  TTJV  opao-iV  rbvavrbv  TOTTOV  /cal  ?/  fi'i/capi'a  fft;?; 

<TV/jL(j)Vrj9  SO'TL     KOI    olfCSta  TOL9  KSKaOap/ASVOLS  T(l  T1]S  ^fUVijV 

alo-07]Tijpia.  Upon  this  principle  lie  proceeds  to  ar^uc 
that  the  happiness  of  infants  in  a  future  state  will  be  in 
proportion  to  their  capacity  for  it,  which  will  be  lower 
than  that  of  those  who  have  lived  virtuously  as  mature 
men  ;  that  it  will  be  analogous  to  their  happiness  in  this 
life,  which  is  of  the  simpler  and  unconscious  kind.  Kada- 
Trsp  <yap  $77X77  KOL  yaXtdKTi  r)  TrpajTq  TWV  VSTTIMV  f)\ircia 
TL0vvovfJLSvr]  £KTpsd>£Tai'  sir  a  StaSeyfTat  TavTrjv  KaTa\\i]\o$ 

rf  «f  /  J^>'  v'  S>     ' 

STSpa  TO)   VTTOKSL/jLSVq)  T^007),  OLKSidJS  T£  KOI   E7TlTr)G£lO)$  TTpQS 

TO  Tpsfyb/Jbsvov  Ivoucraj  sws  av  ETTL  TO  TE\SLOV  (f>0do"rj' 
OUTWS  ol/jiai  /cal  TYJV  ^v^rfv  &ia  TWV  ael  KCLT*  a\\ij\a)i> 
Tagst,  Tivi  /cal  afCoXovQta  fJLSTSf%stv  TTJS  /caTa  <bvaiv  fwr/s,  CDS 
'Xftipsi  /cal  SvvaTai  TWV  sv  TTJ  puKipioT'^TL'jrpOKSifjLsvw 

\afJi(3dvovo-a 'H  &s  ayevo-TOs  Trjs  dpsrijs 

TWV  fjisv  EK  irovypias  ica/cuv,  CLTS  fJirJTE  Trjv  ap%r)V 
Oslaa  ry  Trjs  /ca/clay  vbcrw,  SLafJisvei  d^iETO^os  rijs 
s/cslvr)?  '\r)v  ®EOV  yv&vlv  TS  teal psrovo- lav  TOO-OVTOV  jierfyei 
Trapa  TTJV  TTpwTrjv,  oa-ov  x^Pst>  ro  Tpe<j>6fJievov. — Augustine 
maintained  a  middle  state,  in  his  earlier  theological  life. 
— Dicunt  enim  :  quid  opus  est  ut  nasceretur  qui  antequam 
iniret  ullum  vitse  meritum  excessit  e  vita  ?  Aut  qualia  in 
futtiro  judicio  deputabitur,  cui  neque  inter  justos  locus 
est,  quoniam  nihil  recte  fecit ;  neque  inter  malos,  quomain 
nihil  peccavit?  Quibus  respondetur:  ad  imiversitatis 
complexum,  et  totius  creaturse  vel  per  locos  vel  per  tem- 
pora  ordinatissimam  connexionem,  non  posse  supernuo 
creari  qualemcunque  hominem,  ubi  folium  arboris  nullum 
superfluumcreatur;  sed  sane  super fluo  quaen  dementis 
ejus  qui  nihil  meruerit.  Non  enim  metuendum  est  ne 


382  Note  XVII. 


vita  esse  potuerit  media  qusedam  inter  recte  factum  atque 
peccatum,  et  sententia  judicis  media  esse  non  possit  inter 
prsemium  et  supplicium. — De  Lib.  Arb.  1.  3.  c.  23. 

NOTE  XVII.  p.  121. 

IN  the  first  of  the  following  passages  all  wickedness,  in 
the  second  extreme  wickedness,  is  referred  to  original  sin ; 
in  the  third,  different  degrees  admitted  in  evil,  are  ac 
counted  for  by  different  degrees  of  original  sin  ;  in  the 
fourth  and  fifth  these  degrees  in  evil  appear  as  the  addi 
tions  of  the  individual  to  original  sin,  though  in  what 
precise  sense  they  leave  uncertain. 

(1.)  'Ad  iram  quippe  Dei  [in  consequence  of  original 
sin]  pertinet  justam,  quicquid  caeca  et  indomita  concupis- 
centia  faciunt  libenter  mali.' — Enchiridion,  c.  27.  (2.) 
'  Omnes  ex  eadem  massa  perditionis  et  damnationis  se- 
curidum  duritiem  cordis  sui  et  cor  impenitens,  quantum 
ad  ipsos  pertinet,  thesaurizant  sibi  iram  in  die  irse,  quo 
redditur  unicuique  secundum  opera  sua.' — Contra  Juli- 
anum  Pelagianum,  1.  5.  c.  4.  (3.)  '  Veruntamen  taci 
turn  non  est  quod  erat  eorum  malitia  naturalis ;  quae 
quidem  omnium  hominum,  sed  in  aliis  minor,  in  aliis 
major  est :  sicut  corpora  corruptibilia  sunt  omnium,  sed 
alias  animas  minus,  alias  plus  gravant,  pro  diversitate 
judiciorum  Dei,  occultorurn  quidem,  sed  sine  ulla  dubi- 
tatione  justorum.' — Opus  Imp.  Contra  Julianum,  1.  4. 
c.  128.  (4.)  'Hi  ergo  qui  non  pertinent  ad  istum  cer- 
tissimum  et  felicissimum  numerum  pro  meritis  justissime 
judicantur.  Aut  enim  jacent  sub  peccato,  quod  origin a- 
liter  generatim  traxerunt,  et  cum  illo  hsereditario  debito 
hinc  exeunt,  quod  non  est  regeneratione  dimissum  ;  aut 
per  liberum  arbitrium  alia  insuper  addiderunt ;  arbitrium, 
inquam,  liberum  sed  non  liberatum;  liberum  justitise, 
peccati  autem  servum,  quo  volvuntur  per  diversas  noxias 
cupiditates,  alii  magis,  alii  minus ;  sed  ornnes  mali.' — De 
Correptione  et  Gratia,  c.  1 3.  (5.)  '  Si  autem  male 
vivunt  de  suo  male  vivunt,  vel  quod  originaliter  traxerunt,. 
vel  quod  insuper  addiderunt.  Sed  si  vasa  sunt  irse,  quaa 


Note  XVIII.  383 


perfecta  sunt  ad  perditionem,  quse  illis  debita  redditur, 
sibi  hoc  imputent,  quia  ex  ea  massa  facta  sunt,  quam 
propter  unius  peccaturn,  in  quo  omnes  peccaverunt,  merito 
Deus  justeque  damnavit.' — Ep.  194.  c.  6. 

Jansen  interprets  S.  Augustine  as  making  the  whole 
mass  of  actual  sin  in  the  world  the  simple  effect  and 
development  of  original.  '  Positive  reprobationis  causa  .  . . 
peccata  omnia  cum  quibus  morituri  sunt,  etiam  originale 
peccatum.  Nam  ex  illius  suppliciis  quicquid  peccatorum 
a  reprobatis  perpetratum  est  accessu  libeno  voluntatis, 
fluxit  .  .  .  ut  proinde  ilia  tota  suppliciorum  concatenatio, 
usque  ad  damnationem  in  ignein  8eternam,radicaliter  et  me 
diate  in  peccati  originalis  meritum  referenda  videatur.  Im 
mediate  tamen  prima  poenarum  istarum  promeretur 
secundam,  et  ita  deinceps,  donee  ultima  tandem,  vclut 
praecedentium  complement  um,  inferatur.' — De  Gro.tid 
Christi,p.  1019. 

NOTE   XVIII.  p.  123. 

6  ET  propterea  conantur  parvulis  non  baptizatis  innocentiae 
merito  salutem  ac  vitam  seternam  tribuere  ;  sed,  quia  bap- 
tizati  non  sunt,  eos  a  regno  coelorum  facere  alienos :  nova 
quadam  et  mirabili  prsesumptione,  quasi  salus  ac  vita 
seterna  possit  esse  prseter  Christ!  haereditatem,  printer  reg- 
num  coelorum.  .  .  .  Profecto  ill!  quibus  Sacrament  um 
defuerit  in  eis  habendi  sunt  qui  non  credunt  Filio ;  atcjue 
ideo,  si  hujus  inanes  gratisB  de  corpore  exierint,  sequetur 
eos  quod  dictum  est,  "  Non  habebunt  vitam  sed  ira  Dei 
manet  super  eos."  Unde  hoc,  quando  eos  clarum  est  pec 
cata  propria  non  habere,  si  nee  original!  peccato  teneantur 
obnoxii.'— De  Peccat.  Merit,  et  Rem.  1.  1.  c.  xx. 

4  Quia  ergo  de  ovibus  ejus  non  esse  incipiunt  parvuli 
nisi  per  baptismum ;  profecto,  si  hoc  non  accipiunt, 
peribunt,' — Ibid.  c.  xxvii. 

'  Quemadmodum  enim  omnes  omnino  pertinentes 
generationem  voluntatis  carnis  non  moriuntur  nisi  in  Adam 
in  quo  omnes  peccaverunt :  sic  ex  his  omnes  omnino  per 
tinentes  ad  regenerationem  voluntatis  spiritus  non  vivifi- 


384  Note  XVIII. 


cantur -nisi  in  Christo,  in  quo  omnes  justificantur.  Quia 
si  cut  per  unum  omnes  ad  condemnationem,  sic  per  unum 
omnes  ad  justificationem.  Nee  est  ullus  medius  locus  ut 
possit  esse  nisi  cum  diabolo,  qui  non  est  cum  Christo.  Hie 
et  ipse  Dominns  volens  auferre  de  cordibus  male  credentium 
istam  iiescio  quam  medietatem,  quam  conantur  quidam 
parvulis  non  baptizatis  tribuere,  ut  quasi  merito  innocentise 
sint  in  vita  oeterna,  sed  quia  non  sunt  baptizati  non  sint 
cum  Christo  in  regno  ejus,  definitivam  protulit  ad  haec  ora 
obstruenda  sententiam,  ubi  ait :  "  Qui  mecum  non  est, 
adversum  me  est/'  Constitue  igitur  quemlibet  parvulum  : 
si  jam  cum  Christo  est,  ut  quid  baptizatur  ?  Si  autem, 
quod  habet  veritas,  ideo  baptizatur  ut  sic  cum  Christo, 
profecto  non  baptizatus  non  est  cum  Christo,  et,  quia  non 
est  cum  Christo,  adversus  Christum  est.' — Ibid.  c.  xxviii. 

'  Unde  fit  consequens  ut,  quoniam  nihil  agitur  aliud, 
cum  parvuli  baptizantur,  nisi  ut  incorporentur  ecclesise,  id 
est,  Christi  corpori  membrisque  associentur ;  manifestum 
est  eos  ad  damnationem,  nisi  hoc  eis  collatum  fuerit,  perti  - 
nere.  Non  autem  damnari  possent,  si  peccatum  utique 
non  haberent.  Hoc  quia  ilia  setas  nulla  in  vita  propria 
contrahere  potuit,  restat  intelligere  vel,  si  hoc  nondum 
possumus,  saltern  credere,  trahere  parvulos  originale  pec 
catum.' — Ibid.  1.  3.  c.  iv. 

'  Absit  ut  causam  parvulorum  sic  relinquamus,  ut  esse 
nobis  dicamus  incertum,  utrum  in  Christo  regenerati,  si 
moriantur  parvuli,  transeant  in  seternam  salutem ;  non 
regenerati  autem  transeant  in  mortem  secundam  ;  quoniam 
quod  scriptum  est,  "  Per  unum  hominem  peccatum  intravit 
in  mundum,  et  per  peccatum  mors ;  et  ita  in  omnes 
homines  pertransiit,"  aliter  recte  intelligi  non  potest :  nee 
a  morte  perpetua  quse  justissime  est  retributa  peccato, 
liberat  quenquam  pusillorum  atque  magnorum,  nisi  ille 
qui  propter  remittenda  et  originalia  et  propria  nostra  pec- 
cata  mortuus  est,  sine  ullo  suo  originali  et  proprio  peccato. 
Sed  quare  illos  potius  quam  illos  ?  Iterum  atque  iterum 
dicimus,  nee  nos  piget,  "  0  homo,  tu  quis  es  qui  respondeas 
Deo  ?  "  ' — De  Dono  Perseverantice,  c.  xii. 

'  Sed  ut  id  quod  dicimus  alicujus  exempli  manifesta- 


Note  XV II I. 


385 

tione  clarescat,  constituamus  aliquos  ab  abliqua  meretrice 
geminos  editos,  atque  ut  ab  aliis  colligerentur,  expositos : 
horum  sine  baptismo  expiravit  unus,  alius  baptizatus. 
Quid  restat  quantum  ad  baptizatum  attinet,  nisi  gratia 
Dei  quae  vasis  factis  in  honorem  gratis  datur ;  quantum 
autem  ad  non  baptizatum,  ira  Dei,  quae  vasis  factis  ad  con- 
tumeliam  pro  ipsius  massae  mentis  redditur  ? '— Contra 
Duas  Ep.  Pel.  1.  2.  c.  vii. 

'  Ac  per  hoc,  quia  nihil  ipsi  male  vivendo  addiderunt 
ad  originale  peccatum,  potest  eorum  merito  dici  in  ilia 
damnatione  minima  poena,  non  tamen  nulla.  Quisquis 
autem  putat  diversitatem  futuram  non  esse  pcenarum,  legat 
quod  scriptum  est,  "  Tolerabilius  erit  Sodoma3  in  die  judicii, 
quam  illi  civitati."  Non  ergo  a  deceptoribus  inter  regnum 
et  suppliciiun  medius  locus  quaeratur  infantibus  ;  sedtran- 
seant  a  diabolo  ad  Christum,  hoc  est,  a  morte  ad  vitain,  n<> 
ira  Dei  maneat  super  eos.' — Ep.  1 84.  c.  1 . 

'Respondeat  quid  de  illo  futurum  sit,  qui,  nulla  sua 
culpa  non  baptizatus,  ista  fuerit  temporali  morte  pneventus. 
Si  non  putamus  esse  dicturum  quod  innocentem  Deus,  nee 
habentem  originale  peccatum  ante  annos  quibus  habere 
poterat  proprium,  aeterna  morte  damnabit ;  cogitur  itaque 
respondere  quod  Pelagius  in  ecclesiastico  judicio,  ut  aliquo 
modo  catholicus  pronuntiaretur,  anathematizare  compulsus 
est,  infantes,  etiamsi  non  baptizentur,  habere  vitam  ;eter- 
nam  :  hac  enim  negata,  quid  nisi  mors  sterna  remanebit  ?  ' 
— Ep.  186.  c.  viii. 

'  Primus  hie  error  aversandus  ab  auribus,  exstirpandus 
a  mentibus.  Hoc  novum  in  ecclesia,  prius  inauditum  est, 
esse  vitam  geternam  praeter  regnum  ccelorum,  esse  salutem 
aeternam  praeter  regnum  Dei.  Primo  vide,  frater,  ne  forte 
hie  consentire  nobis  debeas,  quisquis  ad  regnum  Dei  non 
pertinet,  eum  ad  damnationem  sine  dubio  pertinere.  Ven 
turas  Dominus,  et  judicaturus  de  vivis  et  mortuis,  sicut 
evangelium  loquitur,  duas  partes  facturus  est,  dextram  et 
sinistram.  Sinistris  dicturus,  Ite  in  ignem  ccternam,  qui 
paratus  est  Diabolo  et  anyelis  ejus;  dextris  dicturus, 
Venite  benedicti  Patris  mei.perdpite  regnum  quod  vobw 
paratum  est,  ab  origine  mundi.  Hac  regnum  nominat, 

c  c 


386  Note  XIX. 


hac  cum  diabolo  damnationem.  Nullus  relictus  est  medius 
locus,  ubi  ponere  queas  infantes.  De  vivis  et  mortuis 
judicabitur :  alii  erunt  ad  dextram,  alii  ad  sinistram :  non 
novi  aliud.  Qui  inducis  medium,  recede  de  medio,  sed 
noli  in  sinistram.  Si  ergo  dextra  erit,  et  sinistra,  et 
nullum  medium  locum  in  Evangelio  novimus;  ecce  in 
dextra  regnum  coelorum  est,  Perdpite,  inquit,  regnum. 
Qui  ibi  non  est  in  sinistra  est.  Quid  erit  in  sinistra  ?  Itv 
in  ignem  ceternum.  In  dextra  ad  regnum,  utique  aeter- 
num  ;  in  sinistra  in  ignem  seternum.  Qui  non  in  dextra, 
procul  dubio  in  sinistra  :  ergo  qui  non  in  regno,  procul 
dubio  in  igne  asterno.  Certe  habere  potest  vitam  seternam 
qui  non  baptizatur  ?  Non  est  in  dextra,  id  est,  non  erit 
in  regno.  Vitam  aeternam  computas  ignem  sempiternum  ? 
Et  de  ipsa  vita  sterna  audi  expressius,  quia  nihil  aliud  est 
regnum  quam  vita  seterna.  Prius  regnum  nominavit,  sed 
in  dextris  ;  ignem  seternum  in  sinistris.  Extrema  autem 
sententia,  ut  doceret  quid  sit  regnum,  et  quid  sit  ignis 
sempiternus — Tune,  inquit,  abibunt  isti  in  ambustionem 
ceternam  ;  just  I  autem  in  vitam  ceternam. 

'  Ecce  exposuit  tibi  quid  sit  regnum,  et  quid  sit  ignis 
aeternus  ;  ut  quando  confitearis  parvulum  non  futurum  in 
regno,  fatearis  futurum  in  igne  asterno.' — Serm.  294, 
c.  iii. 

NOTE   XIX.  p.  131. 

HOOKER  states  S.  Augustine's  doctrine  of  predestination  as 
the  doctrine  '  that  the  whole  body  of  mankind  in  the  view 
of  Grod's  eternal  knowledge  lay  universally  polluted  with 
sin,  worthy  of  condemnation  and  death  ;  that  over  the  mass 
of  corruption  there  passed  two  acts  of  the  will  of  Grod,  an 
act  of  favour,  liberality,  and  grace,  choosing  part  to  be 
made  partakers  of  everlasting  glory;  and  an  act  of  justice, 
forsaking  the  rest  and  adjudging  them  to  endless  perdition; 
these  vessels  of  wrath,  those  of  mercy ;  which  mercy  is  to 
Grod's  elect  so  peculiar,  and  to  them  and  none  else  (for 
their  number  is  definitely  known,  and  can  neither  be  in 
creased  nor  diminished),  to  them  it  allotteth  immortality 
and  all  things  thereunto  appertaining ;  them  it  predes- 


Note  XIX.  387 


tinateth,  it  calleth,  justifieth,  glorifieth  them;  it  poureth 
voluntarily  that  spirit  into  their  hearts,  which  spirit  so 
given  is  the  root  of  their  very  first  desires  and  motions 
tending  to  immortality  ;  as  for  others  on  whom  such  grace 
is  not  bestowed,  there  is  justly  assigned,  and  immutably 
to  every  of  them,  the  lot  of  eternal  condemnation.'— 
Appendix  to  bk.  v.  Keble's  edition,  p.  730. 

Another  statement,  a  little  further  on,  not  so  much  of 
Augustine's  doctrine  as  professing  to  be  founded  upon  it, 
is  somewhat  less  rigid :  '  To  proceed,  we  have  seen  the 
general  inclination  of  God  towards  all  men's  everlasting 
happiness,  notwithstanding  sin ;  we  have  seen  that  the 
natural  love  of  God  towards  mankind  was  the  cause  of 
appointing  or  predestinating  Christ  to  suffer  for  the  sins 
of  the  whole  world — we  have  seen  that  our  Lord,  who  made 
Himself  a  sacrifice  for  our  sins,  did  it  in  the  bowels  of  a 
merciful  desire  that  no  man  might  perish — we  have  seen 
that  God,  nevertheless,  hath  found  most  just  occasion  to 
decree  the  death  and  condemnation  of  some — we  have  seen 
that  the  whole  cause  why  such  are  excluded  from  life 
resteth  altogether  in  themselves — we  have  seen  that  the 
natural  will  of  God  being  inclined  toward  all  men's  salva 
tion,  and  His  occasioned  will  having  set  down  the  death 
but  of  some  in  such  condemnation,  as  hath  been  shewed, 
it  must  needs  follow  that  of  the  rest  there  is  a  determinate 
ordinance  proceeding  from  the  good  pleasure  of  God, 
whereby  they  are,  and  have  been  before  all  worlds,  predes 
tinated  heirs  of  eternal  bliss— we  have  seen  that  in  Christ, 
the  Prince  of  God's  elect,  all  worthiness  was  foreseen ; 
that  in  the  elect  angels  there  was  not  foreseen  any 
matter  for  just  indignation  and  wrath  to  work  upon  ;  that 
in  all  other  God  foresaw  iniquity,  for  which  an  irrevocable 
sentence  of  death  and  condemnation  might  most  justly 
have  passed  over  all :  for  it  can  never  be  too  often  incul- 
.cated  that  touching  the  very  decree  of  endless  destruction 
and  death,  God  is  the  Judge  from  whom  it  cometh,  but 
man  the  cause  from  which  it  grew.  Salvation  contrari 
wise,  and  life  proceedeth  only  both  from  God  and  of  God. 
We  are  receivers  through  grace  and  mercy,  authors  through 

c  c  2 


388  Note  XIX. 


merit  and  desert  we  are  not,  of  our  own  salvation.  In  the 
children  of  perdition  we  must  always  remember  that  of  the 
Prophet,  "Thy  destruction,  0  Israel  is  of  thyself;"  lest 
we  teach  men  blasphemously  to  cast  the  blame  of  all  their 
misery  upon  (rod.  Again,  lest  we  take  to  ourselves  the 
glory  of  that  happiness,  which,  if  He  did  not  freely  and 
voluntarily  bestow,  we  should  never  be  made  partakers 
thereof,  it  must  ever,  in  the  election  of  saints,  be  remem 
bered,  that  to  choose  is  an  act  of  (rod's  good  pleasure,  which 
presupposeth  in  us  sufficient  cause  to  avert,  but  none  to 
deserve  it.  For  this  cause,  whereas  S.  Augustine  had  some 
time,  been  of  opinion  that  (rod  chose  Jacob  and  hated 
Esau,  the  one  in  regard  of  belief,  the  other  of  infidelity, 
which  was  foreseen,  his  mind  he  afterwards  delivered  thus  : 
"  Jacob  /  have  loved ;  behold  what  (rod  doth  freely  be 
stow.  7  have  hated  Esau  ;  behold  what  man  doth  justly 
deserve." ' —p.  737. 

There  is  some  departure  here  from  the  rigour  of  the 
real  Augustinian  language,  though  no  positive  inconsis 
tency  with  the  Augustinian  doctrine.  The  modification  is 
given  by  suppression  ;  '  We  have  seen,'  he  says,  '  that  the 
whole  cause  why  such  are  excluded  from  life  resteth  alto 
gether  in  themselves.''  S.  Augustine  would  say  this,  but 
he  would  explain  at  the  same  time  that  this  cause  in  man 
himself  was  not  foreseen  personal  sin,  but  original  sin. 
Hooker  suppresses  this  interpretation,  and  leaves  men's 
actual  foreseen  sins  as  the  cause,  according  to  the  natural 
meaning  of  his  phrase,  of  their  exclusion  from  the  decree 
of  predestination  to  life. 

A  third  statement  of  the  doctrine  of  predestination  re 
verts  to  a  stricter  line.  '  It  followeth,  therefore — 1 .  That 
Grod  hath  predestinated  certain  men,  not  all  men ;  2.  That 
the  cause  moving  Him  hereunto  was  not  the  foresight  of 
any  virtue  in  us  at  all;  3.  That  to  Him  the  number  of 
His  elect  is  definitely  known  ;  4.  That  it  cannot  be  but 
their  sins  must  condemn  them  to  whom  the  purpose  of  His 
saving  mercy  doth  not  extend;  5.  That  to  God's  fore 
known  elect  final  continuance  in  grace  is  given  ;  6.  That 
•inward  grace  whereby  to  be  saved  is  deservedly  not  given 
unto  all  men ;  7.  That  no  man  cometh  unto  Christ,  whom 


Note  XX.  389 


(rod  by  the  inward  grace  of  the  Spirit  draweth  not ;  8.  And 
that  it  is  not  in  every  one,  no,  not  in  any  man's  mere  ability, 
freedom,  and  power,  to  be  saved ;  no  man's  salvation  being 
possible  without  grace.  Howbeit,  God  is  no  favourer  of 
sloth,  and  therefore  there  can  be  no  such  absolute  decree 
touching  man's  salvation,  as  on  our  part  includeth  no 
necessity  of  care  and  travail,  but  shall  certainly  take  effect, 
whether  we  ourselves  do  wake  or  sleep.' — p.  752.  The 
difference  between  this  statement  and  the  Lambeth  Articles 
consists  in  an  omission  and  insertion,  softening  the  general 
effect  of  the  language,  while  the  substantial  ground  is  the 
same.  Thus  the  first  Lambeth  Article  mentions  reproba 
tion,  which  the  first  article  of  this  statement  does  not ;  but 
reprobation  is  implied  in  it.  Again,  the  7th  Lambeth 
Article  says,  c  Gratia  salutaris  non  tribuitur  universis  homi- 
nibus  qua  servari  possint,  si  voluerint.'  Hooker  inserts 
after  'is  not  given,'  '  desewedlyj  which  softens  the  effect, 
though  the  desert  may  be  admitted  by  the  most  rigid  pre- 
destinarian  in  the  shape  of  original  sin.  There  is  a  real 
difference  between  the  two  statements  of  doctrine,  in  the 
omission  in  Hooker's  of  the  doctrine  of  assurance,  which  is 
asserted  in  the  Lambeth  document. 


NOTE  XX.  p.  234. 

IN  the  controversy  in  the  Gallican  Church,  on  the  subject 
of  predestination,  which  arose  out  of  the  doctrinal  state 
ments  of  Gotteschalcus ;  which  was  conducted  by  Hinck- 
mar,  archbishop  of  Eheims,  on  the  one  side,  and  Kemigius, 
archbishop  of  Lyons,  on  the  other,  and  which  produced  the 
Councils  of  Quiercy  and  Valence ;  neither  side  appears  to 
have  sifted  the  question  to  its  foundation,  or  to  have 
understood  its  really  turning  points  ;  and  there  is,  accord 
ingly,  a  good  deal  of  arbitrary  adoption  and  arbitrary  re 
jection  of  language  on  both  sides  ;  a  good  deal  of  reliance 
on  distinctions  without  a  difference,  that  is  to  say,  on  words. 
The  doctrinal  statement  of  Gotteschalcus  embraces  the  fol 
lowing  five  points.—  Ushers  Gotteschalci  Historia,  p.  27. 
'  f.  Ante  omnia  secula,  et  antequam  quicquam  faceret 


3QO  Note  XX. 


a  principio  Deus  quos  voluit  praedestinavit  ad  regnum,  et 
quos  voluit  praedestinavit  ad  interitum. 

'  2.  Qui  praedestinati  sunt  ad  interitum  salvari  non  pos- 
sunt,  et  qui  praedestinati  sunt  ad  regnum  perire  non  possunt. 

'  3.  Deus  non  vult  omnes  homines  salvos  fieri,  sed  eos 
tantum  qui  salvantur :  et  quod  dicit  Apostolus  "  Qui  vult 
omnes  homines  salvos  fieri,"  illos  dicit  omnes  qui  tantum- 
modo  salvantur. 

6  4.  Christus  non  venit  ut  omnes  salvaret ;  nee  passus 
est  pro  omnibus,  nisi  solummodo  pro  his  qui  passionis  ejus 
salvantur  mysterio. 

'  5.  Postquam  primus  homo  libero  arbitrio  cecidit, 
nemo  nostrum  ad  bene  agendum,  sed  tantummodo  ad  male 
agendum,  libero  potest  uti  arbitrio.' 

This  statement  of  doctrine  is  substantially  Augustinian, 
and  nothing  more  ;  and  Remigius  approves  of  it  as  a  whole, 
making  an  exception  against  the  5th  proposition  ;  respect 
ing  the  meaning  of  which  he  must  have  been  under  some 
mistake,  for  the  language  expresses  no  more  than  what  is 
necessarily  involved  in  the  doctrine  of  original  sin.  With 
this  exception,  he  maintains  this  doctrinal  statement  to  be 
supported,  '  uno  sensu  uno  ore,  by  the  fathers  and  the 
Church,  and  appeals  to  the  undisputed  authority  of  Augus 
tine  in  their  favour — '  Beatissimi  patris  Augustini  ab 
omni  semper  ecclesia  venerabiliter  recepti  et  usque  in 
finem  seculi  recipiendi,  explaining  the  text  '  Qui  vult 
omnes  homines  salvos  fieri,'  apparently  contradicted  in  the 
3rd  proposition,  according  to  Augustine's  interpretation : 
(1.)  '  Ut  omnes  homines  omnia  hominum  genera  accipia- 
mus  : '  (2.)  c  non  quod  omnes  salventur,  sed  quod  nemo  nisi 
miserationis  ejus  voluntate  salvetur.'  On  the  4th  he  says : 
4  Si  inveniantur  aliqui  patrum  qui  etiam  pro  impiis  in  sua 
impietate  permansuris  Dominum  crucifixum  dicant ; '  if 
they  can  prove  it  out  of  Scripture  well,  if  not,  'quis  non 
videat  potiorem  illam  esse  auctoritatem,  quae  et  tarn  evi- 
denti  ratione  et  tarn  multiplici  Scripturarum  attestatione 
firmatur?  ....  Si  autem  placet,  propter  pacem,  non 
renuatur Nihil  tamen  definiatur.' — p.  34. 

The  Council  of  Quiercy  (Concilium  Carisiacense)  sum- 


Note  XX.  391 


moned  by  Hinckmar,  condemned  the  opinions  of  Gottes- 
chalcus,  and  published  a  counter  statement  of  doctrine, 
which  placed  the  doctrine  of  predestination  upon  a  ground 
of  foreknowledge  :  '  Secundum  prccscientiam  suam  quos 
per  gratiam  praedestinavit  ad  vitam  elegit  ex  massa  per- 
ditionis.  Caeteros  autem  quos  justitiae  judicio  in  massa 
perditionis  reliquit,  perituros  praescivit,  sed  non  ut  perirent 
praedestinavit.' — p.  67.  There  is  nothing  in  the  language 
of  this  proposition  to  which  the  most  rigid  predestinarian 
might  not  subscribe  ;  but  Remigius  interprets  the  prw- 
scientia  as  the  foreknowledge  of  the  individual's  good  life, 
and  as  implying  the  resting  of  the  doctrine  of  predesti 
nation  on  that  ground :  '  Quod  manifesto  contrarium  est, 
Catholicae  tidei.  Quia  Omnipotens  Deus  in  electione  eorum 
quos  prsedestinavit,  et  vocavit  ad  vitam  aeternam,  non  eorum 
merita  prsescivit.'  On  the  subject  of  the  Divine  will  to 
save  all  mankind  the  Council  decreed  :  *  Deus  omnipotens 
omnes  homines  sine  exceptione  vult  salvos  fieri,  licet 
non  omnes  salventur,'  to  which  proposition  Remigius  op 
poses  the  fact  of  the  heathen  world,  the  damnation  of 
which  he  considers  to  be  a  point  which  has  been  decided 
by  the  Church.  The  same  question  was  taken  up  by  the 
Council  in  another  form;  viz.  whether  Christ  did  or  did 
not  suffer  for  all  men,  which  it  decided  in  the  affirmative. 
4  Christus  Jesus  Dominus  noster,  sicut  nullus  homo  est  fuit 
vel  erit  cujus  natura  in  illo  assumpta  non  fuerit,  ita  nullus 
est  fuit  vel  erat  homo  pro  quo  passus  non  fuerit ;  licet  non 
omnes  passionis  ejus  mysterio  redimantur.'  On  this  argu 
ment  Remigius  remarks :  *  Quod  dicitur  quod  nullus  homo 
est  fuit  vel  erit  cujus  natura  in  Christo  assumpta  non 

fuerit Susceptio   iUa  naturae  humanae  in  Christo 

non  fuit  ex  necessitate  originis,  sed  ex  potestate  et  gratia 
et  misericordia  et  dignatione  suscipientis.  Quia  ergo  ista 
tarn  divina  et  singularis  generatio  homims  Chnsl 
aliqua  naturali  necessitate,  sed  sola  ejus  potestate  et  gratia 
et  misericordia  facta  est;  sic  per  omnes  generations  caro 
ejus  descendit;  sic  ex  eis  veraciter  natus  verus  homo  factus 
est  ut  quod  eiplacuit  miserendo,  et  sanawlo,  et  redimendo 
inde  assumeret,  quod  autem  non  placuit  reprobaret.- 


392  Note  XX. 


p.  79.  The  argument  is,  that  our  Lord's  assumption  of 
human  nature  being  itself  a  condescension,  and  special 
dispensation,  has  a  particular  limited  scope,  according  to 
the  Divine  pleasure,  and  only  brings  Him,  as  possessing 
this  nature,  into  communion  with  a  certain  portion  of 
those  whom  this  nature  includes,  and  is  only  beneficial  to 
this  portion. 

The  controversy,  which  is  thus  substantially  between 
the  Augustinian  and  the  Semi-Pelagian  doctrines,  exhibits, 
however,  much  confusion,  and  is  encumbered  by  false  dis 
tinctions.  A  great  deal  is  made  of  the  question  of  the 
duplex  prcedestinatio.  Hinckmar  admitting  a  predesti 
nation  to  life  eternal,  refuses  to  admit  a  predestination  to 
punishment,  and  insists  on  the  distinction  between  leaving 
men  in  their  sinful  state,  of  which  punishment  will  be 
the  consequence,  and  ordaining  men  to  such  punishment. 
'  Quosdam  autem,  sicut  praescivit,  non  ad  mortem  neque 
ad  ignem  prsedestinavit,  sed  in  massa  peccati  et  perdi- 
tionis  juste  deseruit,  a  qua  eos  prsedestinatione  sua  (i.  e. 
gratiae  praeparatione)  occulto  sed  noninjusto  judicionequa- 
quam  eripuit.' — p.  93.  But  the  most  rigid  predestinarian 
would  not  object  to  this  statement.  There  is  no  real  dis 
tinction  between  abandoning  men  to  a  certain  state,  of 
which  punishment  will  be  the  consequence,  and  ordaining 
them  to  that  punishment.  The  only  distinction  which 
would  make  a  difference,  respects  the  nature  of  this  sinful 
state,  to  which  men  are  abandoned,  whether  it  is  original 
sin  or  their  own  personal  perseverance  in  sin.  The  aban 
donment  of  a  certain  portion  of  mankind  to  the  state  of 
sin  in  which  they  are  born,  is  predestinarian  reprobation, 
whether  we  express  it  as  abandonment  to  sin,  or  as  ordain 
ing  to  punishment.  Eemigius  exposes  the  irrelevancy  of 
this  distinction :  4  Mirum  valde  est  quomodo  negare  con- 
tendunt  eum  seternam  ipsorum  damnationem  praedesti- 
nasse,  quos  jam  ab  ipso  mundi  exordio,  cum  primus  homo 
peccavit,  et  omne  humanum  genus  ex  se  propagandum 
unam  massam  damnationis  et  perditionis  fecit,  manifeste 
dicant  in  eadem  massa  damnationis  et  perditionis  justo  Dei 
judicio  deputatos  et  derelictos.  Quid  est  enim  massa  dam- 


Note  XXL  393 


nationis  et  perditionis  ab  initio  mundi  divine  judicio  effecta, 
nisi  eodem  divino  judicio  seterase  damnationi  et  perdition! 
destinata  et  tradita  ? ' — p.  93. 

Hinckmar  insists  again  on  the  Augustinian  definition 
of  predestination  as  gratice  prwparatio  (p.  94.),  as  favour 
ing  his  denial  of  any  prcedestinatio  liumnationis ;  to 
which  Eemigius  replies,  that  a  predestination  to  life  did 
not  exclude  the  predestination  to  punishment.  It  is  ob 
vious  that  the  whole  of  this  discussion  is  verbal,  and  is 
not  concerned  with  the  real  grounds  and  substance  of  the 
controversy. 

NOTE  XXI.  p.  267. 

I  SEE  no  substantial  difference  between  the  Augustiniau 
and  Thomist,  and  the  Calvinist  doctrine  of  predestination. 
S.  Augustine  and  Calvin  alike  hold  an  eternal  Divine 
decree,  which,  antecedently  to  all  action,  separates  one 
portion  of  mankind  from  another,  and  ordains  one  to  ever 
lasting  life  and  the  other  to  everlasting  punishment.  That 
is  the  fundamental  statement  of  both ;  and  it  is  evident, 
that  while  this  fundamental  statement  is  the  same,  there 
can  be  no  substantial  difference  in  the  two  doctrines.  This 
statement  is  the  sum  and  substance  of  the  doctrine  of  pre 
destination :  and  therefore  if  Augustine  and  Calvin  agree 
in  this  statement,  it  may  be  pronounced  in  limine  idle  to 
talk  of  any  real  difference  between  their  respective  doctrines 
on  this  subject.  Let  persons  only  consider  what  this  state 
ment  is,  and  what  it  necessarily  involves,  and  they  must 
see  it  is  impossible  that  there  can  be  any  real  distinction 
of  doctrine  on  the  particular  subject  of  predestination,  after 
this  statement  has  been  agreed  in  by  the  two.  Those  who 
suppose  that  S.  Augustine  differs  from  Calvin  in  his  doc 
trine  of  predestination,  do  not  really  know  the  doctrine 
which  S.  Augustine  held  on  the  subject,  and  suppose  it  to 
be  different  from  what  it  was.  They  suppose  it  to  be  a 
qualified  doctrine  of  predestination  to  privileges  and  means 
of  grace ;  or  they  have  some  general  idea  that  S.  Augustine 
did  not  hold  such  a  doctrine  as  Calvin  held-an  assump 
tion  which  settles  to  begin  with  the  question  for  them. 


394  Note  XXL 


But  if  Augustine's  doctrine  was  the  one  which  has  been 
here  stated  to  be  his,  and  if  it  was  expressed  in  the  above 
fundamental  statement,  it  must  be  seen  immediately  that 
it  is  the  same  as  Calvin's  doctrine. 

And  the  identity  of  the  two  doctrines  thus  apparent  at 
first  sight,  and  from  the  fundamental  statement  by  which 
they  are  expressed,  will  appear  further  from  the  cautions 
and  checks  by  which  each  guards  the  doctrine.  We  may 
be  referred  to  various  cautions  and  checks  which  S.  Augus 
tine  and  his  followers  in  the  schools  appended  to  the  doc 
trine  of  predestination  ;  from  which  it  will  be  argued  that 
the  doctrine  was  not  the  same  as  the  Calvinistic  one.  But 
it  will  be  found  on  examination  that  Calvin  has  just  the 
same  cautions  and  checks. 

The  checks  and  cautions,  which  S.  Augustine  and  his 
followers  in  the  schools  appended  to  their  doctrine  of  pre 
destination,  were  substantially  these  two :  that  God  was 
not  the  author  of  evil ;  and  that  man  had  ivill,  and  was, 
as  having  a  will,  responsible  for  his  own  sins.  The  doctrine 
of  predestination  was  relieved  from  two  consequences  which 
appeared  to  follow  from  it.  If  God  is  the  sole  author  and 
cause  of  our  goodness,  how  is  He  not  the  author  and  cause 
of  our  sin  too  ?  If  we  are  bound  to  refer  the  one  to  Him, 
why  not  the  other  ?  The  doctrine  thus  led  to  the  conse 
quence  that  God  was  the  author  of  evil.  This  consequence, 
then,  was  cut  off  by  a  formal  check,  accompanied  with  more 
or  less  of  argument,  that  God  was  not  the  author  of  evil. 
In  the  same  way  the  doctrine  of  predestination,  maintain 
ing  sin  as  necessary,  led  to  the  result  that  man  was  not 
responsible  for  his  sins.  This  consequence  then  was  cut 
off,  as  the  former  was,  by  a  formal  check,  also  accompanied 
by  more  or  less  of  argument — that  man  had  a  will,  that  he 
sinned  with  this  will  or  willingly,  and  that  sinning  willingly 
he  was  responsible  for  his  sins. 

But  this  whole  check  to  the  doctrine  of  predestination, 
viz.  that  man  is  responsible  for  his  own  sins,  and  not  God^ 
is  appended  to  that  doctrine  by  Calvin  just  as  much  as  it 
is  by  Augustine.  Indeed,  no  one  who  professed  to  be  a 
Christian  could  teach  the  doctrine  without  such  a  check.  No 


Note  XXL  395 


Christian  of  any  school  could  make  God  the  author  of  evil, 
or  say  that  sin  was  not  blameworthy. 

First,  Calvin  protests  generally  against  fatalism  ;  i.e. 
any  doctrine  that  denies  contingency^  and  asserts  all  events  to 
take  place  according  to  a  certain  fixed  and  inevitable  order, 
which  could  not  have  been  otherwise :  '  Vetus  ista  calumnia 
fuit,  qua  se  Augustinus  injuste  fuisse  graviitum  alicubi 
conqueritur :  nunc  obsoletam  esse  decebat.  Certe  horai- 
nibus  probis  et  ingenuis,  si  modo  iidem  docti  sint,  valde 
indigna  est.  Qualis  fuerit  Stoicorum  imaginatio,  notuin 
est.  Fatum  suum  texebant  ex  Gordiano  causarum  com- 
plexu  :  in  quem  cum  Deum  ipsum  involuerant,  fabricabant 
aureas  catenas,  ut  est  in  fabulis,  quibus  Deum  vincirent, 
ut  subjectus  esset  inferioribus  causis.  Stoicos  liodie 
imitantur  astrologi,  quibus  fatalis  ex  stellarum  positu 
dependet  rerum  necessitas.  Valeant  igitur  cum  suo  fato 
Stoici :  nobis  libera  Dei  voluntas  omnium  sit  moderatrix. 
Sed  contingentiam  tolli  ex  mundo  valde  absurdum  est. 
Omitto  qua3  in  Scholis  usitatas  sunt  distinctiones.  Quod 
afferam  simplex,  meo  judicio,  et  minime  coactum  erit, 
deinde  ad  vitae  usum  accommodatum.  Sic  evenire  necesse 
est  quod  statuit  Deus,  ut  tamen  neque  precise  neque 
suapte  natura  necessarium  sit,  Exemplum  in  Christi 
ossibus  familiare  habeo.  Christum  corpus  habuisse  prorsus 
nostro  simile  Scriptura  testatur.  Quare  fragilia  illi  ossa 
fuisse  fateri  nemo  sanus  dubitabit.  Sed  alia  mihi  videtur 
ac  separata  qusestio,  an  ullum  os  ejus  frangi  potuerit. 
Nam  integra  omnia  et  illassa  manere,  quia  fixo  Dei  decreto 
ita  statutum  erat,  necessario  oportuit.  Nee  vero  quod  a 
receptis  loquendi  formis  de  necessitate  secundum  quid  et 
absoluta,  item  consequents  et  consequential  abhorream, 
ita  loquor;  sed  ne  quae  lectoris  argutia  impediat,  qum 
agnoscatvelrudissimusquisqueverum  esse  quod  dico.  .  .  . 
Ac  memoria  tenendum  est,  quod  ante  posui,  ubi  Deus  per 
medias  et  inferiores  causas  virtutem  suam  exerit,  non  e: 
ab  illis  separandam.  Temulenta  est  ista  cogitatio: 
crevit  Deus  quid  futurum  sit;  ergo  curam  et  studmm 
nostrum  interponere  supervacuuin  est.  Atqui,  cum  nob 
quid  agendum  sit,  prascribat,  et  virtutis  suae  organa  n 


396  Note  XXI. 


esse  velit ;  fas  nobis  est  ne  putemus  separare  quae  ille 
conjunxit.  .  .  .  Ergo  quantum  ad  futurum  tempus,  quia 
nos  adhuc  rerum  eventus  latent,  perinde  ad  officium  suum 
intentus  esse  quisque  debet,  ac  si  nihil  in  utramvis  partem 
constitutum  foret.  Vel  ut  magis  proprie  loquar,  talem  in 
omnibus  qua?  ex  Dei  mandato  aggreditur,  successum 
sperare  debet,  ut  in  rebus  sibi  incognitis  contingentiam 
cum  certa  Dei  providentia  conciliet.  .  .  .  Hac  voce  pius 
vir  se  divinae  providentiae  organum  constitui  agnoscet. 
Hac  eadem  promissione  fretus,  alacriter  ad  opus  se  accinget, 
quia  persuasus  erit,  non  fortuitam  se  operam  in  aere 
jacere.  .  .  .  Invocationem  adeo  non  impedit,  ut  potius 
stabiliat.  .  .  .  Non  sequitur  quin  rerum  adversarum  cul- 
pam  vel  ignavia  nostra,  vel  temeritas,  vel  incogitantia, 
vel  aliud  vitium  merito  sustineat.' — De  Prcedestinatione, 
vol.  x.  p.  725. 

Here  is  the  doctrine  of  the  schools  respecting  mediate 
and  secondary  causes ;  that  events  take  their  character 
from  the  causes  that  produce  them,  and  are  necessary  or 
contingent,  according  as  their  causes  are  the  one  or  the 
other.  Calvin  refers  in  the  passage  to  the  distinctions  of 
the  schools,  with  which  he  says  he  does  not  disagree ;  and 
his  statement  is  only  another  form  of  that  of  Aquinas : 
'  Deus  omnia  movet  secundum  eorum  conditionem ;  ita 
quod  ex  causis  necessariis  per  motionem  divinam  sequuntur 
effectus  ex  necessitate,  ex  causis  autem  contingentibus 
sequuntur  effectus  contingentes.'  Supra,  p.  254.  He 
protests  against  indolence  or  carelessness  in  temporal  or 
spiritual  matters,  as  a  wholly  illegitimate  result  to  fasten 
on  his  doctrine  ;  and  says  that  people  must  act  as  if  events 
were  contingent,  and  not  suppose  that,  because  events  are 
foreordained,  that  therefore  they  are  foreordained  without 
the  necessary  means  to  bring  them  about ;  which  means 
lie  in  our  own  conduct  and  course  of  action. 

Thus,  while  maintaining  the  Divine  infallible  decree  of 
predestination,  he  protests  against  men  making  that  decree 
their  starting  point,  and  putting  it  in  prior  order  to  action, 
in  their  own  ideas  and  thoughts  about  themselves  :  'Neque 
ego  sane  ad  arcanam  Dei  electionem  homines  ablego,  ut 


Note  XXL  397 


inde  salutem  hiantes  expectent :  sed  recte  ad  Christum 
pergere  jubeo,  in  quo  nobis  proposita  est  salus ;  qua? 
alioqui  in  Deo  abscondita  lateret.  Nam  quisquis  planam 
fidei  viam  non  ingreditur,  illi  Dei  electio  nihil  (mam 
exitialis  erit  labarynthus.  .  .  .  Hinc  minime  faciendum 
est  exordium,  quid  de  nobis  ante  mundum  conditum 
Deus  statuerit ;  sed  quid  de  paterno  ejus  amore  nobis  in 
Christo  sit  patefactum,  et  quotidie  per  evangelium  Christus 
ipse  prsedicet.  Nihil  altius  nobis  quserendum,  quam  ut 
Dei  filii  simus.'— Vol.  x.  p.  708. 

After  this  protest  against  fatalism,  Calvin  proceeds  to 
acknowledge  a  true  will  in  man ;  that  he  acts  willingly 
and  without  constraint;  and  that  consequently  the  blame 
of  his  sins  rests  entirely  upon  himself;  and  that  to  charge 
(xod  with  the  authorship  of  them  is  impiety  and  blasphemy. 
The  ground  he  takes  is  strictly  Aiigustinian  :  'Voluntas, 
quia  inseparabilis  est  ab  hominis  natura,  non  periit;  sed 
pravis  cupiditatibus  devincta  fuit,  ut  nihil  rectum  appetere 
queat.' — Instit.  1.  2.  c.  2.  s.  12.  'Non  voluntate  privatus 
est  homo  quum  in  hanc  necessitatem  se  addixit.  sed  volun- 
tatis  sanitate.  ...  Si  liberam  Dei  voluntatem  in  bene 
agendo  non  impedit,  quod  necesse  est  ilium  bene  agere : 
si  diabolus,  qui  nonnisi  male  agere  potest,  voluntate  tamen 
peccat;  qui  s  hominem  ideo  minus  voluntarie  peccare  dicet, 
quod  sit  peccandi  necessitati  obnoxius  ?  Hanc  necessitatem 
quum  ubique  praedicet  Augustinus,  dum  etiain  invidiose 
Coelestii  cavillo  urgeretur,  ne  turn  quidem  asserere  dubi- 

tavit "  Per   libertatem  factum  est  ut  esset  homo  cum 

peccato :  sed  jam  poenalis  vitiositas  subsecumta  ex  libertate 
fecit  necessitatem."  Ac  quoties  incidit  ejus  rei  mentio, 
non  dubitat  in  hunc  modum  loqui,  de  necessaria  peccati 
servitute.  Ha3C  igitur  distinctionis  summa  observetur, 
hominem,  ut  vitiatus  est  ex  lapsu,  volentem  quidem  pec- 
care,  non  invitum  nee  coactum:  affectione  ammi  yro- 
pinquissima.  .  .  .  Augustino  subscribens  Bernardus  ita 
scribit,  "Solus  homo  inter  animalia  liber:  et  tamen,  m- 
terveniente  peccato,  patitur  quandam  vim  et  ipse,  sed  a 
voluntate  non  a  natura,  ut  ne  sic  guidem  ingenita  liter- 
tate  privetur.  Quod  enim  voluntarium  etjam  liberum. 


398  Note  XX I. 


Et  paulo  post — "  Ita  nescio  quo  pravo  et  miro  modo  ipsa 
sibi  voluntas,  peccato  quidem  in  deterius  mutata,  necessi- 
tatem  facit ;  ut  nee  necessitas  (cum  voluntaria  sit)  excu- 
sare  valeat  voluntatem,  nee  voluntas  (quum  sit  illecta) 
excludere  necessitatem."  Est  enim  necessitas  haec  quo- 
dammodo  voluntaria.'  L.  2.  c.  3.  s.  5.  'Voluntatem  dico 
aboleri  non  quatenus  est  voluntas,  quia  in  hominis  conver- 
sione  integrum  manet  quod  primse  est  naturae ;  creari 
etiam  novam  dico,  non  ut  voluntas  esse  incipiat,  sed  ut 
vertatur  ex  mala  in  bonam.' — L.  2.  c.  3.  s.  6. 

Upon  the  ground,  then,  of  the  existence  of  this  true 
will  in  man,  he  lays  the  responsibility  of  sin  entirely  upon 
man  himself :  '  Nego  peccatum  ideo  minus  debere  impu- 
tari,  quod  necessarium  est.' — Instit.  1.  2.  c.  4.  s.  5.  '  Eant 
mine  qui  Deum  suis  vitiis  inscribere  audent,  quia  dicimus 
naturaliter  vitiosos  esse  homines.  ...  A  carnis  nostrae 
culpa  non  a  Deo  nostra  perditio  est.' — L.  2.  c.  1.  s.  10. 
'  Respondeant,  possintne  inficiari  causam  contiimaciaa  pra- 
vam  suam  voluntatem  fuisse.  Si  mali  fontem  intra  se 
reperiant,  quid  vestigandis  extraneis  causis  inhiant,  ne 
sibi  ipsi  fuisse  exitii  authores  videantur.' — L.  2.  c.  5.  s.  11. 
'Non  extrinseco  impulsu,  sed  spontaneo  cordis  affectu, 
scientes  ac  volentes  peccarunt.' — De  Freed,  vol.  x.  p.  709. 
'  Ad  reatum  satis  superque  voluntaria  transgressio 
sufficit.  Neque  enim  propria  genuinaque  peccati  causa 
est  arcanum  Dei  consilium,  sed  aperta  hominis  voluntas. 
....  Intus  mali  sui  causam  quum  inveniat  homo,  quid 
circuire  prodest,  ut  earn  in  coelo  quserat?  Palam  in  eo 
apparet  culpa  quod  peccare  voluerit.  Cur  in  coali  adyta 
perrumpens  in  labarynthum  se  demergit  ?  Quanquam  ut 
per  immensas  ambages  vagando,  deludere  se  homines 
conentur,  nunquam  ita  se  obstupefacient,  quin  sensum 
peccati  in  cordibus  suis  insculptum  retineant.  Hominem 
igitur,  quern  ipsius  sui  conscientia  damnat,  frustra  absol- 
vere  tendit  impietas.' — De  Freed,  vol.  x.  p.  711.  'Neque 
in  Deum  transferimus  indurationis  causam  acsi  non  sponte 
propriaque  malitia  seipsos  ad  pervicaciam  acuerent.' — 
p.  727.  '  Quum  perditis  exitium  denuntiat  Scriptura, 
causam  in  seternum  Dei  consilium  minime  rejicit,  vel 


Note  XXL 


399 


transfert;  sed  residere  in  ipsis  testatur.  Nos  vero  non 
ideo  reprobos  tradimus  destitui  Dei  Spiritu,  ut  sceleruui 
suorum  culpam  in  Deum  imputent.  Quicquid  peccant 
homines  sibi  imputent.  Quod  si  quis  subterfugiat,  con- 
scientiae  vinculis  fortius  constringi  dico,  quam  ut  se  a  justa 
damnatione  expediat.  ...  Si  quis  obstrepat,  prompta  est 
exceptio,  Perditio  tua  ex  te  Israel.  .  .  .  Non  audiendi 
sunt  qui  procul  remotas  causas  e  nubibus  accersunt,  ut 
culpse  suae  notitiam,  quae  et  eorum  cordibus  penitus  in- 
sidet,  neque  occulta  latere  potest,  utcunque  obscurent.'— 
p.  721. 

The  cautions  and  checks,  then,  which  Calvin  appends 
to  the  doctrine  of  predestination  are  substantially  the  same 
with  those  we  find  appended  to  the  doctrine  in  S.  Augustine 
and  the  Augustinian  schoolmen.  Predestination,  according 
to  Calvin,  is  no  excuse  for  spiritual  indolence  or  careless 
ness  ;  it  does  not  detract  at  all  from  man's  responsibility, 
who  is  as  much  to  blame  for  his  sins  upon  this  doctrine  as 
upon  the  contrary  one;  and  therefore  whether  we  look  to 
the  fundamental  statement  of  the  doctrine,  or  to  the  checks 
and  cautions  with  which  it  is  surrounded,  the  doctrine  of 
Calvin  on  this  subject  is  seen  to  be  the  same  as  that  of 
S.  Augustine. 

It  is  true  Calvin  condemns  the  scholastic  treatment  of 
this    question,    and   after    S.    Augustine   nobody,   except 
perhaps  S.  Bernard,  seems  to  satisfy  him.     But  this  com 
plaint  is  qualified.     He  acknowledges,  in  the  first  place, 
that  however  their  own  interpretations  of  such  doctrines 
may  have  fallen  short,  the  fundamental  doctrines  of  the 
schools  were  Augustinian  and  orthodox  on  this  question : 
« Qui  postea  secuti  sunt,  alii  post  alios  in  detenus  contmuo 
delapsi  sunt;    donee  eo  ventum  est  ut  vulgo   putaretur 
homo  sensuali  tandem  parte  corruptus.  .  .  .  Interea 
tavit  illud  in  ore  omnium,  naturalia  dona  in  homne 
corrupta  esse,  supernaturalia  vero  ablata.     Sed  quorsum 
tenderet,  vix  cente^imus   quisque  leviter  gustavit. 
certe  si  dilucide  tradere  velim  qualis  sit  naturae  corrupt  € 
his  verbis  facile   sim  contentus.'—Instit.  1.  2.  c.  As.  4 
He  admits  here  a  certain  foundation  in  the  teaching  of  the 


400  Note  XXL 


schools  which  was  orthodox,  though  it  was  overlaid  with 
weak  or  injurious  commentary.  In  the  next  place  he 
makes  a  distinction  amongst  schoolmen;  and  while  he 
complains  of  the  refinements  of  Lombard  and  Aquinas, 
regards  them  as  in  the  main  orthodox :  '  Longiore  inter- 
vallo  a  recentioribus  sophistis  differed — Inst.  1.  2.  c.  2. 
s.  6.  The  older  commentators  he  considers  to  have  main 
tained,  though  with  too  little  boldness  and  openness,  and 
with  too  great  an  appearance  of  compromise,  the  Augus- 
tinian  ground.  Thus  he  complains  of  Lombard's  use  of 
the  term  freewill :  '  Ac  principal  em  quidem  causam  in 
gratia  esse  non  negant :  sed  eo  tamen  contendunt  non  ex- 
cludi  liberum  arbitrium,  per  quod  sit  omne  meritum. 
Neque  id  tradunt  posteriores  modo  sophistse,  sed  eorum 
Pythagoras  Lombardus ;  quern,  si  cum  istis  compares, 
sanum  et  sobrium  esse  dicas.  Mirse  profecto  csecitatis 
fait,  quum  Augustinum  toties  in  ore  haberet,  non  vidisse 
quanta  solicitudine  vir  ille  caverit  ne  ulla  ex  bonis  operibus 
glorise  particula  in  hominem  derivaretur.' — Instit.  1.  3. 
c.  15.  s.  7.  '  Magister  sententiarum  duplicem  gratiam 
necessariam  esse  nobis  docet,  quo  reddamur  ad  opus  bonum 
idonei.  Alteram  vocat  Operantem,  qua  fit  ut  efficaciter 
velimus  bonum  ;  Cooperantem  alteram  quse  bonam  volun- 
tatem  sequitur  adjuvando.  In  qua  parti tione  hoc  mini 
displicet,  quod  dum  Gratias  Dei  tribuit  efficacem  boni 
appetitum,  innuit  hominem  jam  suapte  natura  bonum 
quodammodo  licet  inefficaciter  appetere.  ...  In  secundo 
membro  ambiguitas  me  offendit,  quse  perversam  genuit 
interpretationem.  Ideo  enim  putarunt  nos  secundse  Dei 
gratise  cooperari,  quod  nostri  juris  sit  primam  gratiain  vel 
respuendo  irritam  facere,  v*l  obedienter  sequendo  con- 
firmare.  .  .  .  Hcec  duo  notare  obiter  libuit,  ut  videas 
jam  lector,  quantum  a  sanioribus  scholasticis  dissen- 
tiam.  .  .  .  Utcunque,  ex  hac  tamen  parti  tione  intelligimus 
qua  ratione  liberum  dederint  arbitrium  homini.  Pro- 
nuntiat  enim  tandem  Lombardus,  non  liberi  arbitrii 
ideo  nos  esse,  quod  ad  bonum  vel  ad  malum  vel  agendum 
vel  cogitandum  perceque  polleamus,  sed  duntaxat  quod 
coactione  soluti  sumus.  .  .  .  Optime  id  quidem,  sed 


Note  XXL  4oi 


quorsum  attinebat,  rem  tantulam  adeo  superbo  titulo  in- 

signire Equidem  Xoyofjua^ias  abominor,  quibus 

frustra  ecclesia  fatigatur;  sed  religiose  censeo  cavendas 
eas  voces  quse  absurdum  aliquid  sonant,  proesertim  ubi 
perniciose  erratur.  Quotus  enim  quaeso  qnisque  est,  qui, 
dum  assignari  homini  liberum  arbitrium  audit,  non  statim 
concipit  ilium  esse  et  mentis  sure  et  voluntatis  dominum, 
qui  flectere  se  in  utramvis  partem  a  seipso  possit?  Atqui 
(dicet  quispiam)  sublatum  erit  hujusmodi  perictilum,  si  de 
significatione  diligenter  plebs  admoneatur.  Imo  vero  cum 
in  falsitatem  ultro  humanum  ingenium  propendeat,  citius 
errorem  ex  verbulo  uno  hauriet,  quam  veritatem  ex  prolixa 
oratione.' — Instit.  1.  2.  c.  2.  ss.  6,  7. 

It  is  evident  that  Calvin's  quarrel  with  Lombard  here 
is  about  the  use  of  a  word,  and  not  about  a  substantial 
point  of  doctrine.  In  substantial  doctrine  he  considers 
they  both  agree,  though  he  thinks  Lombard's  distinction 
of  operative  and  co-operative  grace  so  worded  as  to  tend 
to  mislead,  and  though  he  objects  to  the  use  of  the  word 
freewill  altogether,  which  he  thinks  will  always  lie  practi 
cally  understood  by  the  mass  of  men  in  the  sense  of  a  self- 
determining  will.  He  would  not  object  to  the  word  if 
Lombard's  sense  could  be  fastened  upon  it ;  but  he  differs 
from  him  as  to  the  expediency  of  using  a  term  on  which  it 
will  be  so  difficult  to  fasten  this  meaning,  and  which  will 
always  more  readily  suggest  another  and  an  erroneous  one. 
His  disagreement  with  Lombard  is  thus  of  the  same  kind 
with  the  disagreement  noticed  above,  p.  267,  with  Aquinas, 
which  was  concerned  with  language  and  mode  of  statement 
as  distinguished  from  substantial  doctrine. 

Calvin's  reflections  on  the  schoolmen,  then,  do  not 
appear  to  prove  any  substantial  difference  on  the  subject 
of  predestination,  grace,  and  freewill,  between  himself  and 
the  Augustinian  portion  of  the  schoolmen.  And  this  con 
clusion  obliges  me  to  notice  some  remarks  of  Pascal  bearing 
on  this  question  in  the  Provincial  Letters. 

I  must  admit,  then,  that  I  have  against  me,  on  this 
point,  the  authority  of  Pascal,  who  endeavours  in  the  Pro 
vincial  Letters  to  prove  a  strong  distinction  between  the 

DD 


402  Note  XXL 


doctrine  of  Calvin  and  the  Reformers,  and  the  Augustinian 
and  Jansenist  doctrine,  on  the  subject  of  grace  and  free 
will.  But  I  admit  it  the  more  readily,  for  the  obvious 
consideration,  that  Pascal  was  not  in  a  position  to  ackow- 
ledge  such  an  identity  in  the  doctrine  of  the  two  schools. 
As  an  attached  member  of  the  Roman  communion,  he  was 
obliged  by  his  position  to  disconnect  his  own  and  his 
party's  doctrine  as  much  as  possible  from  that  of  the 
Reformers,  and  to  make  out  a  wide  difference  between 
them.  The  Jansenists  were  attacked  on  all  sides  as  dis 
affected  members  of  the  Roman  Church,  Reformers  in 
heart,  though  outwardly  Catholics.  They  disowned  and 
repelled  the  charge  with  indignation.  But  what  is  the 
natural,  the  irresistible  disposition  of  a  religious  party 
under  such  circumstances,  with  respect  to  the  doctrines 
upon  which  such  a  charge  is  founded  ?  It  is,  of  course,  to 
make  out,  in  any  way  they  can,  a  difference  between  these 
doctrines  and  those  of  the  other  school,  with  which  their 
opponents  identify  them.  Under  such  circumstances,  the 
authority  even  of  Pascal  has  not,  upon  the  present  ques 
tion,  any  irresistible  weight.  And  when  we  come  to 
examine  his  argument,  and  the  reasons  upon  which  he 
erects  the  difference  he  does  between  the  Augustinian  and 
the  Calvinistic  doctrine  of  grace,  any  weight  that  we  might 
previously  have  been  inclined  to  give  his  conclusion  is 
much  diminished. 

Every  reader  of  the  Provincial  Letters  will  remember 
the  great  argumentative  clearness  and  penetration,  sup 
ported  by  the  keenest  irony,  with  which  Pascal  proves  the 
identity,  under  a  guise  of  verbal  difference,  of  the  Thomist 
doctrine  of  grace  with  the  Jansenist.  The  Thomist  mem 
bers  of  the  Sorbonne,  siding  with  the  Jesuits  against  the 
Jansenists,  had  distinguished  their  own  doctrine  of  grace 
from  that  of  the  Jansenists  by  a  particular  term ;  to  the 
use  of  which,  though  apparently  counter  to  their  own 
Augustinian  doctrine,  they  had  by  an  arrangement  con 
sented  among  themselves,  but  to  which  the  Jansenists 
would  not  consent.  This  was  the  term  prochain — proxi- 
mus.  The  Thoinists  maintained  that  every  Christian  had 


Note  XXL  403 


the  pouvoir  prochain  to  obey  the  Divine  commandments, 
and  so  attain  eternal  life ;  while  the  Jansenists,  admitting 
the  power  of  any  Christian  to  do  this,  would  not  admit 
that  this  power  was  prochain ;  the  distinction  being,  that 
the  term  power  of  itself,  in  the  Augustinian  sense  (even 
supposing  every  one  had  such  power),  committed  them  to 
no  assertion  contrary  to  the  exclusive  and  predestinarian 
doctrine,  which  made  salvation  only  really  attainable  by 
the  elect.  For  power  in  the  Augustinian  sense  onlv  means 
potestas  si  vult;  in  which  sense  the  admission  that  all 
Christians  have  the  power  is  not  at  all  opposed  to  the 
doctrine  that  only  the  elect  have  the  will  given  to  them 
to  lead  that  good  life  on  which  salvation  depends.  J>ut 
the  addition  of  the  term  '  prochain '  to  'power'  seemed  to 
fix  on  the  word  power  a  freewill  sense,  as  distinguished 
from  the  Augustinian  one ;  and  to  imply  the  admission 
that  every  one  had  the  full  and  complete  power,  in  the 
natural  sense  of  the  term,  to  attain  eternal  life, — which 
was  opposed  to  the  predestinarian  doctrine.  The  Jan 
senists,  therefore,  would  not  admit  the  term  'prochain.' 
Now  it  is  evident  that  in  this  refusal  they  laid  themselves 
open  to  a  charge  of  inconsistency ;  for  if  they  were  ready 
to  admit  '  power '  in  an  artificial  sense,  they  might  have 
admitted  'prochain'  in  an  artificial  sense  too.  But 
Pascal  adroitly  diverts  attention  from  the  inconsistency  of 
the  Jansenists  in  their  meaning  of  the  word  poiver,  to  the 
inconsistency  of  the  Thomists  in  the  meaning  they  gave 
to  '  power  prochain ; '  separating,  as  the  latter  did  from 
the  Jansenists,  on  the  express  ground  of  this  phrase  being 
refused,  when  they  themselves  held  the  phrase  in  a  Jan- 
senist  sense — i.e.  so  as  to  be  consistent  with  the  exclusive 
and  predestinarian  doctrine :  '  Mais  quoi !  mon  pere,  s'il 
manque  quelque  chose  a  ce  pouvoir,  1'appelez-vous  pro- 
chain  ?  et  direz-vous,  par  exemple,  qu'un  homme  ait,  la 
nuit,  et  sous  aucune  lumiere,  U  pouvoir  de  voir?  Oui- 
da,  il  1'auroit  selon  nous,  s'il  n'est  pas  aveugle.'— 1st  Letter. 
It  is  obvious  that  in  this  sense  the  whole  Chnstian  body 
might  have  the  pouvoir  prochain,  and  still  not  a  real  and 
bond  fide  power  of  attaining  salvation,  which  might  t 

D  D  2 


404  Note  XXL 


be  confined  to  the  elect.  He  thus  shows  that  the  Thomists 
only  differed  from  the  Jansenists  in  the  use  of  a  word,  and 
agreed  with  them  in  meaning  and  doctrine.  And  he 
proves  the  same  thing  in  the  case  of  the  term  '  grace 
suffisantej  which  the  Thomists  admitted  while  the  Jan 
senists  rejected  it:  'Mais  enfin,  mon  pere,  cette  grace 
donnee  a  tous  les  hommes  est  suffisante  ?  Oui  dit-il.  Et 
neanmoins  elle  n'a  nul  effet  sans  grace  efficace  ?  Cela  est 
vrai,  dit-il.  Et  tous  les  hommes  ont  la  suffisante,  con- 
tinuai-je,  et  tous  n'o.it  pas  efficace?  II  est  vrai,  dit-il. 
C'est-a-dire,  lui  dis-je,  que  tous  n'ont  assez  de  grace,  et  que 
tous  n'en  ont  pas  assez ;  c'est-a-dire,  que  cette  grace  suffit, 
quoiqu'elle  ne  suffise  pas  ;  c'est-a-dire,  qu'elle  est  suflSsante 
de  nom,  et  insuffisante  en  effet.' — 2nd  Letter.  The 
Thomists  then  admitted  the  term  '  suffisante '  in  an  artifi 
cial  sense,  which  enabled  them  to  say  that  such  sufficient 
grace  was  given  to  all,  while  they  really  held  that  sufficient 
grace,  in  the  natural  sense  of  the  word,  was  only  given  to 
the  elect.  And  therefore  Pascal  shows  in  this  instance 
again,  that  the  Thomists  only  differed  from  the  Jansenists 
upon  a  word,  while  they  agreed  with  them  in  meaning 
and  doctrine. 

But  the  same  argument  by  which  Pascal  proves  that 
the  Thomists  of  the  Sorbonne  agreed  in  doctrine  with  the 
Jansenists,  proves  equally  that  the  Jansenist  or  Augus- 
tinian  agreed  in  doctrine  with  the  Calvinist.  The  eigh 
teenth  Provincial  Letter  contains  a  long  statement  and 
argument  to  show  that  the  Jansenist  doctrine  of  efficacious 
grace  differed  from  the  Calvinist :  the  argument  resting 
upon  a  particular  admission  with  respect  to  this  grace, 
which  the  Calvinists  did  not  make,  and  the  Jansenists  did 
—the  admission,  viz.  that  man  had  the  power  to  resist  this 
grace.  He  raises  on  this  ground  a  broad  distinction  be 
tween  the  Jansenists  and  the  Calvinists ;  that  the  Jan 
senists  allow  freewill,  while  the  Calvinists  represent  man 
as  moved  like  an  inanimate  machine.  I  will  extract  at 
some  length  from  this  part  of  the  Letter. 

'  Vous  verriez,  mon  pere,  que  non-seulement  ils  tien- 


Note  XXL  405 


nent  qu'on  resiste  effectivement  a  ces  graces  faibles,  qu'on 
appelle  excitantes  ou  inefficaces,  en  n'executant  pas  le 
"bien  qu'elles  nous  inspirent,  mais  qu'ils  sont  encore  aussi 
fermes  a  soutenir  centre  Calvin  le  pouvoir  que  la  volonte 
a  de  register  meme  a  la  grace  ejfficace  et  victorieuse 
qu'a  defendre  centre  Molina  le  pouvoir  de  cette  grace 
sur  la  volonte,  aussi  jaloux  de  1'une  de  ces  verites  que 
de  1'autre.  Us  ne  savent  que  trop  que  Thomme,  par 
sa  propre  nature,  a  toujours  le  pouvoir  de  pecker  et  de, 
resister  a  la  grace,  et  que,  depuis  sa  corruption,  il  porte 
un  fonds  malheureux  de  concupiscence  qui  lui  aiigmente 
infiniment  ce  pouvoir  ;  mais  que  neanmoins,  quand  il 
plait  a  Dieu  de  le  toucher  par  sa  misericorde,  il  lui  fait 
faire  ce  qu'il  veut  et  en  la  maniere  qu'il  le  veut,  sans  que 
€ette  infaillibilite  de  1'operation  de  Dieu  detruise  en 
aucune  sorte  la  liberte  naturelle  de  rhomme,  par  les 
secretes  et  admirables  manieres  dont  Dieu  opere  ce 
changement,  que  saint  Augustin  a  si  excellemment  expli- 
quees,  et  qui  dissipent  toutes  les  contradictious  imaginaires 
que  les  ennemis  de  la  grace  efficace  se  figurent  entre  le 
pouvoir  souverain  de  la  grace  sur  le  libre  arbitre,  et  la 
puissance  qu'a  le  libre  arbitre  de  resister^  a  la  grfice  ;  car, 
selon  ce  grand  saint,  que  les  papes  de  1'Eglise  ont  donne 
pour  regie  en  cette  matiere,  Dieu  change  le  coeur  de 
rhomme  par  une  douceur  celeste  qu'il  y  repand,  qui,  sur- 
montant  la  delectation  de  la  chair,  fait  que  rhomme, 
sentant  d'un  cote  sa  mortalite  et  son  neant,  et  decouvrant 
de  1'autre  la  grandeur  et  1'eternite  de  Dieu,  concoit  du 
degout  pour  les  delices  du  peche  qui  le  separent  du  bien 
incorruptible.  Trouvant  sa  plus  grande  joie  dans  le  Dieu 
qui  le  charme,  il  s'y  porte  infailliblement  de  lui-meme  par 
un  mouvement  tout  libre,  tout  volontaire,  tout  amoureiix; 
de  sorte  que  ce  lui  serait  une  peine  et  un  supplice  de  s^en 
separer.  Ce  n'est  pas  qu'il  ne  puisse  toujours^  sen 
eloigner,  et  qu'il  ne  se'n  eloignat  efectiyement  sti  U 
voulait.  Mais  comment  le  voudraiM,  pulque  U 
volonte  ne  se  porte  jamais  qu'a  ce  qui  lui  plait  le  plus, 
et  que  rien  ne  lui  plait  tant  alors  que  ce  bien  unique,  qui 


406  Note  XXL 


comprend  en  soi  tous  les  autres  biens  ?  Quod  enim  am- 
plius  nos  delectat,  secundum  id  operemur  necesse  est, 
comme  dit  saint  Augustin. — Exp.  Ep.  ad  Gal.  n.  49. 

'  Cest  ainsi  que  Dieu  dispose  de  la  volonte  libre  de 
1'homme  sans  lui  imposer  de  necessite,  et  que  le  libre 
arbitre,  qui  pent  toujours  register  a  la  grace,  mais  qui 
ne  le  veut  pas  toujours,  se  porte  aussi  librement  qu'in- 
failliblement  a  Dieu,  lorsqu'il  veut  1'attirer  par  la  douceur 
de  ses  inspirations  efficaces. 

'  Ce  sont  la,  mon  pere,  les  divins  principes  de  saint 
Augustin  et  de  saint  Thomas,  selon  lesquels  il  est  veritable 
que  "  nous  pouvons  resister  a  la  grace,"  centre  Fopinion 
de  Calvin.  .  .  . 

'  C'est  par  la  qu'est  detruite  cette  impiete  de  Luther, 
condamnee  par  le  meme  concile  :  "Que  nous  ne  cooperons 
en  aucune  sorte  a  noire  salut,  non  plus  que  des  choses 
inanimees."  .  .  . 

6  Et  c'est  enfin  par  ce  moyen  que  s'accordent  tous  ces 
passages  de  1'Ecriture,  que  semblent  les  plus  opposes  : 

que,  comme  dit  saint  Augustin,  "  nos 

actions  sont  notres,  a  cause  du  libre  arbitre  qui  les  pro- 
duit ;  et  qu'elles  sont  aussi  de  Dieu,  a  cause  de  sa  grace 
qui  fait  que  notre  arbitre  les  produit."  Et  que,  comme  il 
dit  ailleurs,  Dieu  nous  fait  faire  ce  qu'il  lui  plait,  en  nous 
faisant  vouloir  ce  que  nous  pourrions  ne  vouloir  pas  :  A 
Deo  factum  est  ut  vellent  quod  nolle  potuissent. 

'Ainsi,  mon  pere,  vos  adversaires  sont  parfaitement 
d'accord  avec  les  nouveaux  thomistes  memes,  puisque  les 
thomistes  tiennent  comme  eux,  et  le  pouvoir  de  resister  a 
la  grace,  et  FinfaiJlibilite  de  Teffet  de  la  grace,  qu'ils  font 
profession  de  soutenir  si  hautement,  selon  cette  maxime 
capitale  de  leur  doctrine,  qu' Alvarez,  1'un  des  plus  con 
siderables  d'entre  eux.  repete  si  souvent  dans  son  livre,  et 
qu'il  exprime  (Disp.  72.  1.  viii.  n.  4.)  en  ces  termes : 
"  Quand  la  grace  efficace  meut  le  libre  arbitre,  il  consent 
infailliblement ;  parce  que  I'effet  de  la  grace  est  de  faire 
qu*  encore  qu'il  puisse  ne  pas  consentir,  il  consente  nean- 
moins  en  effet"  Dont  il  donne  pour  raison  celle-ci  de 
saint  Thomas,  son  maitre  (1.  2.  q.  112.  a.  3):  "Que  la 


Note  XXL  407 


volonte  de  Dieu  ne  peut  manquer  d'etre  accomplie  ;  et 
qu'ainsi,  quand  il  veut  qu'un  homme  consente  a  la  grace, 
il  consent  infailliblement,  et  meme  necessaireinent,  non 
pas  d'une  necessite  absolue,  mais  d'une  necessite  d'infail- 
libilite."  En  quoi  la  grace  ne  blesse  pas  "  le  pouvoir  qu'on 
a  de  resister  si  on  le  veut;"  puisqu'elle  fait  seulement 
qu'on  ne  veut  pas  y  resister,  comme  votre  pere  Petau  le 
reconnait  en  ces  termes  (t.  i.  Theol.  Dof/m.  1.  ix.  c.  7.  p. 
602.):  "La  grace  de  Jesus-Christ  fait  qu'on  persevere  in 
failliblement  dans  la  piete,  quoique  non  par  necessite  :  car 
on  peut  n'y  pas  consentir  si  on  le  veut,  comme  dit  le 
concile ;  mais  cette  meme  grace  fait  que  Voti  ne  le  veut 
pas." 

6  C'est  la,  mon  pere,  la  doctrine  constante  de  saint 
Augustin,  de  saint  Prosper,  des  peres  qui  les  ont  suivis, 
des  conciles,  de  saint  Thomas,  et  de  tons  les  thomistes  en 
general.  C'est  aussi  celle  de  vos  adversaires,  quoique  vous 
ne  1'ayez  pas  pense  .... 

'  "  Pour  savoir,  elites-veils,  si  Jansenius  est  a  convert, 
il  faut  savoir  s'il  defend  la  grace  efficace  a  la  maniere  de 
Calvin,  qui  nie  qu'on  ait  le  pouvoir  d'y  resister ;  car  alors 
il  serait  heretique  :  ou  a  la  maniere  des  thomistes,  qui 
Tadmettent ;  car  alors  il  serait  catholique."  Voyez  done, 
mon  pere,  s'il  tient  qu'on  a  le  pouvoir  de  resister,  quand 
il  dit,  dans  des  traites  entiers,  et  entre  autres  au  torn.  iii. 
1.  viii.  c.  20. :  "  Qu'on  a  toujours  le  pouvoir  de  resister 
a  la  grace.,  selon  le  concile :  QUE  LE  LIHRE  ARBITRE 

PEUT  TOUJOURS  AGIR  ET  N^AGIR  PAS,  vouloir  et  1W 
vouloir  pas,  consentir  et  ne  consentir  pas,  faire  le  bien 
et  le  mal ;  et  que  Vhomme  en  cette  vie  a  toujours  ces  deux 
.libertes,  que  vous  appelez  de  contraritte  et  de  contra 
diction."  Voyez  de  meme  s'il  n'est  pas  contraire  a  1'erreur 
de  Calvin,  telle  que  vous-meme  la  representez,  lui  qui  mon- 
tre,  dans  tout  le  chapitre  21 .,  "  que  1'Eglise  a  condamne  cet 
heretique,  qui  soutient  que  la  grace  efficace  n'agit  pas 
.sur  le  libre  arbitre  en  la  maniere  qu'on  1'a  cru  si  long- 
temps  dans  1'Eglise,"  en  sorte  qu'il  soit  ensuite  au  pouvoir 
du  libre  arbitre  de  consentir  ou  de  ne  consentir  pas :  au 
lieu  que,  selon  saint  Augustin  et  le  concile,  on  a  toujours 
le,  pouvoir  de  ne  consentvr  pas,  sionle  veut.' 


408  Note  XXL 


In  this  passage,  then,  we  have  the  ground  on  which 
Pascal  claims  a  great  distinction  to  be  made  between  the 
Jansenist  and  the  Calvinist  doctrine  of  efficacious  grace  ; 
the  ground  being  that  while  the  Calvinists  deny,  the  Jan- 
senists  admit — le  pouvoir  que  la  volonte  a  de  resister 
meme  a  la  grace  efficace  et  victorieuse.  Now  this  admis 
sion  is  in  its  very  form  plainly  and  at  first  sight  unmean 
ing  ;  for  the  only  admission  which  would  carry  freewill 
with  it  would  be  that  man  could  resist  effectively  this 
grace ;  and  certainly  no  effective  resistance  can  by  the 
very  force  of  the  terms  be  made  to  '  victorious  grace/ 
But  the  true  explanation  of  this  whole  argument  is  to  be 
found  in  a  particular  meaning  in  which  the  Augustinian 
school  understood  the  term  power.  Pascal  rests  the  whole 
claim  of  the  Jansenists  to  be  considered  believers  in  free 
will  on  their  use  of  this  word — their  admission  that  man 
has  the  power  to  resist  grace  :  '  Us  ne  savent  que  trop 
quel'homme  a  toujours  le  pouvoir  de  pecher  et  de  resister 
a  la  grace.'  But  the  Augustinian  definition  of  power  en 
tirely  nullifies  this  as  any  admission  really  of.  freewill ;  for 
in  this  definition  power  is  defined  to  be  potestas  si  vult+ 
But,  power  being  thus  understood,  this  admission  leaves 
the  whole  question  of  the  will  and  its  determination  open, 
and  allows  the  person  who  makes  it  to  maintain  that, 
while  every  one  has  the  power  to  resist  grace  if  he  wills, 
no  one  who  is  moved  by  Divine  grace  wills.  Nor  is  this 
meaning  of  the  term  power  at  all  concealed  in  this  letter, 
in  which  Pascal  expressly  time  after  time  thus  qualifies 
the  term  power,  and  appends  to  it  this  condition :  '  Ce 
n'est  pas  qu'il  ne  puisse  toujours  s'en  eloigner,  et  qu'il  ne 
s'en  eloignat  s'il  le  voulait.  Mais  comment  ce  voudrait-il, 
puisque  la  volonte  ne  se  porte  jamais  qu'a  ce  qui  lui  plait, 
etc.  .  .  .  Le  libre  arbitre,  qui  peut  toujours  resister  a  la 
grace,  mais  qui  ne  le  veut  pas.  ...  La  grace  ne  blesse 
pas  le  pouvoir  qu'on  a  de  resister  si  on  le  veut.  .  .  .  Car  on 
peut  n'y  pas  consentir  si  on  le  veut.  ...  On  a  toujours 
le  pouvoir  de  ne  consentir  pas  si  on  le  veut.'  Pascal  tells 
us,  then,  that  by  man's  power  to  resist  grace  is  meant 
power  if  he  wills.  But  would  Calvin  object  to  admit 


Note  XXL  409 


man's  power  to  resist  grace  in  this  sense?  He  could  not, 
for  it  would  leave  him  free  to  hold  his  whole  doctrine  of 
irresistible  grace.  The  doctrine  of  irresistible  grace  i> 
concerned  with  the  will  alone,  and  its  determination  ;  and 
this  admission  says  nothing  about  the  determination  of 
the  will.  Calvin,  then,  would  allow  at  once  that  man  had 
the  power  to  resist  grace  if  he  willed,  but  that  lie  c<m!<l 
not  will  to  resist  effective  grace ;  for  that  this  grace  de 
termined  his  will  and  inclination  itself,  and  caused  it  to 
be  what  it  was.  He  would  simply  say  with  Pascal  himself, 
(  Mais  comment  le  voudrait-il  ? '  with  the  writer  whom 
Pascal  quotes,  '  Encore  qu'il  puisse  ne  pas  consentir,  il  nm- 
sente  neanmoins  en  effet  ;"*  and  with  Augustine,  '  A  ]><',, 
factum  est  ut  vellent  quod  nolle  potuissent.' 

This  sense  of  the  term  power  is  the  key  to  the  state 
ment  quoted  from  Jansen :  '  Qu'on  a  toujours  le  pouvoir 
de  resister  a  la  grace,  selon  le  concile;  que  le  libre'arbitre 
peut  toujours  agir  et  n'agir  pas,  vouloir  et  ne  vouloir  pas. 
consentir   et  ne  consentir  pas,  fa  ire  le  bien  et   le  mal,  <-t 
que  1'homme  en  cette  vie  a  toujours  ces  deux  libertes,  qiir 
vous    appelez    de    contrariete  et  de  contradiction.'     The 
power  spoken  of  is  potestas  si  vult ;  on  which  understand 
ing  the  admission  comes  to  nothing;    Jansen    expressly 
saying  that  practically  the  individual  cannot  act  but  in 
the   way  in  which   grace  moves:  '  Xon  quod  cessatio  ab 
actu  quern  tune  (gratia)  elicit,  cum  graticv  delectanti* 
influxu  consistere  possit  .  .  .  quamvis  fieri  nequeat  ut 
ipsanonactio  cum  gratia  operations  in  eadem  simul 
voluntate    copuletur.'—De  Grat.    Christi,   p.    870. 
short,  all  that  the  Augustinian  and  Jansenist  admission 
with  respect  to  freewill  amounts  to,  is  the  admission  o 
will  in  man ;  and  this  admission  Calvin  is  equally  ready 
to  make.     The   position   condemned   by  the   Council 
Trent,  as  that  of  the  Keformers,  that  man  was  moved 
Divine  grace  like  an  inanimate  thing,  was  not  their  por 
tion  ;   they  fully  acknowledged  a  will   in    man,  that 
acted    willingly  and  without  constraint ;    they   ack: 
ledged  all  the  facts  of  our  consciousness ;  and,  admitt 
them,  they  admitted  all  that  S.  Augustine  and  his 

admitted. 

E  E 


687018 


LONDON  :    PRINTED     BV 

SPOTTISWOODE    AND    CO.,    NEW-STHKET     .SQUARE 
AND     PARLIAMENT     STHEKT 


BT  MOZLEY 

&10     A  TREATISE  ON  THE 

jjgL  AUGUSTINIAN  DOCTRINE 

188.5  OF  PREDESTINATION 

DATE  11/280: 


i  '